Advertisement

Erkenntnis

, Volume 70, Issue 3, pp 285–297 | Cite as

Dear Haecceitism

  • Delia Graff FaraEmail author
Original Article

Abstract

If a counterpart theorist’s understanding of the counterpart relation precludes haecceitist differences between possible worlds, as David Lewis’s does, how can he admit haecceitist possibilities, as Lewis wants to? Lewis (Philosophical Review 3–32, 1983; On the Plurality of Worlds, 1986) devised what he called a ‘cheap substitute for haecceitism,’ which would allow for haecceitist possibilities while preserving the counterpart relation as a purely qualitative one. The solution involved lifting an earlier (Journal of Philosophy 65(5):113–126, 1968; 68(7):203–211, 1971) ban on there being multiple intra-world counterparts. I argue here that serious problems for ‘cheap haecceitism’ lurk very close to its surface, and they emerge when we consider the effect of using an actuality operator in our language. Among the most serious of the problems is the result that being the case in some possible world does not always suffice for possibly being the case. The result applies to any counterpart theory that employs a purely qualitative counterpart relation. The upshot is that if we are to admit haecceitist possibilities, as we should, then we must reject any purely qualitative relation as the one involved in the analysis of what might have been for an individual.

Keywords

Actuality Operator Actual World Qualitative Description Counterpart Relation Counterpart Theory 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Fara, D. G. (2008). Relative-sameness counterpart theory. Review of Symbolic Logic, 1, 167–189.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Fara, M., & Williamson, T. (2005). Counterparts and actuality. Mind, 114, 1–30.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Gibbard, A. (1975). Contingent identity. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 4, 187–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Hazen, A. (1979). Counterpart-theoretic semantics for modal logic. Journal of Philosophy, 76(6), 319–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Kaplan, D. (1989). Demonstratives. In J. Almog, J. Perry, & H. Wettstein (Eds.), Themes from Kaplan (pp. 481–563). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  6. Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. In D. Davidson & G. Harman (Eds.), Semantics of natural language (pp. 253–355). Dordrecht: Reidel. (Reprinted as Naming and necessity, by Kripke, 1980, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).Google Scholar
  7. Lewis, D. (1968). Counterpart theory and quantified modal logic. Journal of Philosophy, 65(5), 113–126.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Lewis, D. (1970). Anselm and actuality. NOÛS, 4, 175–188.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Lewis, D. (1971). Counterparts of persons and their bodies. Journal of Philosophy, 68(7), 203–211.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Lewis, D. (1983). Individuation by acquaintance and by stipulation. Philosophical Review, 3–32.Google Scholar
  11. Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  12. Skow, B. (2008). Haecceitism, anti-haecceitism, and possible worlds. The Philosophical Quarterly, 58, 97–107.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2009

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Philosophy DepartmentPrinceton UniversityPrincetonUSA

Personalised recommendations