Acta Biotheoretica

, Volume 57, Issue 1–2, pp 33–49 | Cite as

Species as a Process

Regular Article

Abstract

Species are generally considered to be the basic units of evolution, and hence to constitute spatio-temporally bounded entities. In addition, it has been argued that species also instantiate a natural kind. Evolution is fundamentally about change. The question then is how species can remain the same through evolutionary change. Proponents of the species qua individuals thesis individuate species through their unique evolutionary origin. Individuals, or spatio-temporally located particulars in general, can be bodies, objects, events, or processes, or a combination of these. It is here argued that species are best understood as open or closed, causally integrated processual systems that also instantiate an historically conditioned homeostatic property cluster natural kind.

Keywords

Species Systems Presentism Eternalism Endurance Perdurance Futuralism 

Notes

Acknowledgments

I thank Rasmus Winther, Francisco Vergara-Silva, and Ingo Brigandt who read an earlier draft of this paper, offering much helpful advice and criticism.

References

  1. Arnold ML (1997) Natural hybridization and evolution. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  2. Avise JC (2000) Phylogeography. The history and formation of species. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  3. Barnes I, Matheus P, Shapiro B, Jensen D, Cooper A (2002) Dynamics of Pleistocene population extinctions in Beringian brown bears. Science 295:2267–2270. doi: 10.1126/science.1067814 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Bertalanffy L (1932) Theoretische Biologie Band I. Gebr. Bornträger, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  5. Bertalanffy L (1941) Die organismische Auffassung und ihre Auswirkungen. Der Biologe 10(247–258):337–345Google Scholar
  6. Bonnet C (1762) Considérations sur les Corps Organisés. Marc Michel Rey, AmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  7. Bonnet Ch (1769-1770) La Palingénésie Philosophique, ou Idées sur l’Etat Passé et sur l’Etat Future des Etres Vivans. Claude Philibert & Barthelemi Chirol, GenevaGoogle Scholar
  8. Bowler PJ (1973) Bonnet and Buffon: theories of generation and the problem of species. J Hist Biol 6:259–281. doi: 10.1007/BF00127610 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Bowler PJ (1975) The changing meaning of ‘evolution’. J Hist Ideas 36:95–114. doi: 10.2307/2709013 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Boyd R (1991) Realism, anti-fondationalism and the enthusiasm for natural kinds. Philos Stud 61:127–148. doi: 10.1007/BF00385837 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Boyd R (1999) Homeostasis, species, and higher taxa. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 141–185Google Scholar
  12. Bredekamp H (2005) Darwins Korallen. Frühe Evolutionsmodelle und die Tradition der Naturgeschichte. Wagenbach, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  13. Brogaard B (2004) Species as individuals. Biol Philos 19:223–242. doi: 10.1023/B:BIPH.0000024322.46358.61 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  14. Claridge MF, Dawah HA, Wilson MR (1997) Species. The units of biodiversity. Chapman and Hall, LondonGoogle Scholar
  15. Coleman KA, Wiley EO (2001) On species individualism: a new defense of the species-as-individuals hypothesis. Philos Sci 68:498–517. doi: 10.1086/392939 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Coyne JA, Orr HA (2004) Speciation. Sinauer, SunderlandGoogle Scholar
  17. Crane JK (2004) On the metaphysics of species. Philos Sci 71:156–173. doi: 10.1086/383009 CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Crisp TM (2003) Presentism. In: Loux MJ, Zimmerman DW (eds) The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 211–245Google Scholar
  19. Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species. John Murray, LondonGoogle Scholar
  20. de Queiroz K (1999) The general lineage concept of species and the defining properties of the species category. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 49–89Google Scholar
  21. de Queiroz K (2005) A unified concept of species and its consequences for the future of taxonomy. Proc Calif Acad Sci 56(suppl 1):186–215Google Scholar
  22. Dunning Hotopp JC, Clark ME, Oliveira DCSG, Foster JM, Fischer P, Munoz Torres MC, Giebel JD, Kumar N, Ishmael N, Wang S, Ingram J, Nene RV, Shepard J, Tomkins J, Richards S, Spiro DJ, Ghedin E, Slatko BE, Tettelin H, Werren JH (2007) Widespread lateral gene transfer from intracellular bacteria to multicellular eukaryotes. Science 317:1753–1756CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Eldredge N, Thompson JN, Brakefield PM, Gavrilets S, Jablonski D, Jackson JB, Lenski RE, Lieberman BS, McPeek MA, Miller WIII (2005) The dynamics of evolutionary stasis. Paleobiology 31:133–145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Ereshefsky M (1999) Species and the Linnean hierarchy. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 285–306Google Scholar
