Biology & Philosophy

, Volume 22, Issue 3, pp 313–331 | Cite as

Representation in the genome and in other inheritance systems

Article

Abstract

There is ongoing controversy as to whether the genome is a representing system (Sterelny K., Smith K.C. and Dickson M. 1996. Biol. Philos. 11: 377–403; Griffiths P.E. 2001. Philos. Sci. 68: 394–412). Although it is widely recognised that DNA carries information, both correlating with and coding for various outcomes, neither of these implies that the genome has semantic properties like correctness or satisfaction conditions (Godfrey-Smith P. 2002. In: Wolenski J. and Kajania-Placek K. (eds), In the Scope of Logic, Methodology, and the Philosophy of Sciences, Vol. II. Kluwer, Dordrecht, pp. 387–400). Here a modified version of teleosemantics is applied to the genome to show that it does indeed have semantic properties – there is representation in the genome. The account differs in three respects from previous attempts to apply teleosemantics to genes. It emphasises the role of the consumer of representations (in addition to their mode of production). It rejects the standard assumption that genetic representation can be used to explain the course of an organism’s development. And it identifies the explanatory role played by representational properties of the genome. A striking consequence of this account is that other inheritance systems could also be representational. Thus, a version of the parity thesis is accepted (Griffiths P.E. 2001. Philos. Sci. 68: 394–412). However, the criteria for being an inheritance system are demanding, so semantic properties are not ubiquitous.

