Skip to main content
Log in

Supererogation: Beyond Positive Deviance and Corporate Social Responsibility

  • Published:
Journal of Business Ethics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The special class of supererogatory actions—those that go “beyond the call of duty”—has thus far been omitted from the management literature. Rather, actions of a firm that may surpass economic and legal requirements have been discussed either under the umbrella term of Corporate Social Responsibility (CSR) or the concept of positive deviance as articulated by the Positive Organizational Scholarship (POS) movement. This paper seeks to clarify how “duty” is understood in these literatures and makes an argument that paradigmatic examples of corporate supererogation in fact lie beyond what is traditionally conceptualized as CSR and positive deviance. In so doing, this paper contributes to the growing body of research on Positive Organizational Ethics, as well as both the CSR and POS literatures, by presenting an extended deontological framework of CSR and bringing conceptual clarity to an otherwise muddied domain.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Underlying this thesis is the understanding that the strategic decisions/actions of the firm are made by people within the organization who are themselves moral agents. However, the unit of analysis herein is the action and not the individual who made the decision to act and hence the level of analysis with regards to duties is at the firm level and not the individual level. Similarly, attributions of supererogation should therefore also be limited to the action, and not to the firm as a whole.

  2. For example, long-standing informal ethical standards were finally codified into law (The Sarbanes–Oxley Act) after the Enron and WorldCom accounting scandals.

  3. Carroll refers to the fourth category as “discretionary” in his 1979 paper, however changes this to “philanthropic” in the 1991 paper.

  4. For example, in a series of recent experiments, Knobe (2006) found that moral considerations affect the way in which people judge the actions of the Chairman of the Board. Given a situation where the Chairman clearly states that he does not care about the environment, but is presented with a new program introduction that would increase profits and also help the environment, most subjects said that despite the increase in profits and benefit to the environment, the Chairman did not intentionally help the environment, nor was his action to accept the new program particularly praiseworthy. In the opposite scenario, where the new program presented would increase profits and also harm the environment, the Chairman’s expressed indifference to the environment coupled with his decision to proceed with the program was seen as both intentionally harmful to the environment and blameworthy. Knobe concludes that people are likely to blame the agent if his/her behavior has a bad side-effect, but not likely to praise the agent if his behavior has a good side-effect.

  5. The condition of permissibility (1) places supererogation, in Heyd’s conceptualization, in “one of the three types of actions considered from a moral standpoint: the obligatory, the permissible and the forbidden” (p. 122).

  6. In Carroll’s (1979) social responsiveness model, going beyond the legal requirements in employee relations or environmental issues would likely be considered a “proactive” strategy. In other “continuums” of social or ethical responsibilities, this perspective is also referred to as “beyond compliance” (Neville 2008; Sekerka 2012).

  7. It is possible, therefore that supererogatory actions may not actually lie on the same curve. Although beyond the scope of this paper, it is conceivable that supererogatory actions, by virtue of their rarity, probably do not adhere to Gaussian statistics altogether, but are rather Pareto distributed.

  8. This is in contrast, for example, to the public outcry for Ford’s failure to recall the Pinto when it knew of the gas-tank defect.

References

  • Arnold, D., & Hartman, L. (2005). Beyond sweatshops: Positive deviance and global labor practices. Business Ethics: A European Review, 14(3), 206–222.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, M. (1987). Kantian ethics and supererogation. The Journal of Philosophy, 84(5), 237–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baucus, M., & Near, J. (1991). Can illegal corporate behavior be predicted? An event history Analysis. Academy of Management Journal, 34(1), 9–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Business Enterprise Trust. (1991). Merck & Co. Inc., Case Study. In D. Bollier & K. Hanson (Eds.). Stanford, CA: Business Enterprise Trust.

  • Cameron, K. S., Dutton, J. E., & Quinn, R. E. (2003). Positive organizational scholarship: Foundations of a new discipline. San Francisco: Berrett-Koehler Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, J. L. (2007). Why would corporations behave in socially responsible ways? An institutional theory of corporate social responsibility. Academy of Management Review, 32(3), 946–967.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, A. B. (1979). A three-dimensional conceptual model of corporate social performance. Academy of Management Review, 4(4), 497–505.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, A. B. (1991). The pyramid of corporate social responsibility: Toward the moral management of organizational stakeholders. Business Horizons, 34(4), 39–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carroll, A. B. (1999). Corporate social responsibility: Evolution of a definitional construct. Business and Society, 38(3), 268–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caza, A., Barker, B. A., & Cameron, K. S. (2004). Ethics and ethos: The buffering and amplifying effects of ethical behavior and virtuousness. Journal of Business Ethics, 52(2), 169–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Bakker, F. G. A., Groenewegen, P., & Den Hond, F. (2005). A bibliometric analysis of 30 years of research and theory on corporate social responsibility and corporate social performance. Business and Society, 44(3), 283–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiMaggio, P. J., & Powell, W. W. (1983). The iron cage revisited: Institutional isomorphism and collective rationality in organizational fields. American Sociological Review, 48(2), 147–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, R. (1984). Strategic management: A stakeholder perspective. Boston, MA: Pitman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1970). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine, 13(1970), 32–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gable, S., & Haidt, J. (2005). What (and why) is positive psychology? Review of General Psychology, 9(2), 103–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gan, A. (2006). The impact of public scrutiny on corporate philanthropy. Journal of Business Ethics, 69, 217–236.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey, P. C. (2005). The relationship between corporate philanthropy and shareholder wealth: A risk management perspective. The Academy of Management Review, 30(4), 777–798.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyd, D. (1982). Supererogation: Its status in ethical theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kashyap, R., Mir, R., & Iyer, E. (2006). Toward a responsive pedagogy: Linking social responsibility to firm performance issues in the classroom. Academy of Management Learning and Education, 5(3), 366–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2006). The concept of intentional action: A case study in the uses of folk psychology. Philosophical Studies, 130, 203–231.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luthans, F. (2002). The need for and meaning of positive organizational behavior. Journal of Organizational Behavior, 23, 695–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. D., & Walsh, J. P. (2003). Misery loves companies: Rethinking social initiatives by business. Administrative Science Quarterly, 48(2), 268–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, R. L. (2002). The virtue matrix: Calculating the return on corporate responsibility. Harvard Business Review, 80(3), 68–75.