  25. Farber PL (1972) Buffon and the concept of species. J Hist Biol 5:259–284CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Foote M, Cowie RH (1988) Developmental buffering as a mechanism for stasis: evidence from the pulmonate Theba pisana. Evolution 42:396–399CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Gallois A (2005) Identity over time. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, Spring 2005 edn. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2005/entries/identity-time/
  28. Gavrilets S (2003) Models of speciation: what have we learned in 40 years. Evolution 57:2197–2215Google Scholar
  29. Gayon J (1992) L’ individualité de l’espèce: une thèse transformiste? In: Gayon J (ed) Buffon 88: Actes du Colloque International Paris - Dijion - Montbard. Vrin, Paris, pp 475–489Google Scholar
  30. Gayon J (1996) The individuality of the species: a Darwinian theory?—from Buffon to Ghiselin, and back to Darwin. Biol Philos 11:215–244CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  31. Ghiselin MT (1966) On psychologism in the logic of taxonomic controversies. Syst Zool 15:207–215CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  32. Ghiselin M (1974) A radical solution to the species problem. Syst Zool 23:536–544CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Ghiselin M (1997) Metaphysics and the origin of species. SUNY, AlbanyGoogle Scholar
  34. Gogarten P, Townsend JP (2005) Horizontal gene transfer, genome innovation and evolution. Nat Rev Microbiol 3:679–687CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Grant PR, Grant BR (2002) Unpredictable evolution in a 30-year study of Darwin’s finches. Science 296:707–711CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  36. Grant PR, Grant BR, Markert JA, Keller LF, Petre K (2004) Convergent evolution of Darwin’s finches caused by introgressive hybridization and selection. Evolution 58:1588–1599Google Scholar
  37. Grene M (1990) Evolution, typology, and population thinking. Am Philos Quart 27:237–244Google Scholar
  38. Grene M (2002) Reply to David Hull. In: Auxier RE, Hahn LE (eds) The philosophy of Marjorie Grene. Open Court, La Salle, pp 279–283Google Scholar
  39. Griffiths PE (1999) Squaring the circle: natural kinds with historical essences. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 209–228Google Scholar
  40. Grube M, Kroken S (2000) Molecular approaches and the concept of species and species complexes in lichenized fungi. Mycol Res 104:1284–1294CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Hacking I (1991) On Boyd. Philos Stud 61:149–154CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Haller A (1758) Sur la Formation du Coeur dans le Poulet; sur l’Oeil; sur la Structure du Jaune &c Premier Mémoire. Marc-Michel Bousquet, LausanneGoogle Scholar
  43. Hartsoeker N (1694) Essai de Dioptrique. J Anisson, ParisGoogle Scholar
  44. Haslanger S (2003) Persistence through time. In: Loux MJ, Zimmerman DW (eds) The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 315–354Google Scholar
  45. Hendry AP, Vamosi SM, Latham SJ, Heilbuth JC, Day T (2000) Questioning species realities. Conserv Genet 1:67–76CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  46. Hennig W (1950) Grundzüge einer Theorie der Phylogenetischen Systematik. Deutscher Zentralverlag, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  47. Hennig W (1966) Phylogenetic systematics. University of Illinois Press, UrbanaGoogle Scholar
  48. Hey J (2001) Genes, categories and species. The evolutionary and cognitive causes of the species problem. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  49. Holloway AK, Cannatella DC, Gerghardt HC, Hillis DM (2006) Polyploids with different origins and ancestors form a single sexual polyploidy species. Am Nat 167:W88–E101CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  50. Hull DL (1976) Are species really individuals? Syst Zool 25:174–191CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  51. Hull DL (1988) Science as a process. An evolutionary account of the social and conceptual development of science. The University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  52. Hull DL (1989) The metaphysics of evolution. State University of New York Press, AlbanyGoogle Scholar
