Biology and Philosophy

, Volume 21, Issue 5, pp 667–702

Aggregate, composed, and evolved systems: Reductionistic heuristics as means to more holistic theories

Article

Abstract

Richard Levins’ distinction between aggregate, composed and evolved systems acquires new significance as we recognize the importance of mechanistic explanation. Criteria for aggregativity provide limiting cases for absence of organization, so through their failure, can provide rich detectors for organizational properties. I explore the use of failures of aggregativity for the analysis of mechanistic systems in diverse contexts. Aggregativity appears theoretically desireable, but we are easily fooled. It may be exaggerated through approximation, conditions of derivation, and extrapolating from some conditions of decomposition illegtimately to others. Evolved systems particularly may require analyses under alternative complementary decompositions. Exploring these conditions helps us to better understand the strengths and limits of reductionistic methods.

Keywords

Aggregativity Heuristics Functional localization fallacies Reductionism Mechanism Complexity Intersubstitutability Nothing-but-ism Decomposability Invariance Richard Levins 

References

  1. Abbott A (2001) Self-similar social structures. In: Chaos among the disciplines, Chapter 8. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  2. Allen G (1979) Thomas Hunt Morgan: the man and his science. Princeton University press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  3. Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1992) Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as scientific research strategies. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  4. Boveri T (1902) On multipolar mitosis as a means of analysis of the cell nucleus, English translation of Über mehrpolige Mitosen als Mittel zur Analyse des Zellkerns. Verhandlungen der physikalish-medizinischen Gesellschaft zu Würzburg 35:67–90. Reprinted in Willier BH, Oppenheim JM (1974) Foundations of experimental embryology, 2nd edn. MacMillan, New York, pp 74–97Google Scholar
  5. Brandon R (1982) The levels of selection. In: PSA-1982, vol 1, pp 315–323 Google Scholar
  6. Brandon R (1999) The units of selection revisited: the modules of selection. Biol Philos 14(#2):167–180CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cartwright N (1983) How the laws of physics lie. Cambridge U. P., LondonGoogle Scholar
  8. Crow JF, Kimura M (1970) An introduction to theoretical population genetics. Norton, EvanstonGoogle Scholar
  9. Darden L (1992) Theory change in science: strategies from Mendelian genetics. Oxford U. P., New YorkGoogle Scholar
  10. Dennett D (1995) Darwin’s dangerous idea. Simon and Schuster, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  11. Glennan SS (1996) Mechanisms and the nature of causation. Erkenntnis 44(1996):49–71Google Scholar
  12. Griesemer J, Wade M (1988) Laboratory models, causal explanation and group selection. Biol Philos 3:67–96CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Griffiths P (1996) Darwinism, process structuralism and natural kinds. Philos Sci 63(3), Supplement: PSA-1996, v. I:1–9Google Scholar
  14. Haugeland J (1999) Having thought: essays in the metaphysics of mind. Harvard U.P., CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  15. Humphreys P (2006) Pattern emergence, draft manuscriptGoogle Scholar
  16. Kauffman S (1971) Articulation of parts explanations in biology and the rational search for them. In: Buck R, Cohen RS (eds) PSA-1970. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 257–272Google Scholar
  17. Levins R (1966) The strategy of model building in population biology. Am Sci 54:421–431Google Scholar
  18. Levins R (1968) Evolution in changing environments. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  19. Levins R (1970) Complexity. In: Waddington CH (ed) Towards a theoretical biology, Vol. 3. University of Edinburgh Press, Edinburgh, pp 67–86Google Scholar
  20. Levins R (1973) The limits of complexity. In: Pattee HH (ed) Hierarchy theory: the challenge of complex systems. George Brazuller, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  21. Lewontin RC (1974) The genetic basis of evolutionary change. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  22. Lewontin RC (1978) Adaptation. Scientific American, SeptemberGoogle Scholar
  23. Lloyd E (1988/93) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Greenwood Press, Westport Conn., 1988. Reissued by Princeton University Press, 1993Google Scholar
