Advertisement

Axiomathes

, Volume 21, Issue 1, pp 33–56 | Cite as

Physicalism, Emergence and Downward Causation

  • Richard J. Campbell
  • Mark H. Bickhard
Article

Abstract

The development of a defensible and fecund notion of emergence has been dogged by a number of threshold issues neatly highlighted in a recent paper by Jaegwon Kim. We argue that physicalist assumptions confuse and vitiate the whole project. In particular, his contention that emergence entails supervenience is contradicted by his own argument that the ‘microstructure’ of an object belongs to the whole object, not to its constituents. And his argument against the possibility of downward causation is question-begging and makes false assumptions about causal sufficiency. We argue, on the contrary, for a rejection of the deeply entrenched assumption, shared by physicalists and Cartesians alike, that what basically exists are things (entities, substances). Our best physics tells us that there are no basic particulars, only fields in process. We need an ontology which gives priority to organization, which is inherently relational. Reflection upon the fact that all biological creatures are far-from-equilibrium systems, whose very persistence depend upon their interactions with their environment, reveals incoherence in the notion of an ‘emergence base’.

Keywords

Physicalism Supervenience Emergence Reduction Processes Downward causation 

References

  1. Alexander S (1927) Space, time and deity, vol 2. Macmillan, LondonGoogle Scholar
  2. Bickhard MH (1993) Representational content in humans and machines. J Exp Theor Artif Intell 5:285–333CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Bickhard M (2009) The interactivist model. Synthese 166:547–591CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bickhard M, Campbell DT (2000) Emergence. In: Andersen PB, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO, Christiansen PV (eds) Downward causation. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus, pp 322–348Google Scholar
  5. Brown HR, Harré R (1988) Philosophical foundations of quantum field theory. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  6. Campbell DT (1974) Evolutionary epistemology. In: Schilpp PA (ed) The philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court, LaSalle, pp 413–463Google Scholar
  7. Campbell R (2009) A processed-based model for an interactive ontology. Synthese 166:453–477CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Cao TY (1999) Introduction: conceptual issues in quantum field theory. In: Cao TY (ed) Conceptual foundations of quantum field theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 1–27CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Davies P (1984) Particles do not exist. In: Christensen S (ed) Quantum theory of gravity. Adam Hilger, Bristol, pp 66–77Google Scholar
  10. Hansen CM (2000) Between a rock and a hard place: mental causation and the mind-body problem. Inquiry 43(4):451–491CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Kim J (1991) Epiphenomenal and supervenient causation. In: Rosenthal DM (ed) The nature of mind, pp 257–265Google Scholar
  12. Kim J (1998) Mind in a physical world. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  13. Kim J (2005) Physicalism or something near enough. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  14. Kim J (2006) Emergence: core ideas and issues. Synthese 151:547–559CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Marras A (2006) Emergence and reduction: reply to Kim. Synthese 151:561–569CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. McClelland D (1987) Human motivation. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  17. Moreno A, Umerez J (2000) Downward causation at the core of living organisms. In: Andersen PB, Emmeche C, Finnemann NO, Christiansen PV (eds) Downward causation. Aarhus University Press, Aarhus, pp 99–117Google Scholar
  18. Morgan CL (1923) Emergent evolution. Williams and Norgate, LondonGoogle Scholar
  19. Mourelatos APD (1978) Events, processes and states. Linguist Philos 2:415–434CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Roeper P (1987) Principles of abstraction for events and processes. J Philos Log 16:273–307CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Saunders S, Brown HR (eds) (1991) The philosophy of vacuum. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  22. Seibt J (2001) Formal process ontology. FOIS-2001 Proceedings, ACM Digital Publications, 2001Google Scholar
  23. Seibt J (2009) Forms of emergent interaction in general process theory. Synthese 166:479–512CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Taylor B (1977) Tense and continuity. Linguist Philos 1:199–220Google Scholar
  25. Teller P (1992) A contemporary look at emergence. In: Beckermann A, Flohr H, Kim J (eds) Emergence or reduction? Essays on the prospects of nonreductive physicalism Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 139–153Google Scholar
  26. Weinberg S (1977) The search for unity—notes for a history of quantum field theory. Daedalus 106:17–35Google Scholar
  27. Weinberg S (1995) The quantum theory of fields, vol I, foundations. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  28. Weinberg S (1996) The quantum theory of fields, vol 2, modern applications. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  29. Wimsatt WC (1986) Forms of aggregativity. In: Donagan A, Perovich A, Wedin M (eds) Human nature and human knowledge. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 259–291Google Scholar
  30. Wimsatt WC (1997) Aggregativity: reductive heuristics for finding emergence. Philos Sci 64:S372–S384. Reprinted in Bedau Mark A, Humphreys P (eds) Emergence—contemporary readings in philosophy and science. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 99–110Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2010

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.The Australian National UniversityCanberraAustralia
  2. 2.Lehigh UniversityBethlehemUSA

Personalised recommendations