Cognitive Processing

, Volume 7, Issue 1, pp 11–29 | Cite as

The biogenic approach to cognition

Review

Abstract

After half a century of cognitive revolution we remain far from agreement about what cognition is and what cognition does. It was once thought that these questions could wait until the data were in. Today there is a mountain of data, but no way of making sense of it. The time for tackling the fundamental issues has arrived. The biogenic approach to cognition is introduced not as a solution but as a means of approaching the issues. The traditional, and still predominant, methodological stance in cognitive inquiry is what I call the anthropogenic approach: assume human cognition as the paradigm and work ‘down’ to a more general explanatory concept. The biogenic approach, on the other hand, starts with the facts of biology as the basis for theorizing and works ‘up’ to the human case by asking psychological questions as if they were biological questions. Biogenic explanations of cognition are currently clustered around two main frameworks for understanding biology: self-organizing complex systems and autopoiesis. The paper describes the frameworks and infers from them ten empirical principles—the biogenic ‘family traits’—that constitute constraints on biogenic theorizing. Because the anthropogenic approach to cognition is not constrained empirically to the same degree, I argue that the biogenic approach is superior for approaching a general theory of cognition as a natural phenomenon.

Keywords

Cognition Theory Explanation Biology of cognition 

References

  1. Adler J, Tso W-W (1974) ’Decision’-making in bacteria: chemotactic response of Escherichia coli to conflicting stimuli. Science 184(4143):1292–2294PubMedGoogle Scholar
  2. Anolli L, Riva G et al (eds) (2005) The hidden structure of interaction: from neurons to culture patterns. Emerging communication: studies on new technologies and practices in communication. IOS Press, AmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  3. Atkinson N (2004) Insect policing carries costs. The Scientist, BioMed CentralGoogle Scholar
  4. Bak P (1996) How nature works: the science of self-organized criticality. Copernicus/Springer, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  5. Balazs A (2004) What does a molecule want? The myth of the self-replicating molecule (comments on the "selfish-gene" paradigm). Biosystems 73(1):1–11PubMedGoogle Scholar
  6. Barham J (1996) A dynamical model of the meaning of information. Biosystems 38(2–2):235–541PubMedGoogle Scholar
  7. Bateson G (1979) Mind and nature: a necessary unity. E.P. Dutton, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  8. Bechtel W (1998) Representations and cognitive explanations: assessing the dynamicist’s challenge in cognitive science. Cogn Sci 22(3):295–517Google Scholar
  9. Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A (1990) Beyond the exclusively propositional era. Synthese 82(2):223–353Google Scholar
  10. Bechtel W, Abrahamsen A et al. (1998) The life of cognitive science. In: Bechtel W, Graham G (eds) A companion to cognitive science. Blackwell, Malden, pp 1–104Google Scholar
  11. Beer RD (1990) Intelligence as adaptive behavior: an experiment in computational neuroethology. Academic, San DiegoGoogle Scholar
  12. Bickhard MH (1980) Cognition, convention, and communication. Praeger Publishers, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  13. Bickhard MH (1998) Levels of representationality. J Exp Theor Artif Intell 10(1998):179–915Google Scholar
  14. Bickhard MH, Terveen L (1995) Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science: impasse and solution. Elsevier, AmsterdamGoogle Scholar
  15. Bingham PM (2000) Human evolution and human history: a complete theory. Evol Anthropol: Issue News Rev 9(6):248–857Google Scholar
  16. Boden MA (ed) (1996). The philosophy of artificial life. Oxford Readings in Philosophy. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  17. Brier S (2000) Biosemiotics as a possible bridge between embodiment in cognitive semantics and the motivation concept of animal cognition in ethology. Cybernet Human Know 7(1):57–75Google Scholar
  18. Brooks R (1991) Intelligence without representation. Artif Intell 47(1–1):139–959Google Scholar