  24. Lloyd E (1989) A structural approach to defining the units of selection. Philos Sci 56:395–418CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Lloyd E (1994) The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton University Press, Princeton Google Scholar
  26. Mainschein J (1991) Transforming traditions in American biology, 1880–1915. Johns Hopkins University press, BaltimoreGoogle Scholar
  27. Martinez S (1992) Robustness and objectivity, draft ms. in English, 1992 (Spanish version published in Dianoia, (Annual of Instituto de Investigaciones Filosoficas, Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico))Google Scholar
  28. McClamrock R (1995) Existential cognition: computational minds in the world. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  29. Moss L (1992) A kernel of truth? On the reality of the genetic program. In: Hull D, Forbes M, Okruhlik K (eds) PSA-1992, vol 1. The Philosophy of Sciences Association, East Lansing, pp 335–348Google Scholar
  30. Nagel E (1961) The structure of science. Harcourt Brace & World, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  31. Odenbaugh J (2001) Searching for patterns, hunting for causes: a philosophical examination of mathematical modeling in theoretical ecology. PhD Dissertation, University of CalgaryGoogle Scholar
  32. Platt JR (1969) Theorems on boundaries of hierarchial systems. In: AGG Wilson, LL Whyte, D Wilson (eds) Hierarchial structures. American Elsevier, New York, pp 201–213Google Scholar
  33. Plutinski A (2006) Strategies of model building in population genetics. Philos Sci 73(5). In pressGoogle Scholar
  34. Ramsey JL (1990) Meta-stable states: the justification of approximative procedures in chemical kinetics, 1923–1947. PhD, Committee on Conceptual Foundations of Science, University of ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  35. Rosenberg A (1978) The supervenience of biological concepts. Philos Sci 45:368–386CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Sarkar S (1992) Models of reduction and categories of reductionism. Synthese 91:167–194CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Sarkar S (1994) The selection of alleles and the additivity of variance. In: Hull D, Forbes M, Burian RM (eds) PSA 1994: proceedings of the 1994 biennial meeting of the philosophy of science association, vol 1. Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 3–12Google Scholar
  38. Sarkar S (1996) Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge U.P., CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  39. Sarkar S (1998) Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge U.P., CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  40. Schank JC, Wimsatt WC (2000) Evolvability: modularity and generative entrenchment. In: Singh R, Krimbas C, Paul D, Beatty J (eds) Thinking about evolution: historical, philosophical and political perspectives, (Festschrift for Richard Lewontin, vol 2), Cambridge U. P., London, pp 322–335Google Scholar
  41. Shapiro JA (1992) Natural genetic engineering in evolution. Genetica 86:99–111CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Simon HA (1962) The architecture of complexity. Reprinted in his The Sciences of the Artificial, MIT Press, 3rd edn, 1996Google Scholar
  43. Sober E (1981) Holism, individualism, and the units of selection. In: PSA-1980, v. 2, pp 93–121Google Scholar
  44. Sober E (1985) The nature of selection. MIT PressGoogle Scholar
  45. Strobeck K (1975) Selection in a fine-grained environment. Am Natural 109:419–426CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Tversky A, Kahnman D (1974) Judgement under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science 185:1124–1131CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  47. Von Neumann J, Morgenstern O (1947) Theory of games and economic behavior, 2nd edn. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  48. Wade MJ (1996) Adaptation in subdivided populations: Kin selection and interdemic selection. In: Rose M, Lauder G (eds) Adaptation. Academic Press, New York, pp 381–405Google Scholar
  49. Wade MJ (1978) A critical review of the models of group selection. Q Rev Biol 53:101–114CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Wagner A (2005) Robustness and evolvability in living systems. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  51. Waters K (1990) Why the Anti-reductionist consensus won’t survive the case of classical Mendelian genetics. In: Fine A, Forbes M, Wessels L (eds) PSA-1990, vol 1. The Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, pp 125–139Google Scholar
  52. Weisberg M (2003) When less is more: tradeoffs and idealization in model building, PhD Dissertation, Stanford UniversityGoogle Scholar
