Erkenntnis

, Volume 75, Issue 3, pp 303–324

Historical Epistemology or History of Epistemology? The Case of the Relation Between Perception and Judgment

Dedicated to Günther Patzig on his 85th birthday
Original Article

Abstract

This essay aims to sharpen debates on the pros and cons of historical epistemology, which is now understood as a novel approach to the study of knowledge, by comparing it with the history of epistemology as traditionally pursued by philosophers. The many versions of both approaches are not always easily discernable. Yet, a reasoned comparison of certain versions can and should be made. In the first section of this article, I argue that the most interesting difference involves neither the subject matter nor goal, but the methods used by the two approaches. In the second section, I ask which of the two approaches or methods is more promising given that both historical epistemologists and historians of epistemology claim to contribute to epistemology simpliciter. Using traditional problems concerning the epistemic role of perception, I argue that the historical epistemologies of Wartofsky and Daston and Galison fail to show that studying practices of perception is philosophically significant. Standard methods from the history of epistemology are more promising, as I show by means of reconstructing arguments in a debate about the relation between perception and judgment in psychological research on the famous moon illusion.

References

  1. Anonymous. (1975). Boston colloquium for the philosophy of science: Fifteenth annual programme, 1974–1975. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 26, 88–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Bennett, J. (1966). Kant’s analytic. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Boring, E. G. (1943). The moon illusion. American Journal of Physics, 11, 55–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Boring, E. G. (1962). On the moon illusion (letter). Science, 137, 902–906.Google Scholar
  5. Burnyeat, M. (1979). Conflicting appearances. Proceedings of the British Academy, 65, 69–111.Google Scholar
  6. Burnyeat, M. (1990). The Theaetetus of Plato. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  7. Carl, W. (1989). Der schweigende Kant. Göttingen: Vandenhoek & Ruprecht.Google Scholar
  8. Carl, W. (1994). Frege’s theory of sense and reference: Its origins and scope. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Daston, L. (1994). Historical epistemology. In J. Chandler, A. I. Davidson, & H. Harootunian (Eds.), Questions of evidence (pp. 282–289). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  10. Daston, L., & Galison, P. (2007). Objectivity. New York: Zone books.Google Scholar
  11. Daston, L., & Lunbeck, E. (Eds.). (2011). Histories of scientific observation. Chicago: Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Dees, J. W. (1966). Moon illusion and size-distance invariance: An explanation based upon an experimental artifact. Perceptual and Motor Skills, 23, 629–630.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Dolling, L. (2003). Dialogue as praxis: Philosophical hermeneutics, historical epistemology, and truth. In C. C. Gould (Ed.), Constructivism and practice (pp. 33–46). Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  14. Egan, F. (1998). The moon illusion. Philosophy of Science, 65, 604–623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Emmert, E. (1881). Grössenverhältnisse der Nachbilder. Klinische Monatsblätter für Augenheilkunde, 19, 443–450.Google Scholar
  16. Feest, U., & Sturm, T. (2011). What (good) is historical epistemology? Editors’ introduction. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9345-4
  17. Fodor, J. (1984). Observation reconsidered. Philosophy of Science, 51, 23–43.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Friedman, M. (1992). Kant and the exact sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Galison, P. (2008). Ten problems in history and philosophy of science. Isis, 99, 111–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Garber, D. (2005). What’s philosophical about the history of philosophy? In T. Sorell & G. Rogers (Eds.), Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy (pp. 129–146). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  21. Goldman, A. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  22. Gould, C. C. (Ed.). (2003). Constructivism and practice: Toward a historical epistemology. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  23. Hacking, I. (1999). Historical meta-epistemology. In W. Carl & L. Daston (Eds.), Wahrheit und Geschichte (pp. 53–77). Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht.Google Scholar