    Google Scholar 

  • McWilliams, A., & Siegel, D. (2001). Corporate social responsibility: A theory of the firm perspective. Academy of Management Review, 26(1), 117–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellema, G. (1991). Beyond the call of duty: Supererogation, obligation and offence. Albany, NY: State University New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellema, G. (1994). Business ethics and doing what one ought to do. Journal of Business Ethics, 13, 149–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Neville, M. G. (2008). Positive deviance on the ethical continuum: Green Mountain Coffee as a case study in conscious capitalism. Business and Society Review, 113(4), 555–576.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Okoye, A. (2009). Theorising corporate social responsibility as an essentially contested concept: Is a definition necessary? Journal of Business Ethics, 89(4), 613–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Orlitzky, M., Schmidt, F. L., & Rynes, S. L. (2003). Corporate social and financial performance: A meta-analysis. Organization Studies, 24(3), 403–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, S. L., & Bennett, R. J. (1995). A typology of deviant workplace behaviors: A multidimensional scaling study. Academy of Management Journal, 38(2), 555–572.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sabadoz, C. (2011). Between profit-seeking and prosociality: Corporate social responsibility as Derridean supplement. Journal of Business Ethics, 104(1), 77–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schwartz, M. S., & Carroll, A. B. (2008). Integrating and unifying competing and complementary frameworks: The search for a common core in the business and society field. Business and Society, 47(2), 148–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scott, W. R. (1995). Institutions and organizations (1st ed.). Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sekerka, L. E. (2012). Compliance as a subtle precursor to ethical corrosion: A strength-based approach as a way forward. Wyoming Law Review, 12(2), 277–302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sekerka, L. E., & Stimel, D. (2011). How durable is sustainable enterprise? Ecological sustainability meets the reality of tough economic times. Business Horizons, 54(2), 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seligman, M. (2002). Positive psychology, positive prevention and positive therapy. In C. Snyder & S. Lopez (Eds.), Handbook of positive psychology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spreitzer, G. M., & Sonenshein, S. (2004). Toward the construct definition of positive deviance. American Behavioral Scientist, 47(6), 828–847.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starik, M., & Rands, G. P. (1995). Weaving an integrated web: Multilevel and multisystem perspectives of ecologically sustainable organizations. Academy of Management Review, 20(4), 908–935.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strike, V. M., Gao, J., & Bansal, P. (2006). Being good while being bad: Social responsibility and the international diversification of US firms. Journal of International Business Studies, 37(6), 850–862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suchman, M. C. (1995). Managing legitimacy: Strategic and institutional approaches. Academy of Management Review, 20(3), 571–610.

    Google Scholar 

  • Swanson, D. L. (1995). Addressing a theoretical problem by reorienting the corporate social performance model. Academy of Management Review, 20(1), 43–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thylefors, B. (2004). Eliminating onchocerciasis as a public health problem. Tropical Medicine and International Health, 9(1), A1–A3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Verbos, A. K., Gerard, J. A., Forshey, P. R., Harding, C. S., & Miller, J. S. (2007). The positive ethical organization: Enacting a living code of ethics and ethical organizational identity. Journal of Business Ethics, 76(1), 17–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddock, S. A., Bodwell, C., & Graves, S. B. (2002). Responsibility: The new business imperative. Academy of Management Executive, 16(2), 132–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, D. E. (2003). Constructive and destructive deviance in organizations. The Academy of Management Review, 29(4), 622–632.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wettstein, F. (2009). Beyond voluntariness, beyond CSR: Making a case for human rights and justice. Business and Society Review, 114(1), 125–152.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

The author is indebted to Mary Crossan, Anthony Skelton, Corey Mulvihill, and the special issue reviewers for their thoughtful guidance, comments, and feedback on this project and would like to acknowledge the Pierre Elliott Trudeau Foundation for their financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daina Mazutis.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mazutis, D. Supererogation: Beyond Positive Deviance and Corporate Social Responsibility. J Bus Ethics 119, 517–528 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1837-5

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10551-013-1837-5

Keywords

Navigation