  19. Byrne RW, Barnard PJ et al. (2004) Understanding culture across species. Trends C Sc 8(8):341–146Google Scholar
  20. Cairns-Smith AG (1985) Seven clues to the origin of life. Cambridge University Press/Canto, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  21. Campbell DT (1974) Evolutionary epistemology. In: Schlipp PA (ed) The philosophy of Karl Popper. Open Court, La Salle, Ill., 1:413–363Google Scholar
  22. Chalmers DJ (1996) The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  23. Cherniak C (1986) Minimal rationality. MIT Press/Bradford, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  24. Chomsky N (1981) The case against B.F. Skinner. In: Bolles EB (ed) Galileo’s commandment. Abacus (Little, Brown and Company), London, pp 80–107Google Scholar
  25. Christensen WD (2004) Self-directedness: a process approach to cognition. Axiomathes 14:171–189Google Scholar
  26. Christensen WD, Hooker CA (2000) Autonomy and the emergence of intelligence: organized interactive construction. Commun Cogn Artif Intell 17(3/4):133–357Google Scholar
  27. Churchland PS (1987) Epistemology in the age of neuroscience. J Philos 84:544–455Google Scholar
  28. Churchland PM (1989) A neurocomputational perspective: the nature of mind and the structure of science. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  29. Clapin H, Staines P et al (eds) (2004) Representation in mind: new approaches to mental representation. Perspectives on cognitive science. Elsevier, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  30. Clark A (1997a) Being there: putting brain, body and world back together again. MIT Press/Bradford, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  31. Clark A (1997b) The dynamical challenge. Cogn Sci 21(4):461–181Google Scholar
  32. Cliff D, Noble J (1997) Knowledge-based vision and simple visual machines. Philos Trans: Biol Sci (R Soc Lond) 352:1165–5175Google Scholar
  33. Copeland BJ (1996) What is computation? Synthese 108(3):335–559Google Scholar
  34. Corning PA, Kline SJ (1998a) Thermodynamics, information and life revisited, Part I: ’To be or entropy’. Syst Res Be 15(4):273–395Google Scholar
  35. Corning PA, Kline SJ (1998b) Thermodynamics, information and life revisited, Part II: Thermoeconomics and control information. Syst Res Be 15(6):453–382Google Scholar
  36. Crane T (1998) Intentionality as the mark of the mental. In: O’Hear A (ed) Current issues in philosophy of mind. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 229–951Google Scholar
  37. Crist E (2002) The inner life of earthworms: Darwin’s argument and its implications. In: Bekoff M, Allen C, Burghardt G (eds) The cognitive animal: empirical and theoretical perspectives on animal cognition. MIT/Bradford Book, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  38. Damasio AR (1999) The feeling of what happens, body and emotion in the making of consciousness. Harcourt Brace & Company, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  39. Darwin C (1874/1909) The descent of man. Selection in relation to sex. John Murray, LondonGoogle Scholar
  40. de Waal FBM (2001) The ape and the sushi master. Cultural reflections by a primatologist, Allen Lane. The Penguin Press, LondonGoogle Scholar
  41. de Waal FBM (2002) Evolutionary psychology: the wheat from the chaff. Curr Directions Psychol Sci 11(6):187–791Google Scholar
  42. Deacon TW (1997) The symbolic species: the co-evolution of language and the brain. W. W. Norton & Company, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  43. Dennett DC (1989) Cognitive ethology: hunting for bargains or a wild goose chase? In: Montefiore A, Noble D (ed) Goals, no-goals and own goals. A debate on goal-directed and intentional behavior. Unwin Hyman, London, pp 101–116Google Scholar
  44. Dennett DC (1991) Consciousness explained. Penguin Books, LondonGoogle Scholar
  45. Dennett DC (1996) Kinds of minds. Towards an understanding of consciousness. Weidenfeld & Nicolson, LondonGoogle Scholar
  46. di Primio F, Müller BS et al. (2000) Minimal cognition in unicellular organisms. In: SAB 2000, sixth international conference on the simulation of adaptive behaviour, Paris, International Society for Adaptive BehaviourGoogle Scholar
