Argumentation

, Volume 31, Issue 1, pp 165–177 | Cite as

Must a Successful Argument Convert an Ideal Audience?

Article
  • 322 Downloads

Abstract

Peter van Inwagen defines a successful argument in philosophy as one that can be used to convert an audience of ideal agnostics in an ideal debate. Sarah McGrath and Thomas Kelly recently argue that van Inwagen’s definition cannot be correct since the idea of ideal agnostics is incoherent with regard to an absolute paradigm of a successful philosophical argument. This paper defends van Inwagen’s definition against McGrath and Kelly’s objection.

Keywords

Argument Philosophy Ideal agnostics The epistemological approach Peter van Inwagen 

References

  1. Ballantyne, N. 2014a. Knockdown arguments. Erkenntnis 79: 525–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Ballantyne, N. 2014b. Counterfactual philosophers. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88(2): 368–387.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Brandt, R.B. 1955. The definition of an “ideal observer” theory in ethics. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 15(3): 407–413.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carson, T. 1984. The status of morality. Dordrecht: D. Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cherniak, C. 1986. Minimal rationality. Cambridge: MIT Press.Google Scholar
  6. Feldman, Richard. 1994. Good arguments. In Socializing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge, ed. Frederick F. Schmitt, 159–188. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  7. Firth, R. 1952. Ethical absolutism and the ideal observer. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 12(3): 317–345.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Fischer, J.M., and N.A. Tognazzini. 2007. Exploring evil and philosophical failure. Faith and Philosophy 24(4): 458–474.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Goldman, Alvin I. 1999. Knowledge in a social world. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Hanna, H. 2015. Philosophical success. Philosophical Studies 172(8): 2109–2121.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Hare, R.M. 1981. Moral thinking. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Lumer, Christoph. 1991. Structure and function of argumentations. An epistemological approach to determining criteria for the validity and adequacy of argumentations. In Proceedings of the second international conference on argumentation, ed. Frans H. van Eemeren, et al., 98–107. Amsterdam: Sicsat.Google Scholar
  13. Lumer, C. 2005a. The epistemological approach to argumentation—A map. Informal Logic 25(3): 189–212.Google Scholar
  14. Lumer, C. 2005b. The epistemological theory of argument: How and why? Informal Logic 25(3): 214–232.Google Scholar
  15. McGrath, S. 2010. Moral realism without convergence. Philosophical Topics 38(2): 59–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. McGrath, S., and Kelly, T. forthcoming. Are there any successful philosophical arguments? In Being, Freedom, and Method: Themes from van Inwagen, ed. John Keller, Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  17. Plato. 1997. In Complete works. eds. Cooper, J.M., and Hutchinson, D.S. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  18. Pojman, L. 2005. A defense of the death penalty. In contemporary debates in applied ethics, ed. Andrew Cohen, and Christopher Wellman, 107–123. Hoboken: Blackwell Publishing.Google Scholar
  19. Siegel, H. 1997. Rationality redeemed?: Further dialogues on an educational ideal. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  20. van Inwagen, P. 2006. The problem of evil. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Nanjing UniversityNanjingChina

Personalised recommendations