Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 27, Issue 4, pp 545–570 | Cite as

How to demarcate the boundaries of cognition

Article

Abstract

Advocates of extended cognition argue that the boundaries of cognition span brain, body, and environment. Critics maintain that cognitive processes are confined to a boundary centered on the individual. All participants to this debate require a criterion for distinguishing what is internal to cognition from what is external. Yet none of the available proposals are completely successful. I offer a new account, the mutual manipulability account, according to which cognitive boundaries are determined by relationships of mutual manipulability between the properties and activities of putative components and the overall behavior of the cognitive mechanism in which they figure. Among its main advantages, this criterion is capable of (a) distinguishing components of cognition from causal background conditions and lower-level correlates, and (b) showing how the core hypothesis of extended cognition can serve as a legitimate empirical hypothesis amenable to experimental test and confirmation. Conceiving the debate in these terms transforms the current clash over extended cognition into a substantive empirical debate resolvable on the basis of evidence from cognitive science and neuroscience.

Keywords

Extended cognition Embodied cognition Mutual manipulability Intervention Mechanism 

References

  1. Adams F, Aizawa K (2001) The bounds of cognition. Philos Psychol 14:43–64CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Adams F, Aizawa K (2008) The bounds of cognition. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  3. Adams F, Aizawa K (2010) Defending the bounds of cognition. In: Menary R (ed) The extended mind. Ashgate, AldershotGoogle Scholar
  4. Autumn K (2006) How gecko toes stick. Am Sci 94:124–132Google Scholar
  5. Autumn K, Liang YA, Shie ST, Zesch W, Chan WP, Kenny TW, Fearing R, Full RJ (2000) Adhesive force of a single gecko foot-hair. Nature 405:681–684CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Ballard D, Hayhoe M, Pelz J (1995) Memory representations in natural tasks. Cogn Neurosci 7:66–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bechtel W (2008) Mental mechanisms: philosophical perspectives on cognitive neuroscience. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  8. Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1993) Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as strategies in scientific research. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  9. Clark A (1997) Being there: putting brain, body, and world together again. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  10. Clark A (1999) An embodied cognitive science? Trends Cogn Sci 3(9):345–351CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Clark A (2005) Intrinsic content, active memory, and the extended mind. Analysis 65(10):1–11CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Clark A (2007) Curing cognitive hiccups: a defense of the extended mind. J Philos 104(4):163–192Google Scholar
  13. Clark A (2008) Supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  14. Clark A, Chalmers DJ (1998) The extended mind. Analysis 58:10–23CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Craver CF (2002) Interlevel experiments and multilevel mechanisms in the neuroscience of memory. Philos Sci Suppl 69:S83–S97CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Craver CF (2007a) Explaining the brain. Oxford University Press, New YorkCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Craver CF (2007b) Constitutive explanatory relevance. J Philos Res 32:3–20Google Scholar
  18. Craver CF, Darden L (2001) Discovering mechanisms in neurobiology: the case of spatial memory. In: Machamer PK, Grush R, McLaughlin P (eds) Theory and method in neuroscience. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 112–137Google Scholar
  19. Dennett DC (1987) The intentional stance. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  20. Feldman AG, Levin MF (1995) Positional frames of reference in motor control: origin and use. Behav Brain Sci 18(4):723–806CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Fisk J, Lackner JR, Dizio P (1993) Gravitoinertial force level influences arm movement control. J Neurophysiol 69(2):504–511Google Scholar
  22. Fodor JA (2009) Where is my mind? Review of supersizing the mind: embodiment, action, and cognitive extension. Lond Rev Books 31(3):13–15Google Scholar
  23. Grush R (2003) In defense of some ‘Cartesian’ assumptions concerning the brain and its operation. Biol Philos 18:53–93CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Haugeland J (1995/1998) Mind embodied and embedded. Acta Philosophica Fennica 58:233–267 (Reprinted in Haugeland, J. Having Thought. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press)Google Scholar
  25. Logothetis NK (2008) What we can and what we cannot do with fMRI. Nature 453:869–878CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Machamer P, Darden L, Craver CF (2000) Thinking about mechanisms. Philos Sci 67:1–25Google Scholar
  27. Nelson WL (1983) Physical principles for economies of skilled movements. Biol Cybern 46:135–147CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Polger T (2004) Natural minds. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  29. Polit A, Bizzi E (1978) Processes controlling arm movements in monkeys. Science 201(4362):1235–1237CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Putnam H (1975) The nature of mental states. In: Mind, language, and reality. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  31. Rodieck RW (1998) The first steps in seeing. Sinauer, SunderlandGoogle Scholar
  32. Romo R, Hernández A, Zainos A, Salinas E (1998) Somatosensory discrimination based on cortical microstimulation. Nature 392(6674):387–390CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Rowlands M (1999) The body in mind. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Rowlands M (2010) The new science of the mind: from extended mind to embodied phenomenology. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  35. Rumelhart DE, Smolensky P, McClelland JL, Hinton G (1986) Schemata and sequential thought processes in PDP models. In: McClelland JL, Rumelhart D (eds) Parallel distributed processing: explorations in the microstructure of cognition, vol. 2: psychological and biological models. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 7–57Google Scholar
  36. Rupert R (2004) Challenges to the hypothesis of extended cognition. J Philos 101(8):389–428Google Scholar
  37. Searle J (1980) Minds, brains, and programs. Behav Brain Sci 3:417–424CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Shadmehr R, Wise SP (2005) The computational neurobiology of reaching and pointing: a foundation for motor learning. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  39. Shapiro LA (2009) Review of the bounds of cognition. Phenomenol Cogn Sci 8:267–273CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Simon HA (1969) The sciences of the artificial. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  41. Talbot WH, Darian-Smith I, Kornhuber HH, Mountcastle VB (1968) The sense of flutter-vibration: comparison of the human capacity with response patterns of mechanoreceptive afferents from the monkey hand. J Neurophysiol 31(2):301–334Google Scholar
  42. Velliste M, Perel S, Spalding MC, Whitford AS, Schwartz AB (2008) Cortical control of a prosthetic arm for self-feeding. Nature 453:1098–1101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Wheeler M (2010) Extended functionalism. In: Menary R (ed) The extended mind. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  44. Wilson RA (2004) Boundaries of the Mind: the individual in the fragile sciences. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  45. Wolpert DM, Ghahramani Z (2000) Computational principles of movement neuroscience. Nat Neurosci 3:1212–1217CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Woodward J (2003) Making things happen: a theory of causal explanation. Oxford University Press, New York Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Anatomy and NeurobiologyWashington University School of MedicineSaint LouisUSA

Personalised recommendations