  24. Hacking, I. (2002). Historical ontology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  25. Hatfield, G. (1990). The natural and the normative. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  26. Hatfield, G. (1996). The importance of the history of science for philosophy in general. Synthese, 106, 113–138.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Hatfield, G. (2002). Perception as unconscious inference. In D. Heyer & R. Mausfeld (Eds.), Perception and the physical world (pp. 116–143). Chichester, NY: Wiley.Google Scholar
  28. Hatfield, G. (2005). The history of philosophy as philosophy. In T. Sorell & G. Rogers (Eds.), Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy (pp. 83–128). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Hershenson, M. (Ed.). (1989). The moon illusion. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  30. Holway, A. F., & Boring, E. G. (1940a). The moon illusion and the angle of regard. American Journal of Psychology, 53, 109–116.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Holway, A. F., & Boring, E. G. (1940b). The apparent size of the moon as a function of the angle of regard. American Journal of Psychology, 53, 537–553.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Kaufman, L., & Kaufman, J. H. (2000). Explaining the moon illusion. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, 97, 500–505.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Kaufman, L., Kaufman, J. H., Noble, R., Edlund, S., Bai, S. & King, T. (2007). Perceptual distance and the constancy of size and stereoscopic depth. Spatial Vision, 19, 439–457.Google Scholar
  34. Kaufman, L., & Rock, I. (1962a). The moon illusion, I. Science, 136, 953–961.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Kaufman, L., & Rock, I. (1962b). The moon illusion. Scientific American, 207, 120–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Kaufman, L., & Rock, I. (1989). The moon illusion thirty years later. In M. Hershenson (Ed.), The moon illusion (pp. 193–234). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  37. Kemmerling, A. (1996). Ideen des Ich: Studien zu Descartes’ Philosophie. Frankfurt a.M.: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  38. Kenny, A. (2005). The philosopher’s history and the history of philosophy. In T. Sorell & G. Rogers (Eds.), Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy (pp. 13–24). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  39. Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  40. Krüger, L. (Ed.). (2005). Why do we study the history of philosophy? In Why does history matter to philosophy and the sciences? (pp. 231–254). Berlin: De Gruyter. Ed. by T. Sturm, W. Carl & L. Daston.Google Scholar
  41. Kusch, M. (2011). Reflexivity, relativism, microhistory: Three desiderata for historical epistemologies. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9336-5
  42. Lecourt, D. (1969). L’Epistémologie historique de Gaston Bachelard. Paris: Vrin.Google Scholar
  43. Mash, R. (1987). How important for philosophers is the history of philosophy? History and Theory, 26, 278–299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. McDowell, J. (1994). Mind and world. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  45. Müller-Wille, S., & Rheinberger, H.-J. (Eds.). (2007). Heredity produced: At the crossroads of biology, politics, and culture 1500–1870. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  46. Müller-Wille, S., & Rheinberger, H.-J. (2009). Vererbung: Geschichte und Kultur eines biologischen Konzepts. Frankfurt a.M.: Fischer.Google Scholar
  47. Nozick, R. (1993). The nature of rationality. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  48. Plug, C., & Ross, H. E. (1989). Historical review. In M. Hershenson (Ed.), The moon illusion (pp. 5–30). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  49. Plug, C., & Ross, H. E. (1994). The natural moon illusion: A multifactor angular account. Perception, 23, 321–333.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Renn, J. (1995). Historical epistemology and interdisciplinarity. In Kostas. Gavroglu, et al. (Eds.), Physics, philosophy and the scientific community (pp. 241–251). Dordrecht: Kluwer.Google Scholar
  51. Renn, J. (1996). Historical epistemology and the advancement of science. Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte, Preprint 36. Berlin: Max-Planck-Institut für Wissenschaftsgeschichte. (http://www.mpiwg-berlin.mpg.de/Preprints/P36.PDF).
