Erkenntnis

, Volume 70, Issue 2, pp 189–209 | Cite as

Iterated Belief Revision

Original article

Abstract

This is a discussion of the problem of extending the basic AGM belief revision theory to iterated belief revision: the problem of formulating rules, not only for revising a basic belief state in response to potential new information, but also for revising one’s revision rules in response to potential new information. The emphasis in the paper is on foundational questions about the nature of and motivation for various constraints, and about the methodology of the evaluation of putative counterexamples to proposed constraints. Some specific constraints that have been proposed are criticized. The paper emphasizes the importance of meta-information—information about one’s sources of information—and argues that little of substance can be said about constraints on iterated belief revision at a level of abstraction that lacks the resources for explicit representation of meta-information.

References

  1. Boutilier, C. (1996). Iterated revision and minimal change of conditional beliefs. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 25, 262–305.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Darwiche, A., & Pearl, J. (1997). On the logic of iterated belief revision. Artificial Intelligence, 89, 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Friedman, N., & Halpern, J. (1999). Belief revision: A critique. Journal of Logic, Language, and Information, 8, 401–420.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Gärdenfors, P., & Rott, H. (1995). Belief revision. In D. Gabbay, et al. (Eds.), Handbook of logic in artificial intelligence and logic programming IV: Epistemic and temporal reasoning (pp. 35–132). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Ginsberg, M. (1986). Counterfactuals. Artificial Intelligence, 30, 35–80.Google Scholar
  6. Grove, A. (1988). Two modellings for theory change. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 17, 157–170.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hild, M. (1998). Auto-epistemology and updating. Philosophical Studies, 92, 321–361.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Lehmann, D. (1995). Belief revision, revised. In Proceedings of the Fourteenth International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence (pp. 1534–1540).Google Scholar
  9. Rott, H. (1999). Coherence and conservativism in the dynamics of belief. Erkenntnis, 50, 387–412.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Rott, H. (2001). Change, choice and inference. Oxford Logic Guides (Vol. 42). Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  11. Rott, H. (2004). A counterexample to six fundamental principles of belief formation. Synthese, 139b, 225–240.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Spohn, W. (1988). Ordinal conditional functions: A dynamic theory of epistemic states. In W. Harper & B. Skyrms (Eds.), Causation in decision, belief change and statistics (Vol. 2, pp. 105–134). Dordrecht: Reidel.Google Scholar
  13. Stalnaker, R. (1994). What is a nonmonotonic consequence relation? Fundamenta Informaticae, 21(1/2), 7–12.Google Scholar
  14. Stalnaker, R. (2006). On logics of knowledge and belief. Philosophical Studies, 120, 169–199.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Williamson, T. (2001). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.CambridgeUSA

Personalised recommendations