Erkenntnis

, Volume 78, Issue 2, pp 451–468 | Cite as

Regulative Assumptions, Hinge Propositions and the Peircean Conception of Truth

Original Article

Abstract

This paper defends a key aspect of the Peircean conception of truth—the idea that truth is in some sense epistemically-constrained. It does so by exploring parallels between Peirce’s epistemology of inquiry and that of Wittgenstein in On Certainty. The central argument defends a Peircean claim about truth by appeal to a view shared by Peirce and Wittgenstein about the structure of reasons. This view relies on the idea that certain claims have a special epistemic status, or function as what are popularly called ‘hinge propositions’.

References

  1. Bennett, J. (1974). Kant’s dialectic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Bernstein, R. (2010). The pragmatic turn. Malden, MA: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  3. Hookway, C. J. (1985). Peirce. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
  4. Hookway, C.J. (1998). Peirce, Charles Sanders. In E. Craig (Ed.), Routledge encyclopedia of philosophy (Vol. 7, pp. 269–282). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  5. Hookway, C. (2002). Truth, rationality and pragmatism: Themes from Peirce. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Hookway, C. (2007). Fallibilism and the Aim of Inquiry (Inaugural Address). In Proceedings of the Aristotelian society, Supplementary volume LXXXI, pp. 1–22.Google Scholar
  7. Johanson, A. E. (1994). Peirce and Wittgenstein’s on certainty. In G. Debrock & M. Hulswit (Eds.), Living doubt: Essays concerning the epistemology of C. S. Peirce (pp. 171–186). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  8. Lewis, D. (1969). Convention. London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Misak, C. (2004). Truth and the end of inquiry: A Peircean account of truth. Oxford: Clarendon.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Misak, C. (forthcoming). Pragmatism & indispensability arguments, 2011 Presidential Address to the Charles S. Peirce Society, Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society.Google Scholar
  11. Nesher, D. (2001). Peircean epistemology of learning and the function of abduction as the logic of discovery. Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society, 37(1), 23–57.Google Scholar
  12. Peirce, C. S. (1992). The essential Peirce, vol 1 (EP vol./page no.)). Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Pettit, P. (1998). Practical belief and philosophical theory. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 76(1), 15–33.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Pritchard, D. (2011). Wittgenstein on scepticism. In M. McGinn (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of Wittgenstein. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  15. Putnam, H. (1995). Words and life. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Russell, B. (1946). History of western philosophy. London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  17. Smart, J. J. C. (1986). Realism v. Idealism. Philosophy, 61, 295–312.Google Scholar
  18. Wittgenstein, L. (1969). On certainty (OC). In G. E. M. Anscombe & G. H. von Wright (Eds.), On certainty (P. Denis & G. E. M. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  19. Wright, C. (1992). Truth and objectivity. London: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyCalifornia State University, FullertonFullertonUSA

Personalised recommendations