  47. Dretske F (1988) Explaining behavior. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  48. Dretske F (2000) Perception, knowledge and belief: selected essays. Cambridge University press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  49. Dupuy J-P (2000) The mechanization of the mind: on the origins of cognitive science. Princeton University Press, PrincetonGoogle Scholar
  50. Eder J, Rembold H (1992) Biosemiotics—a paradigm of biology. Naturwissenschaften 79:60–107PubMedGoogle Scholar
  51. Eigen M, Schuster P (1979) The hypercycle: a principle of natural self-organization. Springer, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  52. Emmeche C (1998) Defining life as a semiotic phenomenon. Cybernet Human Know 5(1):3–37Google Scholar
  53. Fischer JH, Freake MJ et al (2001) Evidence for the use of magnetic map information by an amphibian. Anim Behav 62(1):1–10Google Scholar
  54. Fodor JA (1986) Why paramecia don’t have mental representations. Midwest Stud Philos X:3–33Google Scholar
  55. Freeman WJ (1999) How brains make up their minds. Phoenix Paperback, LondonGoogle Scholar
  56. Gardner H (1985) The mind’s new science: a history of the cognitive revolution. Basic Books, Inc., Publishers, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  57. Gibson JJ (1979) The ecological approach to visual perception. Houghton Mifflin, DallasGoogle Scholar
  58. Godfrey-Smith P (1996) Complexity and the function of mind in nature. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  59. Godfrey-Smith P (2003) Between Baldwin skepticism and Baldwin boosterism. In: Weber BH, Depew DJ (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT Press/Bradford, Cambridge, pp 53–37Google Scholar
  60. Goodson FE (2003) The evolution and function of cognition. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates Inc., Mahwah, NJGoogle Scholar
  61. Gray RD (1994) Sparrows, matching and the ideal free distribution - Can biological and psychological approaches be synthesized. Anim Behav 48(2):411–123Google Scholar
  62. Hammond RL, Keller L (2004) Conflict over male parentage in social insects. PLoS Biol 2(9):e248PubMedGoogle Scholar
  63. Hardcastle VG (2001) Consciousness: chili of the brain. Conscious C 10:418–820Google Scholar
  64. Harnad S (1993) Problems, problems: the frame problem as a symptom of the symbol grounding problem. Psycholoquy 4(34):(11)Google Scholar
  65. Haselager P, de Groot A et al. (2003) Representationalism vs. anti-representationalism: a debate for the sake of appearance. Philos Psyc 16(1):5–53Google Scholar
  66. Haugeland J (1997) What is mind design? In: Haugeland J (ed) Mind design II: philosophy, psychology, artificial intelligence. MIT/Bradford, Cambridge, pp 1–18Google Scholar
  67. Hoffmeyer J, Emmeche C (1991) Code-duallity and the semiotics of nature. In: Anderson M, Merrell F (ed) On semiotic modeling. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin, pp 117–766Google Scholar
  68. Holmes B (2004) Manna or millstone. New Sci 183(2465):29–91Google Scholar
  69. Hull DL (2001) That just don’t sound right: a plea for real examples. In: Hull DL (ed) Science and selection: essays on biological evolution and the philosophy of science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 196–621Google Scholar
  70. Hurley SL (1998) Consciousness in action. Harvard University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  71. Husserl E (1952) Ideas: general introduction to a pure phenomenology. Allen & Unwin, LondonGoogle Scholar
  72. Jennings HS (1905/1962) Behavior of the lower organisms. Indiana University Press, BloomingtonGoogle Scholar
  73. Kauffman S (2000) Investigations. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  74. Keijzer F (2001) Representation and behavior. MIT Press/Bradford Book, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  75. Kerepesi A, Jonsson GK et al (2005) Detection of temporal patterns in dog-human interaction. Behav Proc 70(1):69–99Google Scholar
  76. Kitano H (2002) Systems biology: a brief overview. Science 295(1 March 2002):1662–2664PubMedGoogle Scholar
  77. Koshland DE Jr (1980) Bacterial chemotaxis as a model behavioral system. Raven Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  78. Kringelbach ML (2004) Food for thought: hedonic experience beyond homeostasis in the human brain. Neuroscience 126(4):807–719PubMedGoogle Scholar
