Erkenntnis

, Volume 78, Issue 6, pp 1367–1379 | Cite as

Soames’s Deflationism About Modality

Original Article

Abstract

One type of deflationism about metaphysical modality suggests that it can be analysed strictly in terms of linguistic or conceptual content and that there is nothing particularly metaphysical about modality. Scott Soames is explicitly opposed to this trend. However, a detailed study of Soames’s own account of modality reveals that it has striking similarities with the deflationary account. In this paper I will compare Soames’s account of a posteriori necessities concerning natural kinds with the deflationary one, specifically Alan Sidelle’s account, and suggest that Soames’s account is vulnerable to the deflationist’s critique. Furthermore, I conjecture that both the deflationary account and Soames’s account fail to fully explicate the metaphysical content of a posteriori necessities. Although I will focus on Soames, my argument may have more general implications towards the prospects of providing a meaning-based account of metaphysical modality.

References

  1. Ballarin, R. (2011). The necessity of origin: A long and winding route. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9354-3.
  2. Barnes, G. P. (2000). Modal inquiry: An epistemological study. Doctoral dissertation. Retrieved from ProQuest Dissertations and Theses (Accession Order No. AAT 9972796).Google Scholar
  3. Chalmers, D. (2006a). Foundations of two-dimensional semantics. In M. Garcia-Carpintero & J. Macia (Eds.), Two-dimensional semantics: Foundations and applications (pp. 55–140). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Chalmers, D. (2006b). Scott Soames’ two-dimensionalism. For a session at the meeting of the American Philosophical Association, Central Division, in April 2006. http://consc.net/papers/soames2d.pdf.
  5. Dumsday, T. (2012). Using natural-kind essentialism to defend dispositionalism. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-012-9361-z.
  6. Fine, K. (1994). Essence and modality. In J. E. Tomberlin (Ed.), Philosophical perspectives (Vol. 8, pp. 1–16). Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview.Google Scholar
  7. Jackson, F. (1998). From metaphysics to ethics: A defence of conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Lowe, E. J. (2007a). Does the descriptivist/anti-descriptivist debate have any philosophical significance? Philosophical Books, 48, 27–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Lowe, E. J. (2007b). A problem for a posteriori essentialism concerning natural kinds. Analysis, 67(4), 286–292.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Lowe, E. J. (2011). Locke on real essence and water as a natural kind: A qualified defence. Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 85(1), 1–19.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Needham, P. (2011). Microessentialism: What is the argument? Noûs, 45(1), 1–21.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Oderberg, D. (2011). Essence and properties. Erkenntnis, 75, 85–111.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Putnam, H. (1990). Is water necessarily H2O? In J. Conant (Ed.), Realism with a human face (pp. 54–79). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  14. Salmon, N. U. (2005). Reference and essence, (2nd ed., 1st ed. published 1982) New York: Prometheus Books, Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  15. Sidelle, A. (1989). Necessity, essence and individuation. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Sidelle, A. (2002). On the metaphysical contingency of laws of nature. In T. S. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Conceivability and possibility (pp. 309–336). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Soames, S. (2002). Beyond rigidity: The unfinished semantic agenda of naming and necessity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Soames, S. (2005). Reference and description: The case against two-dimensionalism. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Soames, S. (2006a). The philosophical significance of the Kripkean necessary aposteriori. Philosophical Issues 16: Philosophy of Language, 288–309.Google Scholar
  20. Soames, S. (2006b). Reply to critics of Reference and description. For a session at the meeting of the American Philosophical Association, Central Division, in April 2006. http://www-bcf.usc.edu/~soames/replies/Rep_Chicago.pdf.
  21. Soames, S. (2007a). The substance and significance of the dispute over two-dimensionalism. Philosophical Books, 48, 34–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Soames, S. (2007b). What are natural kinds? Philosophical Topics, 35 (1-2), 329–342. Page numbers refer to the version available on Soames’s website, http://www-bcf.usc.edu/~soames/forthcoming_papers/Natural_Kinds.pdf.
  23. Soames, S. (2010). True at. Analysis, 71(1), 124–133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Soames, S. (2011). Kripke on epistemic and metaphysical possibility: Two routes to the necessary aposteriori. In A. Berger (Ed.), Saul kripke (pp. 78–99). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. Syntax and Semantics, 9, 315–32. Reprinted in Context and content: Essays on intentionality in speech and thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.Google Scholar
  26. Tahko, T. E. (2009). On the modal content of a posteriori necessities. Theoria: A Swedish Journal of Philosophy, 75, 344–357.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Tahko, T. E. (2012). Natural kind essentialism revisited. Available from www.ttahko.net/nke.pdf.
  28. van Brakel, J. (1986). The chemistry of substances and the philosophy of mass terms. Synthese, 69, 291–324.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, History, Culture and Art StudiesUniversity of HelsinkiHelsinkiFinland

Personalised recommendations