On Scott-Phillips’ General Account of Communication

Regular Article

Abstract

The purpose of this paper is to critically engage with a recent attempt by Thom Scott-Phillips to offer a general account of communication. As a general account, it is intended to apply equally well to both non-human and human interactions which are prima facie communicative in character. However, so far, Scott-Phillips has provided little detail regarding how his account is supposed to apply to the latter set of cases. After presenting what I take to be the most plausible way of filling in those details, I argue that his account would appear to be too narrow: it (minimally) fails to capture a range of human interactions which strike us as instances of communication. To wit, these are cases in which some but not all of the information an act is designed to convey to a reactor actually reaches that reactor. An alternative account incorporating Scott-Phillips’ main insights is then sketched, and it is suggested that this account, or something like it, would accommodate the full range of non-human and human interactions that are intuitively communicative.

Keywords

Communication Function Information Coercion Cue Ostensive communication Partial communication 

References

  1. Bratman ME (1989) Intention and personal policies. Philos Perspect 3:443–469CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  2. Cappelen H, Lepore E (2007) Relevance theory and shared content. In: Burton-Roberts N (ed) Pragmatics. Palgrave-Macmillan, Basingstoke, pp 115–135Google Scholar
  3. Csibra G (2010) Recognizing communicative intentions in infancy. Mind Lang 25(2):141–168CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Gillies MT (1980) The role of carbon dioxide in host-finding by mosquitoes (Diptera: Culicidae): a review. Bull Entomol Res 70(04):525–532CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Grice HP (1957) Meaning. Philos Rev 66:377–388CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Grosse G, Behne T, Carenter M, Tomasello M (2010) Infants communicate in order to be understood. Dev Psychol 46(6):1710–1722CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Hailman JP (1977) Optical signals: animal communication and light. Indiana University Press, BloomingtonGoogle Scholar
  8. Herzog M, Hopf Sigrid (1984) Behavioral responses to species-specific warning calls in infant squirrel monkeys reared in social isolation. Am J Primatol 7(2):99–106CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Kimura D (1993) Neuromotor mechanisms in human communication. Clarendon Press/Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Lewis D (1969) Convention. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  11. Moore R (2016) Meaning and ostension in great ape gestural communication. Anim Cogn 19(1):223–231CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Origgi G, Sperber D (2000) Evolution, communication and the proper function of language. In: Carruthers P, Chamberlain A (eds) Evolution and the human mind: language, modularity and social cognition. Cambridge University Press, pp 140–169Google Scholar
  13. Russon A, Andrews K (2010) Orangutan pantomime: elaborating the message. Biol Lett 7(4):627–630Google Scholar
  14. Scott-Phillips T (2008) Defining biological communication. J Evol Biol 21(2):387–395CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Scott-Phillips T (2014) Speaking our minds: why human communication is different, and how language evolved to make it special. Palgrave MacMillan, BasingstokeGoogle Scholar
  16. Scott-Phillips T (2015) Nonhuman primate communication, pragmatics, and the origins of language. Curr Anthropol 56(1):56–80CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Scott-Phillips T (2017) Pragmatics and the aims of language evolution. Psychon Bull Rev 24:1–4CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Scott-Phillips TC, Kirby S (2013) Information, influence and inference in language evolution. In: Stegmann UE (ed) Animal communication theory information and influence. Cambridge University Press, pp 421–442. doi:10.1017/CBO9781139003551.025
  19. Searle J (1985) Intentionality. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  20. Shwe HI, Markman EM (1997) Young children’s appreciation of the mental impact of their communicative signals. Dev Psychol 33(4):630–663CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Skyrms B (2010) Signals: evolution, learning, and information. Oxford University Press, OxfordCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Smith WJ (1980) The behavior of communicating. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  23. Smith JM, Harper D (2003) Animal signals. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  24. Sperber D, Wilson D (1986) Relevance: communication and cognition. Blackwell Publishers, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  25. Sperber D, Wilson D (1987) Precis of relevance: communication and cognition. Behav Brain Sci 10(04):697CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Sperber D, Wilson D (1995) Relevance: communication and cognition, 2nd edn. Blackwell Publishers, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  27. Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of wiley-human cognition. Wiley-Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  28. Tomasello M (2008) Origins of human communication. MIT press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.School of PhilosophyThe Australian National UniversityCanberraAustralia

Personalised recommendations