  79. La Cerra P, Bingham R (2002) The origin of minds. Harmony Books, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  80. Lawton G (2004) Urban legends. New Sci 183(2465):32–25Google Scholar
  81. Levi-Strauss C (1969) The raw and the cooked. Harper & Row, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  82. Lockery S (1989) Representation, functionalism, and simple living systems. In: Montefiore A, Noble D (eds) Goals, no-goals and own goals. A debate on goal-directed and intentional behaviour. Unwin Hyman, London, pp 117–758Google Scholar
  83. Lyon P (2004) Autopoiesis and knowing: reflections on Maturana’s biogenic explanation of cognition. Cybernet Human Know 11(4):21–16Google Scholar
  84. Lyon P (2005) Agent in the organism: toward a biogenic theory of cognition. PhD thesis, Australian National University (forthcoming)Google Scholar
  85. Macnab RM, Koshland DE (1972) The gradient-sensing mechanism in bacterial chemotaxis. PNAS 69(9):2509–9512PubMedGoogle Scholar
  86. Macphail EM, Bolhuis JJ (2001) The evolution of intelligence: adaptive specialization versus general process. Biol Rev Camb Philos Soc 76(3):341–164PubMedGoogle Scholar
  87. Marahiel MA, Zuber P (1999) Sporulation and cell differentiation. In: Lengeler JW, Drews G, Schlegel HG (eds) Biology of the prokaryotes. Blackwell, New York, pp 586–601Google Scholar
  88. Margulis L (2001) The conscious cell. Ann N Y Acad Sci 929:55–50PubMedCrossRefGoogle Scholar
  89. Martin E, Hine RS (eds) (2000) A dictionary of biology. Oxford Reference Paperback. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  90. Maturana HR (1970/1980) Biology of cognition. In: Maturana HR, Varela FJ (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, 42:1–18Google Scholar
  91. Maturana HR (1990) The biological foundations of self-consciousness and the physical domain of existence. In: Luhmann N, Maturana HR, Namiki M, Redder V, Varela F (eds) Beobachter: Konvergenz der Erkenntnistheorien? Wilhelm Fink Verlag, Munich, pp 47–717Google Scholar
  92. Maturana HR (2003) Autopoiesis, structural coupling and cognition: a history of these and other notions in the biology of cognition. Cybernet Human Know 9(3–3):5–54Google Scholar
  93. Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1973/1980) Autopoiesis: the organization of the living. In: Maturana HR, Varela FJ (eds) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, 42:59–938Google Scholar
  94. Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1980) Autopoiesis and cognition: the realization of the living. D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Boston, LondonGoogle Scholar
  95. Maturana HR, Varela FJ (1992) The tree of knowledge: the biological roots of human understanding. Shambala Publications Inc. BostonGoogle Scholar
  96. Maynard Smith J, Szathmáry E (1999) The origins of life: from the birth of life to the origin of language. Oxford University Press, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  97. McCulloch WS, Pitts W (1943) A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. B Math Biophys 5:115–53Google Scholar
  98. Merleau-Ponty M (1962) Phenomenology of perception. Routledge & Kegan Paul, LondonGoogle Scholar
  99. Miller GA (2003) The cognitive revolution: a historical perspective. Trends C Sc 7(3):141–144Google Scholar
  100. Millikan RG (1989) Biosemantics. J Philos 86(6):281–197Google Scholar
  101. NIH (2001) Elucidation of the underlying mechanisms of placebo effect (research funding announcement), National Institues of Health (USA). 2001Google Scholar
  102. Nordstrom K, Wallen R et al. (2003) A simple visual system without neurons in jellyfish larvae. P Roy Soc B 270(1531):2349–9354Google Scholar
  103. O’Brien G, Opie J (2004) Notes toward a structuralist theory of mental representation. In: Clapin H, Staines P, Slezak P (eds) Representation in mind: new approaches to mental representation. Elsevier, New York, pp 1–10Google Scholar
  104. Olson ET (1997) The human animal: personal identity without psychology. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  105. Pattee HH (1969) How does a molecule become a message? Dev Biol Suppl 3:1–16Google Scholar
