Journal of Business Ethics

, Volume 106, Issue 3, pp 313–324 | Cite as

For-Profit Business as Civic Virtue

Article

Abstract

According to the commonsense view of civic virtue, the places to exercise civic virtue are largely restricted to politics. In this article, I argue for a more expansive view of civic virtue, and argue that one can exercise civic virtue equally well through working for or running a for-profit business. I argue that this conclusion follows from four relatively uncontroversial premises: (1) the consensus definition of “civic virtue”, (2) the standard, most popular theory of virtuous activity, (3) a conception of the common good widely shared by liberal political philosophers, and (4) the mainstream economic theory of for-profit business.

Keywords

Civic virtue Civic republicanism Extrapolitical conception of civic virtue For-profit business 

References

  1. Alston, R. M., Kearl, J. R., & Vaughan, M. B. (1992). Is there a consensus among economists in the 1990’s? American Economic Review, 82, 203–209.Google Scholar
  2. Annas, J. (2000). Virtue ethics. In D. Copp (Ed.), The Oxford companion to ethical theory. New York City, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Becker, G. (1980). The obligation to work. Ethics, 91, 35–49.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Brennan, J. (2011). The ethics of voting. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  5. Brennan, J. (2012) Political liberty: Who needs it? Social Philosophy and Policy 29 (forthcoming).Google Scholar
  6. Brennan, G., & Hamlin, A. (1995). Economizing on virtue. Constitutional Political Economy, 6, 35–60.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Brennan, G., & Lomasky, L. (2006). Against reviving republicanism. Politics, Philosophy, and Economics, 5, 221–252.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Burtt, S. (1990). The good citizen’s psyche: On the psychology of civic virtue. Polity, 23, 23–38.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Cohen, G. A. (1995). Self-ownership, freedom, and equality. New York City, NY: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Cowen, T. (2000). In praise of commercial culture. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  11. Crittenden, J. (2007). Civic education. In E. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/entries/civic-education/.
  12. Dagger, R. (1997). Civic virtues: Rights, citizenship, and republican liberalism. New York City, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  13. Ekelund, R., Ressler, R., & Tollison, R. (2006). Microeconomics: Private and public choice. New York City, NY: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  14. Freidman, M. (1970, Sep 13). The social responsibility of business is to increase its profits. New York Times Magazine.Google Scholar
  15. Galston, W. (2007). Pluralism and civic virtue. Social Theory and Practice, 33, 625–635.Google Scholar
  16. Gaus, G. (1990). The commitment to the common good. In P. Harris (Ed.), On political obligation. New York City, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Gaus, G. (1996). Justificatory liberalism. New York City, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  18. Hursthouse, R. (1999). On virtue ethics. New York City, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  19. Krugman, P., & Wells, R. (2009). Economics (2nd ed.). New York City, NY: Worth Publishers.Google Scholar
  20. Lovett, F. (2010). Republicanism. In E. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/republicanism/.
  21. Mankiw, G. (2008). Principles of economics (5th ed.). New York City, NY: Southwestern College Publishers.Google Scholar
  22. McConnell, C., Brue, S., & Flynn, S. (2008). Economics (18th ed.). New York City, NY: McGraw-Hill.Google Scholar
  23. Oldfield, A. (1990). Citizenship: An unnatural practice. Political Quarterly, 61, 177–187.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Patten, A. (1996). The republican critique of liberalism. British Journal of Political Science, 26, 25–44.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Raeder, L. C. (1998). Liberalism and the common good: A Hayekian perspective on communitarianism. The Independent Review, 2, 519–535.Google Scholar
  26. Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Redner, H. (2001). Ethical life: The past and present of culture. Lanham, CO: Rowman and Littlefield.Google Scholar
  28. Schmidtz, D. (1995). Rational choice and moral agency. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  29. Schmidtz, D., & Brennan, J. (2010). A brief history of liberty. Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Stevenson, B., & Wolfers, J. (2008). Economic growth and subjective well-being: Reassessing the Easterlin paradox. Brookings Papers on Economic Development, 39, 1–102.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Weil, D. (2009). Economic growth (2nd ed.). New York City, NY: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2011

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Brown UniversityProvidenceUSA

Personalised recommendations