Advertisement

Journal of Business Ethics

, Volume 125, Issue 2, pp 235–251 | Cite as

Conceptualising Meaningful Work as a Fundamental Human Need

  • Ruth Yeoman
Article

Abstract

In liberal political theory, meaningful work is conceptualised as a preference in the market. Although this strategy avoids transgressing liberal neutrality, the subsequent constraint upon state intervention aimed at promoting the social and economic conditions for widespread meaningful work is normatively unsatisfactory. Instead, meaningful work can be understood to be a fundamental human need, which all persons require in order to satisfy their inescapable interests in freedom, autonomy, and dignity. To overcome the inadequate treatment of meaningful work by liberal political theory, I situate the good of meaningful work within a liberal perfectionist framework, from which standpoint I develop a normative justification for making meaningful work the object of political action. To understand the content of meaningful work, I make use of Susan Wolf’s distinct value of meaningfulness, in which she brings together the dimensions of objectivity and subjectivity into the ‘bipartite value’ of meaningfulness (BVM) (Wolf, Meaning in life and why it matters, 2010). However, in order to be able to incorporate the BVM into our lives, we must become valuers, that is, co-creators of values and meanings. This demands that we acquire the relevant capabilities and status as co-authorities in the realm of value. I conclude that meaningful work is of first importance because it is a fundamental human need, and that society ought to be arranged to allow as many people as possible to experience their work as meaningful through the development of the relevant capabilities.

Keywords

Capabilities Human need Liberal neutrality Liberal perfectionism Meaningful work Meaning in life 

