Journal of Business Ethics

, Volume 108, Issue 1, pp 15–25 | Cite as

Bernard Hodgson’s Trojan Horse Critique of Neoclassical Economics and the Second Phase of the Empiricist Level of Analysis

Article
  • 246 Downloads

Abstract

This article examines and assesses Bernard Hodgson’s critique of the Neoclassical concept of rationality and its place in the literature. It is argued that Hodgson’s Trojan horse critique is superior to the others because it addresses the role of empiricist epistemology in reducing reason to instrumental rationality and consequent disappearance of the human subject of political economy. The second phase of the empiricist level of analysis reintroduces the capacities for ethical deliberation, self-determination, and the socio-historical conditions and institutional setting of the economic agent. Because Hodgson’s solutions presuppose empiricist terrain, they are arbitrary. This occurs because the fundamental problem of Neoclassical rationality is its ontology. Yet by introducing the human subject into economic theory, Hodgson’s solutions move onto an ontological terrain adequate for economic analysis of human subjects.

Keywords

Ontology Rationality Neoclassical economics Organicism Atomism Trojan horse 

References

  1. Arnsperger, C., & Varoufakis, Y. (2006). What is neoclassical economics? The three axioms responsible for its theoretical oeuvre, practical irrelevance, and, thus, discursive power. Post-Autistic Economics Review, 38, 2–12.Google Scholar
  2. Badeen, D. (2004). General equilibrium theory as normative ideal social order. In B. Hodgson (Ed.), The invisible hand and the common good (pp. 183–204). New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  3. Elster, J. (1983). Sour grapes: studies in the subversion of rationality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Hausman, D. M., & McPherson, M. S. (1996). Economics analysis and moral philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Hodgson, B. (2001). Economics as moral science. New York: Springer.Google Scholar
  6. Hodgson, B. (2007). Logical positivism and the Vienna circle. In C. Boundas (Ed.), Columbia companion to twentieth century philosophy (pp. 98–115). New York: Columbia University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Hodgson, G. (2001). How economics forgot history: the problem of historical specificity in social science. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Hume, D. (1985). Treatise of human nature. New York: Penguin Books.Google Scholar
  9. Lawson, T. (1997). Economics and reality. New York: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Lawson, T. (2003). Reorienting economics. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  11. Sen, A. (1985). Commodities and capabilities. New Delhi: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Sen, A. (1987). On ethics and economics. New York: Basil Blackwell.Google Scholar
  13. Winslow, E. (1994). Atomism and organicism. In Geoffrey M. Hodgson, Warren J. Samuels, & Marc R. Tool (Eds.), Elgar companion to institutional and evolutionary economics (pp. 11–13). Brookfield: Aldershot.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.York UniversityTorontoCanada

Personalised recommendations