Argumentation

, Volume 27, Issue 4, pp 369–401 | Cite as

Strategies of Character Attack

Article

Abstract

Why are personal attacks so powerful? In political debates, speeches, discussions and campaigns, negative character judgments, aggressive charges and charged epithets are used for different purposes. They can block the dialogue, trigger value judgments and influence decisions; they can force the interlocutor to withdraw a viewpoint or undermine his arguments. Personal attacks are not only multifaceted dialogical moves, but also complex argumentative strategies. They can be considered as premises for further arguments based on signs, generalizations or consequences. They involve tactics for arousing emotions such as fear, hate or contempt, or for ridiculing the interlocutor. The twofold level of investigation presented in this paper is aimed at distinguishing the different roles that ad hominem have in a dialogue and bringing to light their hidden dimensions. The reasoning structure of each type of attack will be distinguished from the tactics used to increase its effectiveness and conceal its weaknesses.

Keywords

Fallacies Ad hominem Character attack Emotive words Emotions Fear Pity Undercutter Argument from consequences Values Political discourse 

References

  1. Aristotle. 1984a. Topica. In The works of Aristotle, ed. J. Barnes (trans: Pickard-Cambridge W. A.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  2. Aristotle 1984b. Rhetorica. In The works of Aristotle, ed. J. Barnes (trans: Rhys Roberts, W.). Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Battaly, H. 2010. Attacking character: Ad hominem argument and virtue epistemology. Informal logic 30(4): 361–390.Google Scholar
  4. Ben-Ze’ev, A. 2000. The subtlety of emotions. Cambridge: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  5. Blanchette, I. 2006. The effect of emotion on interpretation and logic in a conditional reasoning task. Memory and cognition 34: 1112–1125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Blanchette, I., and A. Richards. 2004. Reasoning about emotional and neutral materials: Is logic affected by emotion? Psychological Science 15: 745–752.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Cantrell, C. 2003. Prosecutorial misconduct: recognizing errors in closing argument. American Journal of trial advocacy 26: 535–562.Google Scholar
  8. Cicero, M.T. 1977. In Catilinam I-IV; Pro Murena; Pro Sulla; Pro Flacco. (trans MacDonald, C.). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  9. Doerksen, S., and A. Shimamura. 2001. Source memory enhancement for emotional words. Emotion 1(1): 5–11.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Dumas, A. 2001. The whites and the blues. (trans: Morlock, F.). Amsterdam: Fredonia Books.Google Scholar
  11. Grice, P. 1975. Logic and conversation. In Syntax and semantics 3: Speech acts, ed. P. Cole and J. Morgan, 41–58. New York: Academic Press.Google Scholar
  12. Groarke, L. 2011. Emotional arguments: ancient and contemporary views. In Proceedings of the seventh conference of the international society for the study of argumentation, ed. van Eemeren F.H., B.J. Garssen, D. Godden, and G. Mitchell, Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat. CD-ROM.Google Scholar
  13. Hitchcock, D. 2007. Why there is no argumentum ad hominem fallacy. In Proceedings of the sixth conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, J.A. Blair, C.A. Willard, and B. Garssen, 615–620. Amsterdam: Sic Sat.Google Scholar
  14. Holdgraves, T. 2008. Language as social action. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.Google Scholar
  15. Johnstone Jr, H.W. 1996. Lock and Whately on the argumentum ad hominem. Argumentation 10: 89–97.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kauffeld, F. 1998. Presumptions and the distribution of argumentative burdens in acts of proposing and accusing. Argumentation 12: 245–266.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Krabbe, E. 2003. Metadialogues. In Anyone who has a view: Theoretical contributions to the study of argumentation, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, J.A. Blair, ChA Willard, and A.F. Snoeck Henkemans, 83–90. Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. LaFave, L., J. Haddad, and W.A. Maesen. 1976. Superiority, enhanced self-esteem, and perceived incongruity humour theory. In Humor and laughter: Theory, research, and applications, ed. A.J. Chapman and H.C. Foot, 63–91. London: John Wiley & Sons.Google Scholar