Key words

Genetic information Genetic representation Inheritance systems Ontogenetic and phylogenetic explanation Teleosemantics 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Alberts B., Bray D., et al. (2004) Essential Cell Biology. Garland Science, New York & AbingdonGoogle Scholar
  2. Dennett D.C. (1981) True believers: the intentional strategy and why it works. In: Heath A.F. (ed.) Scientific Explanation. O.U.P., OxfordGoogle Scholar
  3. Dretske F. (1981) Knowledge and the Flow of Information. MIT Press, Cambridge, M.AGoogle Scholar
  4. Field H. (1978) Mental representation. Erkenntnis 13: 9–61CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Flatt T. (2005) The evolutionary genetics of canalization. Quart. Rev. Biol. 80(3): 287–316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Godfrey-Smith P. (1991) Signal, decision, action. J. Philos. 88: 709–722CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Godfrey-Smith P. (1993) Functions: consensus without unity. Pacific Philos. Quart. 74: 196–208Google Scholar
  8. Godfrey-Smith P. (1999) Genes and codes: lessons from the philosophy of mind. In: Hardcastle V. (ed.) Where Biology Meets Psychology: Philosophical Essays. MIT Press, London/Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  9. Godfrey-Smith P. (2000a) Information, arbitrariness and selection. Philos. Sci. 67: 202–207CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Godfrey-Smith P. (2000b) On the theoretical role of “genetic coding”. Philos. Sci. 67: 26–44CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Godfrey-Smith P. (2002) On genetic information and genetic coding In: Gardenfors P., Wolenski J., Kajania-Placek K. (eds) In the Scope of Logic, Methodology, and the Philosophy of Science, Vol. II. Kluwer, Dordrecht. pp. 387–400Google Scholar
  12. Godfrey-Smith P. (2006) Information in biology. In: Hull D., Ruse M. (eds) The Cambridge Companion to the Philosophy of Biology. CUP, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  13. Grice P. (1957) Meaning. Philos. Rev. 66: 377–388CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Griffiths P.E. (1993) Functional analysis and proper functions. Brit. J. Philos. Sci. 44: 409–422CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Griffiths P.E. (2001) Genetic information: a metaphor in search of a theory. Philos. Sci. 68: 394–412CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Griffiths P.E. (2005) The fearless vampire conservator: Philip Kitcher, genetic determinism and the informational gene. In: Neumann-Held E.M., Rehmann-Sutter C. (eds) Genes in Development: Re-reading the Molecular Paradigm. Duke University Press, Durham, NCGoogle Scholar
  17. Griffiths P.E., Gray R.D. (2005) Discussion: three ways to misunderstand developmental systems theory. Biol. Philos. 20: 417–425CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Jablonka E. (2002) Information: its interpretation, its inheritance, and its sharing. Philos. Sci. 69: 578–605CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Jablonka E., Lamb M.J. (1995) Epigenetic Inheritance and Evolution: The Lamarkian Dimension. OUP, Oxford/New YorkGoogle Scholar
  20. Jablonka E., Lamb M.J. (2005) Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. MIT Press, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  21. Lehrman D.S. (1970) Semantic and conceptual issues in the nature-nurture problem. In: Lehrman D.S. (ed.) Development & Evolution of Behaviour. W. H. Freeman, & Co, San Francisco pp 17–52Google Scholar
  22. Lewontin R. (1978) Adaptation. Sci. Am. 239: 156–169CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Maclaurin, J. 2002. The resurrection of innateness. Monist 85(1): 105–130Google Scholar
  24. Mameli M. (2005) The inheritance of features. Biol. Philos. 20: 365–399CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Maynard Smith J. (2000) The concept of information in biology. Philos. Sci. 67: 177–194CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Maynard Smith J., Szathmáry E. (1995) The Major Transitions in Evolution. Freeman, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  27. Millikan R.G. (1996) Pushmi-pullyu representations. In: Tomberlin J. (ed.) Philosophical Perspectives, Vol. 9. Ridgeview Publishing, Atascadero, CA pp 185–200Google Scholar
  28. Millikan R.G. (2000) On Clear and Confused Ideas. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  29. Millikan R.G. (2004) Varieties of Meaning. MIT Press, London/Cambridge MAGoogle Scholar
  30. Moss L. (2001) Deconstructing the gene and reconstructing molecular developmental systems. In: Oyama S., Griffiths P.E., Gray R.D. (eds) Cycles of Contingency: Developmental Systems and Evolution. MIT Press, London/Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  31. Moss L. (2003) What Genes Can’t Do. MIT Press, London, Cambridge, MAGoogle Scholar
  32. Oyama S. (1985) The Ontogeny of Information: Developmental Systems and Evolution. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  33. Papineau D. (2003) Is representation rife? Ratio 16: 107–123CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  34. Sarkar S. (2004) Genes encode information for phenotypic traits. In: Hitchcock C. (ed.) Contemporary Debates in Philosophy of Science. Oxford, Blackwell pp 259–274Google Scholar
  35. Schlosser G. and Wagner G.P. (eds) 2004. Modularity in Development and Evolution. University of Chicago Press, London/ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  36. Shannon C.E. (1949) The mathematical theory of communication. In: Shannon C.E., Weaver W. (eds) The Mathematical Theory of Communication. University of Illinois Press, UrbanaGoogle Scholar
  37. Shea N. 2007. Consumers need information: supplementing telesemantics with an input condition. Philos. Phenomen. Res. 75(2)Google Scholar
  38. Stegmann U.E. (2005) Genetic information as instructional content. Philos. Sci. 72(3): 425–443CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Sterelny K. (2000) The “genetic program” program: a commentary on Maynard Smith on information in biology. Philos. Sci. 67: 195–201CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Sterelny K. (2004) Symbiosis, evolvability, and modularity. In: Schlosser G., Wagner G.P. (eds) Modularity in Development and Evolution. University of Chicago Press, London/ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  41. Sterelny K., Smith K.C., Dickson M. (1996) The extended replicator. Biol. Philos. 11: 377–403CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Weaver W. 1949. Recent contributions to the mathematical theory of communication. In: Shannon C.E. and Weaver W. (eds), The Mathematical Theory of CommunicationGoogle Scholar
  43. Weber M. (2005) Philosophy of Experimental Biology. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge/New YorkGoogle Scholar
  44. Wheeler M. 2003. Do genes code for traits? In: Rojszczak A., Cachro J. and Kurczewski G. (eds), Philosophical Dimensions of Logic and Science: Selected Contributed Papers from the 11th International Congress of Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science. Dortrecht, Kluwer. Synthese Library 320: 151–164Google Scholar
  45. Wheeler M. Traits, genes and coding. In: Matthen M. and Stephens C. (eds.), Handbook of the Philosophy of Biology. Elsevier, London/Amsterdam, (in press)Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media, B.V. 2006

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Faculty of PhilosophyUniversity of OxfordOxfordUK

Personalised recommendations