  52. Renn, J. (2004). The relativity revolution from the perspective of historical epistemology. Isis, 95, 640–648.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  53. Renn, J. (2008). The historical epistemology of mechanics. Foreword to Matthias Schemmel, The English Galileo. Thomas Harriot’s work on motion as an example of preclassical mechanics (pp. vii–x). Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  54. Renn, J., Damerow, P., & McLaughlin, P. (2004). Aristotle, Archimedes, and the origins of mechanics: The perspective of historical epistemology. In J. L. Montesinos Sirera (Ed.), Symposium Arquímedes (pp. 43–59). Fundación Canaria Orotava de Historia de la Cienci.Google Scholar
  55. Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  56. Rheinberger, H.-J. (2010). On historicizing epistemology (D. Fernbach, Trans.). Stanford: Stanford University Press.Google Scholar
  57. Rock, I., & Kaufman, L. (1962a). The moon illusion, II. Science, 136, 1023–1031.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Rock, I., & Kaufman, L. (1962b). On the moon illusion (reply to letters by Wallach and Boring). Science, 137, 906–911.Google Scholar
  59. Ross, H. E., & Plug, C. (2002). The mystery of the moon illusion. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  60. Schaffer, S. (1994). Making up discovery. In M. Boden (Ed.), Dimensions of creativity (pp. 13–51). Cambridge/MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  61. Schickore, J. (2006). Misperception, illusion, and epistemological optimism: Vision studies in early nineteenth-century Britain and Germany. British Journal for the History of Science, 39, 383–405.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Schumacher, R. (2004a). Die kognitive Undurchdringbarkeit optischer Täuschungen. Zeitschrift für Philosophische Forschung, 58, 505–526.Google Scholar
  63. Schumacher, R. (Ed.). (2004b). Perception and reality. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  64. Sorell, T., & Rogers, G. (Eds.). (2005). Analytic philosophy and history of philosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  65. Stroud, B. (2011). Epistemology, the history of epistemology, historical epistemology. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9337-4
  66. Sturm, T. (2006). Wie können wir von Kant lernen? Das Achtzehnte Jahrhundert, 30, 89–95.Google Scholar
  67. Sturm, T. (2009). Kant und die Wissenschaften vom Menschen. Paderborn: Mentis.Google Scholar
  68. Sturm, T., & Wunderlich, F. (2010). Kant and the scientific study of consciousness. History of the Human Sciences, 23, 48–71.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Taylor, D. W., & Boring, E. G. (1942). The moon illusion as a function of binocular regard. American Journal of Psychology, 55, 189–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  70. Turner, R. S. (1994). In the eye’s mind: Vision and the Helmholtz-Hering controversy. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  71. Wade, N. J. (2005). Perception and illusion. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  72. Wartofsky, M. (1976). The mind’s eye and the hand’s brain: Toward an historical epistemology of medicine. In H. T. Engelhardt Jr. & D. Callaghan (Eds.), Science, ethics, and medicine (pp. 167–194). New York: University Publications of America.Google Scholar
  73. Wartofsky, M. (1979). Models: Representation and the scientific understanding. Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  74. Wartofsky, M. (1983a). From genetic epistemology to historical epistemology: Kant, Marx, and Piaget. In L. S. Liben (Ed.), Piaget and the foundations of knowledge (pp. 1–18). Hillsdale/NJ: Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  75. Wartofsky, M. (1983b). The child’s construction of the world and the world’s construction of the child: From historical epistemology to historical psychology. In F. S. Kessel & A. S. Siegel (Eds.), The child and other cultural inventions (pp. 1–18). New York: Praeger.Google Scholar
  76. Wartofsky, M. (1987). Epistemology historicized. In A. Shimony & D. Nails (Eds.), Naturalistic epistemology (pp. 357–374). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Williams, B. (1978). Descartes: The project of pure enquiry. Harmondsworth: Penguin.Google Scholar
  78. Wilson, C. (1995). The invisible world: Early modern philosophy and the invention of the microscope. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Departament de FilosofiaUniversitat Autònoma de BarcelonaBellaterra (Barcelona)Spain

Personalised recommendations