Argumentation

, Volume 26, Issue 4, pp 489–503 | Cite as

Regress Argument Reconstruction

Article

Abstract

If an argument can be reconstructed in at least two different ways, then which reconstruction is to be preferred? In this paper I address this problem of argument reconstruction in terms of Ryle’s infinite regress argument against the view that knowledge-how requires knowledge-that. First, I demonstrate that Ryle’s initial statement of the argument does not fix its reconstruction as it admits two, structurally different reconstructions. On the basis of this case and infinite regress arguments generally, I defend a revisionary take on argument reconstruction: argument reconstruction is mainly to be ruled by charity (viz. by general criteria which arguments have to fulfil in order to be good arguments) rather than interpretation.

Keywords

Infinite regress Argument Reconstruction Charity Interpretation 

References

  1. Armstrong, D.M. 1974. Infinite regress arguments and the problem of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 52: 191–201.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Beth, E.W. 1952. The prehistory of research into foundations. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 3: 58–81.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Black, O. 1996. Infinite regress arguments and infinite regresses. Acta Analytica 16: 95–124.Google Scholar
  4. Carroll, L. 1895. What the tortoise said to Achilles. Mind 4: 278–280.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Clark, R. 1988. Vicious infinite regress arguments. Philosophical Perspectives 2: 369–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Day, T.J. 1986. Infinite regress arguments. Some metaphysical and epistemological problems. PhD dissertation, Indiana University.Google Scholar
  7. Day, T.J. 1987. Infinite regress arguments. Philosophical Papers 16: 155–164.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Fantle, J. 2011. Ryle’s regress defended. Philosophical Studies 156: 121–130.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Feldman, R. 1993. Reason and argument (2nd ed. 1999). Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  10. Gettier, E.L. 1965. Review of Passmore’s Philosophical reasoning. Philosophical Review 2: 266–269.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gillett, C. 2003. Infinitism redux? A response to Klein. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66: 709–717.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Gratton, C. 1997. What is an infinite regress argument? Informal Logic 18: 203–224.Google Scholar
  13. Gratton, C. 2010. Infinite regress arguments. Dordrecht: Springer.Google Scholar
  14. Hetherington, S. 2006. How to know (that knowledge-that is knowledge-how). In Epistemology futures, ed. S. Hetherington, 71–94. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  15. Jacquette, D. 1996. Adversus adversus regressum (against infinite regress objections). Journal of Speculative Philosophy 10: 92–104.Google Scholar
  16. Johnson, O. 1978. Cartesian demonology revived. In Skepticism and cognitivism (ch. 3). Berkeley: CUP.Google Scholar
  17. Johnson, R.H. 2000. Manifest rationality. A pragmatic theory of argument. Mahwah: LEA.Google Scholar
  18. Johnstone H.W. Jr. 1996. The rejection of infinite postponement as a philosophical argument. Journal of Speculative Philosophy 10: 92–104.Google Scholar
  19. Juvenal 1st–2nd century CE. 1992. The Satires. (trans: Rudd, N.). Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  20. Klein, P.D. 1999. Human knowledge and the infinite regress of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives 13: 297–325.Google Scholar
  21. Klein, P.D. 2003. When infinite regresses are not vicious. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 66: 718–729.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Maurin, A.-S. 2007. Infinite regress: Virtue or vice? In Hommage à Wlodek, ed. T. Rønnow-Rasmussen et al., 1–26. Lund University.Google Scholar
  23. Nolan, D. 2001. What’s wrong with infinite regresses? Metaphilosophy 32: 523–538.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Paglieri, F. 2007. No more charity, please! Enthymematic parsimony and the pitfall of benevolence. In Dissensus and the search for common ground, ed. H.V. Hansen, et al. Windsor, ON: OSSA.Google Scholar
  25. Passmore, J. 1961. Philosophical reasoning (2nd ed. 1970). New York: Scribner’s Sons.Google Scholar
  26. Peijnenburg, J. 2010. Ineffectual foundations. Mind 119: 1125–1133.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Peijnenburg, J. 2011. Epistemic foundationalism and Aristotle’s principle of the absolute. In ISSA 2010 proceedings, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, et al., 1496–1503. Amsterdam: Sit Sat.Google Scholar
  28. Rankin, K.W. 1969. The duplicity of Plato’s third man. Mind 78: 178–197.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  29. Rescher, N. 1964. Introduction to logic. New York: St. Martin.Google Scholar
  30. Rescher, N. 2010. Infinite regress. The theory and history of a prominent mode of philosophical argumentation. New Brunswick: Transaction.Google Scholar
  31. Rosenberg, J.F. 1978. Infinite regress. In The practice of philosophy, 69–73. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.Google Scholar
  32. Ruben, D.-H. 1990. Mill and Hempel on explanation. In Explaining explanation (ch. 4). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  33. Russell, B. 1903. The objectionable and the innocent kind of endless regress. In The principles of mathematics (2nd ed. 1937, §329). London: Allen & Unwin.Google Scholar
  34. Ryle, G. 1945. Knowing how and knowing that. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 46: 1–16.Google Scholar
  35. Ryle, G. 1949. The concept of mind. Chicago: UCP.Google Scholar
  36. Sanford, D.H. 1984. Infinite regress arguments. In Principles of philosophical reasoning, ed. J.H. Fetzer, 93–117. Totowa: Rowman & Allanheld.Google Scholar
  37. Schlesinger, G.N. 1983. Induction, infinite regresses, the uniformity of nature and the intelligibility of nature. In Metaphysics. Methods and problems (ch. 8). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  38. Sextus Empiricus 160–210 CE. 1996. Outlines of Pyrrhonism (trans: Mates, B.) In The skeptic way. Oxford: OUP.Google Scholar
  39. Sider, T. 1995. Sorensen on unknowable obligations. Utilitas 7: 273–279.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Sorensen, R. 1995. Unknowable obligations. Utilitas 7: 247–271.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Stanley, J., and T. Williamson. 2001. Knowing how. Journal of Philosophy 98: 411–444.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Walton, D.N. 1996. Argument structure. A pragmatic theory. Toronto: UTP.Google Scholar
  43. Walton, D.N., and C.A. Reed. 2005. Argumentation schemes and enthymemes. Synthese 145: 339–370.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Wieland, J.W. 2011. Proto-regress argument schemas. In ISSA 2010 proceedings, ed. F.H. van Eemeren, et al., 2000–2007. Amsterdam: Sit Sat.Google Scholar
  45. Wieland, J.W. ms. And so on. Two theories of regress arguments in philosophy. PhD dissertation, Ghent University.Google Scholar
  46. Wilson, N.L. 1959. Substances without substrata. Review of Metaphysics 12: 521–539.Google Scholar
  47. Williams, J.N. 2008. Propositional knowledge and know-how. Synthese 165: 107–125.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  48. Yalden-Thomson, D.C. 1964. Remarks about philosophical refutations. Monist 48: 501–512.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2012

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Centre for Logic & Philosophy of ScienceGhent UniversityGhentBelgium

Personalised recommendations