Erkenntnis

, Volume 77, Issue 1, pp 15–30 | Cite as

Arntzenius on ‘Why ain’cha rich?’

Original Article

Abstract

The best-known argument for Evidential Decision Theory (EDT) is the ‘Why ain’cha rich?’ challenge to rival Causal Decision Theory (CDT). The basis for this challenge is that in Newcomb-like situations, acts that conform to EDT may be known in advance to have the better return than acts that conform to CDT. Frank Arntzenius has recently proposed an ingenious counter argument, based on an example in which, he claims, it is predictable in advance that acts that conform to EDT will do less well than acts that conform to CDT. We raise two objections to Arntzenius’s example. We argue, first, that the example is subtly incoherent, in a way that undermines its effectiveness against EDT; and, second, that the example relies on calculating the average return over an inappropriate population of acts.

References

  1. Arntzenius, F. (2008). No regrets, or: Edith Piaf revamps decision theory. Erkenntnis, 68, 277–297.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Dummett, M. (1964). Bringing about the past. Philosophical Review, 73, 338–359.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Eells, E. (1982). Rational decision and causality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Gibbard, A., & Harper, W. (1981). Counterfactuals and two kinds of expected utility. In W. Harper, R. Stalnaker, & G. Pearce (Eds.), Ifs: Conditionals, belief, decision, chance and time (pp. 153–192). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  5. Hitchcock, C. (1996). Causal decision theory and decision-theoretic causation. Noûs, 30, 508–526.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Joyce, J. (1999). The foundations of causal decision theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Joyce, J. (2007). Are Newcomb problems really decisions? Synthese, 156, 537–562.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Lewis, D. (1981a). Causal decision theory. In P. Gardenfors & N.-E. Sahlin (Eds.), Decision, probability and utility: Selected readings (pp. 377–405). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Lewis, D. (1981b). Why ain’cha rich? Noûs, 15, 377–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Nozick, R. (1970). Newcomb’s problem and two principles of choice. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Essays in honor of Carl G. Hempel (pp. 114–146). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.Google Scholar
  11. Pearl, J. (2000). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Price, H. (1993). The direction of causation: Ramsey’s ultimate contingency. In D. Hull, M. Forbes, & K. Okruhlik (Eds.), PSA 1992 (Vol. 2, pp. 253–267). East Lansing, Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association.Google Scholar
  13. Rabinowicz, W. (2002). Does practical deliberation crowd out self-prediction? Erkenntnis, 57, 91–122.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Faculty of PhilosophyUniversity of CambridgeCambridgeUK
  2. 2.Centre for Time, SOPHI, Faculty of ArtsUniversity of SydneySydneyAustralia

Personalised recommendations