  53. Hull DL (1997) The ideal species concept–and why we can’t get it. In: Claridge MF, Dawah HA, Wilson MR (eds) Species: the units of biodiversity. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 357–380Google Scholar
  54. Hull DL (1999) On the plurality of species: questioning the party line. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 23–48Google Scholar
  55. Hull DL (2002a) A portrait of biology. In: Auxier RE, Hahn LE (eds) The philosophy of Marjorie Grene. Open Court, La Salle, pp 259–278Google Scholar
  56. Hull DL (2002b) Words about words about species. Evolution 56:426–428Google Scholar
  57. Jockusch EL, Wake DB (2002) Falling apart and merging: diversification of slender salamanders (Plethodontidae: Batrachoseps) in the American West. Biol J Linn Soc 76:361–391CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  58. Keller RA, Boyd RN, Wheeler QD (2003) The illogical basis of phylogenetic nomenclature. Bot Rev 69:93–110CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  59. Konstantinidis KT, Ramette A, Tiedje JM (2006) The bacterial species definition in the genomic era. Phil Trans R Soc Lond B361:1929–1940Google Scholar
  60. LaPorte J (2004) Natural kinds and conceptual change. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  61. Leibniz GW (1710) Essais de Théodicée. Isaak Troyrl, AmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  62. Levinton JS (1983) Stasis in progress: the empirical basis of macroevolution. Annu Rev Ecol Sys 14:103–137CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  63. Loux MJ (2003) Metaphysics. A contemporary introduction, 2nd edn. Routledge, LondonGoogle Scholar
  64. Lovejoy AO (1959) Buffon and the problem of species. In: Glass B, Temkin O, WKjr Strauss (eds) Forerunners of Darwin 1745–1859. The Johns Hopkins, Baltimore, pp 84–113Google Scholar
  65. Løvtrup S (1977) The phylogeny of vertebrata. Wiley, LondonGoogle Scholar
  66. Løvtrup S (1979) The evolutionary species: fact or fiction? Syst Zool 28:386–392CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Mahner M, Bunge M (1997) Foundations of biophilosophy. Springer, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  68. Marris E (2007) The species and the specious. Nature 446:250–253CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  69. Mayr E (1963) Animal species and evolution. The Belknap Press at Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  70. Mayr E (1982) The history of biological thought. The Belknap Press at Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  71. Millikan R (1999) Historical kinds and the “special sciences”. Philos Stud 95:45–65CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  72. Mishler BD (1999) Getting rid of species. In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 307–315Google Scholar
  73. Mortensen Ch (2006) Change. In: Zalta EN (ed) The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy Winter 2006 Ed URL <http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2006/entries/change/>
  74. Omland KE, Lanyon SM, Fritz SJ (1999) A molecular phylogeny of the New World orioles (Icterus): the importance of dense taxon sampling. Mol Phylo Evol 12:224–239CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  75. Otte D, Endler JA (1989) Speciation and its consequences. Sinauer, SunderlandGoogle Scholar
  76. Otto SP, Whitton J (2000) Polyploid incidence and evolution. Annu Rev Genet 34:401–437CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  77. Popper KR (1989) Conjectures and refutations. Routledge & Kegan Paul, LondonGoogle Scholar
  78. Purvis OW (1997) The species concept in lichens. In: Claridge MF, Dawah HA, Wilson MR (eds) Species: the units of biodiversity. Chapman & Hall, London, pp 109–134Google Scholar
  79. Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  80. Rea MC (2003) Four-dimensionalism. In: Loux MJ, Zimmerman DW (eds) The Oxford handbook of metaphysics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 246–280Google Scholar
  81. Rescher N (1996) Process metaphysics. An introduction to process philosophy. State University of New York Press, AlbanyGoogle Scholar
  82. Rescher N (2000) Process philosophy. A survey of basic issues. University of Pittsburgh Press, PittsburghGoogle Scholar
  83. Reydon TAC (2003) Discussion: species are individuals—or are they? Philos Sci 70:49–56CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  84. Rieppel O (1986a) Atomism, epigenesis, peformation and pre-existence: a clarification of terms and consequences. Biol J Linn Soc 28:331–341CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  85. Rieppel O (1986b) Der Artbegriff im Werk des Genfer Naturphilosophen Charles Bonnet (1720–1793). Gesnerus 43:205–212Google Scholar
  86. Rieppel O (1986c) Species are individuals: a review and critique of the argument. Evol Biol 20:283–317Google Scholar
