Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 27, Issue 4, pp 481–496 | Cite as

Mathematical models of biological patterns: Lessons from Hamilton’s selfish herd

Article

Abstract

Mathematical models of biological patterns are central to contemporary biology. This paper aims to consider what these models contribute to biology through the detailed consideration of an important case: Hamilton’s selfish herd. While highly abstract and idealized, Hamilton’s models have generated an extensive amount of research and have arguably led to an accurate understanding of an important factor in the evolution of gregarious behaviors like herding and flocking. I propose an account of what these models are able to achieve and how they can support a successful scientific research program. I argue that the way these models are interpreted is central to the success of such programs.

Keywords

Models Idealization Gregarious behavior Voronoi diagrams 

Notes

Acknowledgments

Earlier versions of this paper were presented at the Missouri Philosophy of Science Workshop (MOPS), March 2011 and the 14th Congress of Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science, Nancy, France, July 2011. I am grateful to both audiences and two journal referees for their comments and suggestions. I would also like to thank André Ariew for many insightful discussions about this paper and the philosophy of biology more generally.

References

  1. Brierley AS, Cox MJ (2010) Shapes of krill swarms and fish schools emerge as aggregation members avoid predators and access oxygen. Curr Biol 20:1758–1762CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Early RL, Dugatkin LA (2010) Behavior in groups. In: Westneat DF, Fox CW (eds) Evolutionary behavioral ecology, Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 285–307Google Scholar
  3. Forber P (2010) Confirmation and explaining how possible. Stud Hist Philos Biol Biomed Sci 41:32–40Google Scholar
  4. Godfrey-Smith P (2006) The strategy of model-based science. Biol Philos 21:725–740CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Hamilton WD (1971) Geometry for the selfish herd. J Theor Biol 31:295–311CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. James R, Bennett PG, Krause J (2004) Geometry for mutualistic and selfish herds: the limited domain of danger. J Theor Biol 228:107–113CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Lima SL (2002) Putting predators back into behavioral predator-prey interactions. Trends Ecol Evol 17:70–75CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Lind J, Cresswell W (2005) Determining the fitness consequences of antipredation behavior. Behav Ecol 16:945–956CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Morrell LJ, Ruxton GD, James R (2011) The temporal selfish herd: predation risk while aggregations form. Proc R Soc B 278:605–612CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Odenbaugh J (2005) Idealized, inaccurate but successful: a pragmatic approach to evaluating models in theoretical ecology. Biol Philos 20:231–255CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Okabe A, Boots B, Sugihara K, Chiu SN (2000) Spatial tesselations: concepts and applications of Voronoi diagrams, 2nd edn. Wiley, HobokenGoogle Scholar
  12. Quinn JL, Cresswell W (2006) Testing domains of danger in the selfish herd: sparrowhawks target widely spaced redshanks in flocks. Proc R Soc B 273:2521–2526CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Rands SA, Pettifor RA, Rowcliffe JM, Cowlishaw G (2004) State-dependent foraging rules for social animals in selfish herds. Proc R Soc B 271:2613–2620CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Stankowich T (2003) Marginal predation methodologies and the importance of predator preferences. Anim Behav 66:589–599CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Teller P (2009) Fictions, fictionalization, and truth in science. In: Suárez M (ed) Fictions in science: philosophical essays on modeling and idealization. Routledge, London, pp 235–247Google Scholar
  16. Vine I (1971) Risk of visual detection and pursuit by a predator and the selective advantage of flocking behaviour. J Theor Biol 30:405–422CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Viscido SV (2003) The case for the selfish herd hypothesis. Comments Theor Biol 8:665–684Google Scholar
  18. Viscido SV, Miller M, Wethey DS (2002) The dilemma of the selfish herd: the search for a realistic movement rule. J Theor Biol 217:183–194CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Weisberg M (2007a) Three kinds of idealization. J Phil 104:639–659Google Scholar
  20. Weisberg M (2007b) Who is a modeler? Br J Phil Sci 58:207–233CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Wood AJ (2010) Strategy selection under predation; evolutionary analysis of the emergence of cohesive aggregations. J Theor Biol 264:1102–1110CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of MissouriColumbiaUSA

Personalised recommendations