References

  1. Alfes, K., Truss, C., Soane, E. C., Rees, C., & Gatenby, M. (2010). Creating an engaged workforce: Findings from the Kingston Employee Engagement Consortium Project. CIPD Report. Accessed 13 December 2011, from http://www.cipd.co.uk/NR/rdonlyres/DD66E557-DB90-4F07-8198-87C3876F3371/0/Creating_engaged_workforce.pdf.
  2. Arendt, H. (1977 [1954]). What is freedom? In Between past and future. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  3. Arneson, R. J. (1987). Meaningful work and market socialism. Ethics, 97(3), 517–545.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Arneson, R. J. (2000). Perfectionism and politics. Ethics, 111(1), 36–63.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Arnold, K. A., Turner, N., Barling, J., Kelloway, E. K., & McKee, M. C. (2007). Transformational leadership and psychological well-being: The mediating role of meaningful work. Journal of Occupational Health Psychology, 12, 193–203.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Baier, K. (2000 [1957]). The meaning of life. In E. D. Klemke (Ed.), The meaning of life. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Baumeister, R. F. (1991). Meanings of life. New York: Guilford.Google Scholar
  8. Bechky, B. (2003). Sharing meaning across occupational communities: The transformation of understanding on a production floor. Organization Science, 14(3), 312–330.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Blustein, D. L. (2006). The psychology of working: A new perspective for career development, counselling and public policy. Mahweh, NJ: Erlbaum. Google Scholar
  10. Blustein, D. L. (2008). The role of work in psychological health and well-being. American Psychologist, 63(4), 228–240.Google Scholar
  11. Bosma, H., Marmot, M. G., Hemingway, H., Nicholson, A. C., Brunner, E., & Stansfeld, S. (1997). Low job control and risk of coronary heart disease in Whitehall II (prospective cohort) study. British Medical Journal, 314, 558–565.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Breen, K. (2011, June 3). Work and practical reasoning: On two rival visions of the workplace. Paper presented to the Contemporary Aristotelian Studies (CAS) specialist group of the Political Studies Association (PSA), 1st annual conference.Google Scholar
  13. Broom, D. H., D’Souza, R. M., Strazdius, P., Butterworth, P., Plaslow, B., & Rodgers, B. (2006). The lesser evil: Bad jobs or unemployment? A survey of mid-aged Australians. Social Sciences & Medicine, 63(3), 575–586.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Burawoy, M. (1979). Manufacturing consent: Changes in the labor process under monopoly capitalism. London: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  15. Campbell, J. (1989). Joy in work, German work: The national debate, 1800–1945. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Carter, N. (2003, March 28–April 2). Workplace democracy: Turning workers into citizens? Paper presented at ECPR joint sessions, Edinburgh.Google Scholar
  17. Council of Civil Service Unions/Cabinet Office. (2004). Work, stress and health: The Whitehall II study. London: Public and Commercial Services Union.Google Scholar
  18. Christiano, T. (2005). An argument for Egalitarian justice and against the levelling-down objection. In J. K. Campbell, M. O’Rourke, & D. Shier (Eds.), Law & social justice. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  19. Christman, J. (2002). Social and political philosophy. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Ciulla, J. B. (2000). The working life: The promise and betrayal of modern work. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
  21. Doherty, M. (2009). When the working day is through: The end of work as identity? Work, Employment & Society, 23(1), 84–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Drucker, P. (2010). Men, ideas and politics. Boston: Harvard Business Review Press.Google Scholar
  23. Dzur, A. W. (1998). Liberal perfectionism and democratic participation. Polity, 30(4), 667–690.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Elster, J. (1983). Sour grapes: Studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Elster, J. (1986). Self-realisation in work & politics: The Marxist conception of the good life. Philosophy & Social Policy, 3(2), 99–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Fourier, C. (1983). In J. Beecher & R. Bienvenu (Eds.), The utopian vision of Charles Fourier: Selected texts on work, love, and passionate attraction. Columbia: University of Missouri Press.Google Scholar
  27. Frankl, V. E. (1978). The unheard cry for meaning: Psychotherapy and humanism. New York: Simon & Schuster.Google Scholar
  28. Frankl, V. E. (1984). Man’s search for meaning. New York: Washington Square Press.Google Scholar
  29. Frankl, V. E. (1988). The will to meaning. New York: New American Library.Google Scholar
  30. Frankl, V. E. (2004). Logos, paradox, and the search for meaning. In A. Freeman, M. J. Mahoney, & P. DeVito (Eds.), Cognition and psychotherapy. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  31. Gilligan, C. (1982). In a different voice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Gomberg, P. (2007). How to make opportunity equal: Race and contributive justice. Malden, MA: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Hare, R. M. (1972). Essays on the moral concepts. Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.Google Scholar
  34. Hauser, R. M., & Roan, C. L. (2007). Work complexity and cognitive functioning at midlife: Cross-validating the Kohn–Schooler hypothesis in the American cohort. CDE Working Paper No. 2007-08, Center for Demography and Ecology, University of Wisconsin-Madison.Google Scholar
  35. Hicks, J. A., & King, L. A. (2009). Meaning in life as a subjective judgement and lived experience, social and personality psychology. Compass, 3(4), 638–653.Google Scholar
