Advertisement

Axiomathes

, Volume 27, Issue 6, pp 705–720 | Cite as

Uncoupling Mereology and Supervenience: A Dual Framework for Emergence and Downward Causation

  • Marta BertolasoEmail author
Original Paper
  • 113 Downloads

Abstract

The philosophical discussion of emergence is often focused on properties of ‘wholes’ that are evaluated as emergent with respect to the properties of ‘parts’. Downward causation is, consequently, evaluated as some kind of causal influence of whole properties over parts properties. Yet, several important cases in scientific practice seem to be pursuing hypotheses of parts properties emerging from wholes properties, inverting the instinctive association of emergence with wholes. Furthermore, some areas of reflection which are very important for emergence, e.g., the philosophy of consciousness, do not allow mapping properties onto part-whole organizations. The conceptual puzzle is solved by constructing a framework that disentangles the mereological dimension (parts–whole, micro–macro) from the superventional dimension (basal-supervenient). By liberalizing the spatio-temporal allocation of emergent properties, the proposed dual framework could better capture the way in which emergence and downward causation are addressed in scientific practice.

Keywords

Emergence Supervenience Reduction Explanation Scientific practice 

Notes

Acknowledgements

The author thanks very much two anonymous reviewers for their helpful suggestions. The author also thanks Sandy Mitchell, Marco Buzzoni, Anya Plutynski and Carl Craver for past exchanges on this topic and on an early version of this paper.