  53. Weisberg M (2006) Robustness analysis. Philos Sci 73(5). In pressGoogle Scholar
  54. Weisberg M, Reisman K (2007) The Robust Volterra principle. Currently under reviewGoogle Scholar
  55. Wimsatt WC (1971) Some problems with the concept of ‘Feedback’. In: Buck RC, Cohen RS (eds) PSA-1970 (Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol 8). Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 241–256Google Scholar
  56. Wimsatt WC (1972) Teleology and the logical structure of function statements. Stud Hist Philos Sci 3:1–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  57. Wimsatt WC (1974) Complexity and organization. In: Buck R, Cohen RS (eds) PSA-1972. Boston Studies in Phil. Sci., v.20, pp 67–86Google Scholar
  58. Wimsatt WC (1976a) Reductionism, levels of organization and the mind-body problem. In: Globus GG, Maxwell G, Savodnik I (eds) Consciousness and the brain. Plenum, New York, pp 199–267Google Scholar
  59. Wimsatt WC (1976b) Reductive explanation—a functional account. In: Michalos AC, Hooker CA, Pearce G, Cohen RS (eds) PSA-1974 (Boston studies in the philosophy of science, vol 30). Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 671–710Google Scholar
  60. Wimsatt WC (1979) Reduction and reductionism. In: Asquith PD, Kyberg H (eds) Current research in philosophy of science. The Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, Michigan, pp 352–377Google Scholar
  61. Wimsatt WC (1980a) Randomness and perceived-randomness in evolutionary biology. Synthese 43:287–329CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Wimsatt WC (1980b) Reductionistic research strategies and their biases in the units of selection controversy. In: Nickles T (ed) Scientific discovery-vol II: case studies. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 213–259Google Scholar
  63. Wimsatt WC (1981a) Robustness, reliability and over determination. In: Brewer R, Collins B (eds) Scientific inquiry and the social sciences. Jossey-Bass, San Francisco (festschrift for Donald Campbell)Google Scholar
  64. Wimsatt WC (1981b) Units of selection and the structure of the multi-level genome. In: Asquith P, Giere R (eds) PSA-1980, vol 2. Published by the Philosophy of Science Association, pp 122–183Google Scholar
  65. Wimsatt WC (1985) Heuristics and the study of human behavior. In: Fiske DW, Shweder R (eds) Metatheory in social science: pluralisms and subjectivities. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 293–314Google Scholar
  66. Wimsatt WC (1986a) Developmental constraints, generative entrenchment, and the innate-acquired distinction. In: Bechtel W (ed) Integrating scientific disciplines. Martinus Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 185–208Google Scholar
  67. Wimsatt WC (1986b) Forms of Aggregativity. In: Donagan A, Perovich N, Wedin M (eds) Human nature and natural knowledge, (Festschrift for Marjorie Grene). Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 259–293Google Scholar
  68. Wimsatt WC (1987) False models as means to truer theories. In: Nitecki M, Hoffman A (eds) Neutral models in biology. Oxford University Press, London, pp 23–55Google Scholar
  69. Wimsatt WC (1992) Golden generalities and co-opted anomalies: Haldane vs. Muller and the Drosophila group on the theory and practice of linkage mapping. In: Sarkar S (ed) The founders of evolutionary genetics. Martinus-Nijhoff, Dordrecht, pp 107–166Google Scholar
  70. Wimsatt WC (1994) The ontology of complex systems: levels, perspectives, and causal thickets. In: Matthen M, Ware R (eds) Biology and society: reflections on methodology. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, Supplementary volume #20, pp 207–274Google Scholar
  71. Wimsatt WC (1997) Functional organization, functional analogy, and functional inference. Evol Cogn 3(2):102–133Google Scholar
  72. Wimsatt WC (2001) Richard Levins as philosophical revolutionary. Biol Philos 16:103–108CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  73. Wimsatt WC (2002) Functional organization, Functional inference, and Functional analogy. In Robert Cummins, Andre Ariew, Mark Periman (eds) Function. Oxford, pp 174–221Google Scholar
  74. Wimsatt WC (2007) Re-engineering philosophy for limited beings: piecewise approximations to reality. Harvard U. P., CambridgeGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, B.V. 2007

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Philosophy, Committee on Evolutionary Biology and Committee on the Conceptual Foundations of ScienceUniversity of ChicagoChicagoUSA

Personalised recommendations