  87. Rieppel O (1988) The reception of Leibniz’ philosophy in the writings of Charles Bonnet (1720–1793). J Hist Biol 21:119–145CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  88. Rieppel O (2001a) Charles Bonnet (1720–1793). In: Jahn J, Schmitt M (eds) Darwin & Co, vol 1. C.H. Beck, München, pp 51–78Google Scholar
  89. Rieppel O (2001b) Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon (1707–1788). In: Jahn J, Schmitt M (eds) Darwin & Co, vol 1. C.H. Beck, München, pp 31–50Google Scholar
  90. Rieppel O (2003) Semaphoronts, cladograms, and the roots of total evidence. Biol J Linn Soc 80:167–186CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  91. Rieppel O (2007a) Species: kinds of individuals or individuals of a kind. Cladistics 23:373–384CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  92. Rieppel O (2007b) The metaphysics of Hennig’s phylogenetic systematics: substance, events and laws of nature. Syst Biodivers 5:345–360CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  93. Rieseberg LH, Wood TE, Baack EJ (2006) The nature of plant species. Nature 440:524–527CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  94. Roger J (1971) Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée Française du XVIIIe siècle, 2nd edn. Armand Collin, ParisGoogle Scholar
  95. Ruse M (1998) All my love is towards individuals. Evolution 52:283–288CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  96. Sherburne DW (1966) A key to Whitehead’s process and reality. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  97. Sklar L (2006) Space, time, and relativity. In: Newton-Smith WH (ed) A companion to the philosophy of science. Blackwell, Malden, pp 461–469Google Scholar
  98. Stamos DN (1998) Buffon, Darwin, and the non-individuality of species—a reply to Jean Gayon. Biol Philos 13:443–470CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  99. Sterelny K (1994) The nature of species. Philos Books 35:9–20CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  100. Sucker U (1978) Philosophische Probleme der Arttheorie. Gustav Fischer, JenaGoogle Scholar
  101. Talbot SL, Shields GF (1996) A phylogeny of the bears (Ursidae) inferred from complete sequences of three mitochondrial genes. Mol Phylo Evol 5:567–575CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  102. Taylor K (1998) Truth & meaning. An introduction to the philosophy of language. Blackwell, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  103. Vermeij GJ, Dietl GP (2006) Majority rule: adaptation and the long-term dynamics of species. Paleobiology 32:173–178CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  104. Vrijrnhoek RC (2006) Polyploid hybrids: multiple origins of a treefrog species. Curr Biol 6:R245–R247CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  105. West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  106. Whiston W (1696) A new theory of the earth. Benjamin Tooke, LondonGoogle Scholar
  107. Whitehead AN (1920) The concept of nature. Tarner lectures delivered in Trinity College November 1919. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  108. Whitehead AN (1979) Process and reality. Free, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  109. Williamson PG (1987) Selection or constraint? A proposal on the mechanisms for stasis, pp. 129–142. In: Campbell KSW, Day MF (eds) Rates of evolution. Allen and Unwin, BostonGoogle Scholar
  110. Willmann R (1985) Die Art in Raum und Zeit Das Artkonzept in der Biologie und Paläontologie. Paul Parey, BerlinGoogle Scholar
  111. Wilson RA (1996) Discussion: promiscuous realism. Br J Philos Sci 47:303–316CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  112. Wilson RA (1999) Realism, essence, and kind: resuscitating species essentialism? In: Wilson RA (ed) Species new interdisciplinary essays. MIT, Cambridge, pp 187–207Google Scholar
  113. Woodger JH (1952) From biology to mathematics. Br J Philos Sci 3:1–21CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  114. Ziehen Th (1934) Erkenntnistheorie. Zweite Auflage. Erster Teil. Allgemeine Grundlegung der Erkennnistheorie. Spezielle Erkenntnistheorie der Empfindungstatsachen einschliesslich Raumtheorie. Gustav Fischer, JenaGoogle Scholar
  115. Ziehen Th (1939) Erkenntnistheorie. Zweite Auflage. Zweiter Teil. Zeittheorie. Wirklichkeitsproblem. Erkenntnistheorie der anorganischen Natur (erkenntnisheoretische Grundlagen der Physik) Kausalität. Gustav Fischer, JenaGoogle Scholar
  116. Zimmer C (2002) Darwin’s avian muses continue to evolve. Science 296:633–634CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of GeologyThe Field MuseumChicagoUSA

Personalised recommendations