  106. Piaget J (1970) Genetic epistemology. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  107. Popper KR (1965/1972) Of clouds and clocks: an approach to the problem of rationality and the freedom of man. In: Popper KR (ed) Objective knowledge. An evolutionary approach. Clarendom, Oxford, pp 206–655Google Scholar
  108. Prete FR. (ed) (2004) Complex worlds from simpler nervous systems. MIT Press/Bradford, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  109. Prigogine I (1996) The end of certainty: time, chaos, and the new laws of nature. The Free Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  110. Putnam H (1988) Representation and reality. MIT Press/Bradford, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  111. Richards RJ (1987) Darwin and the emergence of evolutionary theories of mind and behavior. University of Chicago Press, ChicagoGoogle Scholar
  112. Rose S (1998) The rise of neurogenetic determinism. In: Cornwell J (ed) Consciousness and human identity. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 86–600Google Scholar
  113. Rosen R (1985) Anticipatory systems: philosophical, mathematical, and methodological foundations. Pergamon, OxfordGoogle Scholar
  114. Rosen R (2000) Essays on life itself. Columbia University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  115. Rosenberg A (1986) Intention and action among the macromolecules. In: Rescher N (ed) Current issues in teleology. University Press of America, Lanham, pp 65–56Google Scholar
  116. Scheper WJ, Scheper GC (1996) Autopsies on autopoiesis. Behav Sci 41(1):3–32Google Scholar
  117. Searle JR (1981) Minds, brains, and programs. In: Hofstadter DR, Dennett DC (eds) The mind’s I. Penguin Books, London, pp 351–173Google Scholar
  118. Sebeok TA (ed) (1996) Advances in semiotics. Indiana University Press, BloomingtonGoogle Scholar
  119. Shannon CE, Weaver W (1949) The mathematical theory of communication. University of Illinois Press, UrbanaGoogle Scholar
  120. Silver BL (1998) The ascent of science. Oxford University Press, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  121. Sterelny K (2001) The evolution of agency and other essays. Cambridge University Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  122. Sterelny K (2003) Thought in a hostile world: the evolution of human cognition. Blackwell, Malden, MAGoogle Scholar
  123. Stewart J (1996) Cognition = life: implications for higher-level cognition. Behav Proc 35(1–1):311–126Google Scholar
  124. Stewart J, Coutinho A (2004) The affirmation of self: a new perspective on the immune system. Artif Life 10(3):261–176PubMedGoogle Scholar
  125. Stich SP (1983) From folk psychology to cognitive science: the case against belief. MIT/Bradford, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  126. Tebbich S, Bshary R (2004) Cognitive abilities related to tool use in the woodpecker finch, Cactospiza pallida. Anim Behav 67(4):689–997Google Scholar
  127. Trefil J (2003) The nature of science: an A-Z guide to the laws & principles governing our universe. Houghton Mifflin Company, BostonGoogle Scholar
  128. Turing AM (1936) On computable numbers, with an application to the Entscheidungsproblem. Proc Lond Math Soc 42(ser 2):230–305Google Scholar
  129. Varela FJ, Thompson E et al (1991) The embodied mind: cognitive science and human experience. MIT Press, CambridgeGoogle Scholar
  130. Vertosick FTJ (2002) The genius within: discovering the intelligence of every living thing. Harcourt Inc, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  131. von Bertalanffy L (1968) General system theory: foundations development applications. Penguin Books, HarmondsworthGoogle Scholar
  132. von Glasersfeld E (1997) Distinguishing the observer: an attempt at interpreting Maturana. Ecology of Mind, 2003Google Scholar
  133. Washburn MF (1936) The animal mind: a text-book of comparative psychology. MacMillan, New YorkGoogle Scholar
  134. Wittgenstein L (1953/1994) Philosophical investigations. Basil Blackwell Ltd., OxfordGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Marta Olivetti Belardinelli and Springer-Verlag 2005

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Australian National University/University of AdelaideEvandaleAustralia

Personalised recommendations