  36. Holbrook, D. (1977). Politics and the need for meaning. In R. Fitzgerald (Ed.), Human needs and politics. Oxford: Pergamon Press.Google Scholar
  37. Honig, B. (1993). Political theory and the displacement of politics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  38. Honneth, A. (1995). The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts. Cambridge: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  39. Hsieh, N. (2008). Survey article: Justice in production. The Journal of Political Philosophy, 16(1), 72–100.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Hurka, T. (1993). Perfectionism. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Joske, W. D. (1974). Philosophy and the meaning of life. In E. D. Klemke (Ed.), The meaning of life. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  42. Kauppinen, A. (2008). Why the shape of a life matters. Accessed 30 July 2011, from http://www.philosophy.northwestern.edu/conferences/moralpolitical/08/papers/Kauppinen.pdf.
  43. Keat, R. (2006). Liberalism, neutrality, and varieties of capitalism. Accessed 17 January 2011, from http://www.russellkeat.net/research/ethicsmarkets/keat_liberalism_neutrality_vocs.pdf.
  44. Keat, R. (2009a). Choosing between capitalisms: Habermas, ethics and politics. Res Publica, 15, 355–376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Keat, R. (2009b). Anti-perfectionism, market economics and meaningful work. Accessed 17 January, 2011, from http://www.russellkeat.net/research/ethicsmarkets/keat_antiperfectionism.pdf.
  46. Kekes, J. (1986). The informed will and the meaning of life. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 47(1), 75–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Kohn, M. L., & Schooler, C. (1983). Work and personality: An inquiry into the impact of social stratification. Norwood: Ablex Publishing.Google Scholar
  48. Kohn, M. L., & Slomczynski, K. M. (1990). Social structure and self-direction: A comparative analysis of the United States and Poland. Oxford, UK: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  49. Kornhauser, A. (1965). Mental health of the industrial worker: A Detroit study. Oxford: Wiley.Google Scholar
  50. Korsegaard, C. M. (2009). Self-constitution: Agency, identity and integrity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Kovacs, G. (1986). Phenomenology of work and self-transcendence. The Journal of Value Inquiry, 20(3), 195–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Kymlicka, W. (2002). Contemporary political philosophy: An introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  53. Laborem Exercens. (1981). Encyclical on human work, Pope John Paul II.Google Scholar
  54. Lane, R. E. (1991). The market experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  55. Lawrence, G. (1977). Management development…some ideals, images and realities. Journal of European Industrial Training, 1(2), 21–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  56. Levy, N. (2005, June 2). Downshifting and meaning in life. Ratio, XVIII, 176–189.Google Scholar
  57. MacIntyre, A. (1981). After virtue: A study in moral theory. London: Duckworth.Google Scholar
  58. Maddi, S. R. (1970). The search of meaning. In Nebraska symposium on motivation 1971, University of Nebraska Press.Google Scholar
  59. Margalit, A. (1996). The decent society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Martsolf, D. S., & Mickley, J. R. (1998). The concept of spirituality in nursing theories: Differing world-views and extent to focus. Journal of Clinical Nursing, 27, 294–303.Google Scholar
  61. Marx, K. (1978 [1844]). Economic and philosophical manuscripts. In R. Tucker (Ed.), The Marx–Engels reader (2nd ed.). New York: W. W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
  62. Marx, K. (1978 [1867]). Capital, Vol. 1: The process of production of capital. In R. Tucker (Ed.), The Marx–Engels reader (2nd ed.). New York: W. W. Norton & Company.Google Scholar
  63. Metz, T. (2001). The concept of a meaningful life. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38(2), 137–153.Google Scholar
  64. Michaelson, C., Pratt, M. G., Grant, A. M., & Dunn, C. P. (2013). Meaningful work: Connecting business ethics and organization studies. Journal of Business Ethics. doi: 10.1007/s10551-013-1675-5.
  65. Miller, D. (1999). Principles of social justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  66. Miller, R. W. (2003). Capitalism & Marxism. In R. G. Frey & C. Wellman (Eds.), A companion to applied ethics. Malden, MA: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  67. Morris, W. (1884). Art and socialism. Accessed 16 October 2011, from http://www.marxists.org/archive/morris/works/1884/as/as.htm.
  68. Morris, W. (1993 [1890]). News from nowhere and other writings. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  69. Muirhead, R. (2004). Just work. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  70. Nagel, T. (1971). The absurd. Journal of Philosophy, 68, 716–727.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  71. Naoi, M., & Schooler, C. (1985). Occupational conditions and psychological functioning in Japan. American Journal of Sociology, 90, 729–752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Nozick, R. (1974). Anarchy, state and utopia. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  73. Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  74. Rawls, J. (1999 [1971]). Theory of justice. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  75. Raz, J. (1986). The morality of freedom. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  76. Raz, J. (1996). Ethics in the Public Domain. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  77. Raz, J. (2001). Value, respect and attachment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  78. Raz, J. (2003). The practice of value. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  79. Reader, S. (2005). Aristotle on necessities and needs. In S. Reader (Ed.), The philosophy of need: Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  80. Roessler, B. (2012). Meaningful work: Arguments from autonomy. Journal of Political Philosophy, 20(1), 71–93.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  81. Rosso, B. D., Dekas, K. H., & Wrzesniewski, A. (2010). On the meaning of work: A theoretical integration and review. Research in Organizational Behavior, 30, 91–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  82. Sayers, S. (2005). Why work? Marx and human nature. Science and Society, 69(4), 606–616.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  83. Scheffler, S. (2006). Projects, relationships and reasons. In R. J. Wallace, P. Pettit, S. Scheffler, & M. Smith (Eds.), Reason and value: Themes from the moral philosophy of Joseph Raz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  84. Schooler, C. (2007). Culture and social structure: The relevance of social structure to cultural psychology. In S. Kitayama & D. Cohen (Eds.), Handbook of cultural psychology. New York: The Guildford Press.Google Scholar
  85. Schwartz, A. (1982). Meaningful work. Ethics, 92(4), 634–646.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  86. Schwartz, M. (1998). Peter Drucker and the denial of business ethics. Journal of Business Ethics, 17, 1685–1692.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  87. Sen, A. K. (1999). Development as freedom. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  88. Sen, A. K. (2009). The idea of justice. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press.Google Scholar
  89. Sher, G. (1997). Beyond neutrality: Perfectionism and politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  90. Shershow, S. C. (2005). The work and the gift. London: The Chicago University Press.Google Scholar
  91. Smart, J. J. C., & Williams, B. (1983). Utilitarianism: For & against. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  92. Smith, A. (1999 [1776]). The wealth of nations. London: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  93. Sparks, J. R., & Schenk, J. A. (2001). Explaining the effects of transformational leadership: An investigation of the effects of higher-order motives in multilevel marketing organizations. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 22, 849–869.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Spelman, E. V. (2003). Repair: The impulse to restore in a fragile world. Boston: Beacon Press.Google Scholar
  95. Starkey, C. (2006). Meaning and affect. The Pluralist, 1(2), 88–103.Google Scholar
  96. Taylor, R. (1970). Good and evil: A new direction. New York: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  97. Terkel, S. (1975). Working. London: Wildwood House.Google Scholar
  98. Thomson, G. (1987). Needs. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
  99. Thomson, G. (2005). Fundamental needs. In S. Reader (Ed.), The philosophy of need. Royal Institute of Philosophy supplement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  100. Wallace, K. (1993). Reconstructing judgement: Emotion and moral judgement. Hypatia, 8(3), 61–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  101. Walzer, M. (1983). Spheres of justice: A defence of pluralism & equality. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  102. Walzer, M. (1994). Thick and thin. Paris: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  103. Weick, K. E. (1995). Sensemaking in Organizations. London: SAGE Publications.Google Scholar
  104. Wiggins, D. (1988). Truth, invention, and the meaning of life. In G. Sayre-McCord (Ed.), Essays on moral realism. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.Google Scholar
  105. Williams, B. (1981). Persons, character and morality. In B. Williams (Ed.), Moral luck. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  106. Wolf, S. (1982). Moral saints. The Journal of Philosophy, 79(8), 419–439.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  107. Wolf, S. (1997a). Happiness and meaning: Two aspects of the good life. Social Philosophy & Policy, 14, 207–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  108. Wolf, S. (1997b). Meaningful lives in a meaningless world. In Quaestiones infinitae (Vol. 19). Utrecht: Utrecht University.Google Scholar
  109. Wolf, S. (2002). The true, the good, and the lovable: Frankfurt’s avoidance of objectivity. In S. Buss & L. Overton (Eds.), Contours of agency: Essays on themes from Harry Frankfurt. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  110. Wolf, S. (2007). The meanings of lives. New York University. Accessed 25 July 2009, from http://www1.law.nyu.edu/clppt/program2003/readings/wolf.pdf.
  111. Wolf, S. (2010). Meaning in life and why it matters. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  112. Wong, W. (2008). Meaningfulness and identities. Ethical Theory and Moral Practice, 11(2), 123–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  113. Wrzesniewski, A., & Dutton, J. (2001). Crafting a job: Revisioning employees as active crafters of their work. Academy of Management Review, 26(2), 179–201.Google Scholar
  114. Wrzesniewski, A., Dutton, J., & Debebe, G. (2003). Interpersonal sensemaking and the meaning of work. In R. Kramer & B. M. Staw (Eds.), Research in organisational behaviour (Vol. 25, pp. 93–135). San Francisco: Interscience.Google Scholar
  115. Young, I. M. (1990). Justice and the politics of difference. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Oxford Centre for Mutual and Employee-Owned Business, Kellogg CollegeUniversity of OxfordOxfordUK

Personalised recommendations