  19. Levinson, S. 1992. Activity types and language. In Talk at work: Interaction in institutional settings, ed. P. Drew, and J. Heritage, 66–100. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  20. Macagno, F., and D. Walton. 2009. Argument from analogy in law, the classical tradition, and recent theories. Philosophy and rhetoric 42(2): 154–182.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Macagno, F., and D. Walton. 2010a. The argumentative uses of emotive language. Revista Iberoamericana de Argumentación 1: 1–37.Google Scholar
  22. Macagno, F., and D. Walton. 2010b. What we hide in words: Emotive words and persuasive definitions. Journal of Pragmatics 42: 1997–2013.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Manzoni, A. 2007. I promessi sposi, the Betrothed. New York: Wildside Press.Google Scholar
  24. Meyer, J. 2000. Humor as a double-edged sword: four functions of humor in communication. Communication theory 10(3): 310–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Perelman, C., and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca. 1951. Act and person in argument. Ethics 61(4): 251–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Pollock, J.L. 1974. Knowledge and justification. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  27. Rigotti, E. 2006. Relevance of context-bound loci to topical potential in the argumentation stage. Argumentation 20: 519–540.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Rigotti, E., and S. Cigada. 2004. La comunicazione verbale. Milano: Apogeo.Google Scholar
  29. Rigotti, E., and A. Rocci. 2006. Towards a definition of communication context. Foundations of an interdisciplinary approach to communication. Studies in communication sciences 6(2): 155–180.Google Scholar
  30. Rocci A. 2005. Connective predicates in dialogic and monologic argumentation. In Argumentation in dialogic interaction. Studies in communication sciences, Special issue eds. M. Dascal, F.H. van Eemeren, E. Rigotti, S. Stati, and A. Rocci, 97–118.Google Scholar
  31. Smith, C., and B. Voth. 2002. The role of humor in political argument: How “Strategery” and “Lockboxes” changed a political campaign. Argumentation and advocacy 39: 110–129.Google Scholar
  32. Van Eemeren, F.H. 2010. Strategic maneuvering in argumentative discourse. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.Google Scholar
  33. Van Eemeren, F.H., and R. Grootendorst. 1995. Argumentum ad hominem: A pragma-dialectical case in point. In Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings, ed. H.V. Hansen, and R.C. Pinto, 223–228. University Park: Penn State Press.Google Scholar
  34. Van Eemeren, F.H., and P. Houtlosser. 2005. Theoretical construction and argumentative reality: An analytic model of critical discussion and conventionalised types of argumentative activity. In The uses of argument. Proceedings of a conference at McMaster University, ed. D. Hitchcock and D. Farr, 75–84. Hamilton, ON: OSSA.Google Scholar
  35. Van Eemeren, F.H., B. Meuffels, and M. Verburg. 2000. The (un)reasonableness of ad hominem fallacies. Journal of language and social psychology 19: 419–435.Google Scholar
  36. Vanderveken, D. 1990. Meaning and speech acts. Vols. I and II.. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  37. Walton, D. 1995. A pragmatic theory of fallacy. Tuscaloosa, London: The University of Alabama Press.Google Scholar
  38. Walton, D. 1997. Appeal to pity. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  39. Walton, D. 1998a. Ad hominem arguments. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.Google Scholar
  40. Walton, D. 1998b. The new dialectic. Conversational contexts of argument. Toronto: University of Toronto Press.Google Scholar
  41. Walton, D. 2001. Searching for the roots of the circumstantial ad hominem. Argumentation 15: 207–221.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Walton, D. 2002. Legal argumentation and evidence. University Park, PA: The Pennsylvania State University Press.Google Scholar
  43. Walton, D., and E. Krabbe. 1995. Commitment in dialogue. Albany: State University of New York Press.Google Scholar
  44. Walton, D., C. Reed, and F. Macagno. 2008. Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  45. Whately, R. 1975. Elements of logic. Delmar, NY: Scholars Facsimiles and Reprints.Google Scholar
  46. Zarefsky, D., C. Miller-Tutzaur, and F. Titzuar. 1984. Reagan’s safety net for the truly needy: the rhetorical uses of definition. Central states speech 35: 113–119.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2013

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.ArgLab, Instituto de Filosofia da Linguagem (IFL)Universidade Nova de LisboaLisbonPortugal

Personalised recommendations