References

  1. Bechtel W, Richardson RC (1993) Discovering complexity: decomposition and localization as research strategies. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  2. Bedau M (1997) Weak emergence. In: Tomberlin J (ed) Philosophical perspectives: mind, causation, and world. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 375–399Google Scholar
  3. Bertolaso M (2016) Philosophy of cancer: a dynamic and relational view. Springer, BerlinCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bertolaso M, Buzzoni M (2016) Causality and levels of explanation in biology. In: Paoletti MP, Orilia F (eds) Philosophical and scientific perspectives on downward causation. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  5. Bertolaso M, Giuliani A, Filippi S (2013) The mesoscopic level and its epistemological relevance in systems biology. Recent advances in systems biology. Nova Science Publishers Inc, New York, pp 19–36Google Scholar
  6. Bissell MJ, Hall HG, Parry G (1982) How does the extracellular matrix direct gene expression? J Theor Biol 99(1):31–68CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Bissell MJ et al (2002) The organizing principle: microenvironmental influences in the normal and malignant breast. Differentiation 70(9–10):537–546CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Boogerd FC et al (2005) Emergence and its place in nature: a case study of biochemical networks. Synthese 145(1):131–164CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Broad CD (1925) The mind and its place in nature. Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co, LondonGoogle Scholar
  10. Corradini A (2008) Emergent dualism: why and how ? In: Antonietti A, Corradini A, Lowe EJ (eds) Psycho-physical dualism today: an interdisciplinary approach. Lexington, Lanham, pp 185–209Google Scholar
  11. Corradini A (2010) The emergence of mind: a dualistic understanding. In: Causality, meaningful complexity and embodied cognition. Springer, Dordrecht, pp 265–273Google Scholar
  12. Correia AL, Bissell MJ (2012) The tumor microenvironment is a dominant force in multidrug resistance. Drug Resist Updat 15(1–2):39–49CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Craver CF (2007) Explaining the brain: mechanisms and the mosaic unity of neuroscience. Clarendon Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Craver CF (2016) The explanatory power of network models. Philos Sci 83(5):698–709CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Craver CF, Bechtel W (2006) Top-down causation without top-down causes. Biol Philos 22(4):547–563CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Giuliani A (2010) Collective motions and specific effectors: a statistical mechanics perspective on biological regulation. BMC Genom 11(Suppl 1):S2CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Giuliani A (2014) Networks as a privileged way to develop mesoscopic level approaches in systems biology. Systems 2(2):237–242CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Glennan S (2010) Mechanisms, causes, and the layered model of the world. Philos Phenomenol Res 81(2):362–381CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. Gozzano S (2003) Second order properties: why Kim’s reduction does not work. Log Philos Sci 1(1):1–15Google Scholar
  20. Gozzano S (2009) Levels, orders and the causal status of mental properties. Eur J Philos 17(3):347–362CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Humphreys P (1997) Emergence, not supervenience. Philos Sci 64:S337–S345CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Humphreys P (2016) Emergence. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Hüttemann A, Papineau D (2005) Physicalism decomposed. Analysis (Oxford) 65(January):33–39CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Kim J (1999) Making sense of emergence. Philos Stud 95(1):3–36CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Kim J (2003) Blocking causal drainage and other maintenance chores with mental causation. Philos Phenomenol Res 67(1):151–176CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Kim J (2005) Physicalism, or something near enough. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  27. Kim J (2006) Emergence: core ideas and issues. Synthese 151(3):547–559CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Kostić D (2016) The topological realization. Synthese. doi: 10.1007/s11229-016-1248-0
  29. Laughlin RB et al (2000) The middle way. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 97(1):32–37CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Macdonald C, Macdonald G (2006) The metaphysics of mental causation. J Philos 103:539–576CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Malaterre C (2011) Making sense of downward causation in manipulationism: illustrations from cancer research. Hist Philos Life Sci 33:537–561Google Scholar
  32. Marras A (2006) Emergence and reduction: reply to Kim. Synthese 151(3):561–569CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Mayr E (1982) The growth of biological thought: diversity, evolution, and inheritance. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  34. Mitchell SD (2012) Emergence: logical, functional and dynamical. Synthese 185:171–186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Moreno A, Umerez J (2000) Downward causation at the core of living organization. In: Andersen PB et al (eds) Downward causation: minds, bodies and matter. Aarhus University Press, Oakville, pp 99–117Google Scholar
  36. Orilia F, Paoletti MP (2017) Three grades of downward causation. In: Philosophical and scientific perspectives on downward causation. RoutledgeGoogle Scholar
  37. Palumbo MC et al (2005) Functional essentiality from topology features in metabolic networks: a case study in yeast. FEBS Lett 579(21):4642–4646CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Palumbo MC et al (2007) Essentiality is an emergent property of metabolic network wiring. FEBS Lett 581(13):2485–2489CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Putnam H (1967) Psychological predicates. In: Capitan WH, Merrill DD (eds) Art, mind, and religion. University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh, pp 37–48Google Scholar
  40. Rueger A, McGivern P (2010) Hierarchies and levels of reality. Synthese 176(3):379–397CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Schaffer J (2003) Is there a fundamental level? Nous 37(3):498–517CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Schaffner KF (2006) Reduction: the Cheshire cat problem and a return to roots. Synthese 151(3):377–402CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Shoemaker S (2001) Realization and mental causation. In: Gillett C, Loewer B (eds) Physicalism and its discontents. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 74–98CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Shoemaker S (2007) Physical realization. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Sonnenschein C, Soto AM (1999) The society of cells: cancer and control of cell proliferation. Springer-Verlag Inc, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  46. Stephan A (1998) Varieties of emergence in artificial and natural systems. Z Naturforsch C 53:639–656Google Scholar
  47. Stephan A (2006) The dual role of “emergence” in the philosophy of mind and in cognitive science. Synthese 151(3):485–498CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Varzi A (2016) Mereology. The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2016/entries/mereology/. Accessed 17 June 2016
  49. Welshon R (2002) Emergence, supervenience, and realization. Philos Stud 108(1/2):39–51CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Wimsatt WC (2000) Emergence as non-aggregativity and the biases of reductionisms. Found Sci 5(3):269–297CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Yablo S (1992) Mental causation. Philos Rev 101:245–280CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Institute of Philosophy of Scientific and Technological Practice, Faculty of EngineeringUniversità Campus Bio-Medico di RomaRomeItaly

Personalised recommendations