Skip to main content
Log in

A top dog tale with preference complementarities

  • Published:
Journal of Economics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The emergence of a winner-take-all (top dog) outcome is generally due to political or institutional constraints or to specific technological features which favour the performance of just one individual. In this paper we provide a different explanation for the occurrence of a top-dog equilibrium in exchange economies. We show that once heterogeneous complementarities (i.e. Scarf’s preferences) are analysed with general endowment distributions, a variety of equilibria different from the well-known symmetric outcome with full utilisation of resources can emerge. Specifically, we show that stable corner equilibria with a winner-take-all (top dog) individual arise that are Pareto optima although the remaining individuals are no better off than with zero consumption and resources can be unused. Because of heterogenous complementarities, market mechanisms are weak and cannot overcome the top dog’s power. Voting mechanisms or taxation policies can reduce the top dog’s privileged position.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Bundled complementarities exist if each individual utility depends only on fixed coefficient combinations of different pairs (or groups) of goods.

  2. If we define the top dog as the individual with the highest welfare and we compare the set of efficient allocations (and later the equilibria) in terms of utility distribution, we should assume cardinal and interpersonally comparable utility. Alternatively, the top dog in our context can be identified also as the individual getting the highest shares of all the goods that she desires and the analysis can be developed in terms of the individual consumption allocations (and later equilibria). This requires only ordinal preferences. However, for easy of exposition, we assume cardinal and interpersonally comparable utility. Of course our main results on the full set of efficient and equilibrium allocations and stability of the equilibria only depend on ordinal preferences.

  3. We use “usefully” consumed or utilised resources or “useful” consumption or resources to indicate economic activities or resources that yield utility. When (some quantities of) the goods are “not useful”or are “useless” the individual is indifferent between consuming or freely disposing them.

References

  • Anderson CM, Plott CR, Shimomura KI, Granat S (2004) Global instability in experimental general equilibrium: the scarf example. J Econ Theory 115:209–249

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Artik A (2003) Globally stable price dynamics. J Math Econ 39:27–38

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • De Nicolò V, Franzoni LA (2010) On the winner-take-all principle in innovation races. J Eur Econ Assoc 8:1133–1158

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feldman AM, Serrano R (2006) Welfare econonomics and social choice theory. Springer, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Fullerton R, Preston McAfee P (1999) Auctioning entry into tournaments. J Polit Econ 107:573–605

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hirota M (1981) On the stability of competitive equilibrium and the patterns of initial holdings: an example. Int Econ Rev 22:461–467

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kumar A, Shubik M (2004) Variations on the theme of Scarf’s counter-example. Comput Econ 24:1–19

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lizzeri A, Persico N (2001) The provision of public goods under alternative electoral incentives. Am Econ Rev 91:225–239

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lizzeri A, Persico N (2005) A drawback of electoral competition. J Eur Econ Assoc 3:1318–1348

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lindbeck A, Weibull J (1987) Balanced-budget redistribution as the outcome of political competition. Public Choice 52:173–197

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maurer SM, Scotchmer S (2002) The independent invention defence in intellectual property. Economica 69:535–547

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moldovanu B, Sela A (2001) The optimal allocation of prizes in contests. Am Econ Rev 91:542–558

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mukherji A (2007) Global stability condition on the plane: a general law of demand. J Econ Theory 134:583–592

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ogata K (1970) Modern control engineering. Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs

    Google Scholar 

  • Piccione M, Rubinstein A (2007) Equilibrium in the jungle. Econ J 117:883–896

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Postlewaite A (1979) Manipulation via endowments. Rev Econ Stud 46:255–262

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen S (1981) The economics of superstars. Am Econ Rev 7:845–858

    Google Scholar 

  • Scarf H (1960) Some Examples of global instability of the competitive equilibrium. Int Econ Rev 1:157–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yamamoto T, Asano M, Togawa Y, Ohya M (2008) On the Scarf-Hirota model in the price-scaled adjustment process. arXiv:0802.2413v1 [maths.DS]

Download references

Acknowledgments

We gratefully acknowledge participants at ESEM 2010, ASSET 2010, 10th Journées Gerard Varet 2011, II Workshop in General Equilibrium 2011 at University of York and seminar participants at University of California San Diego and University of Bologna.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Emanuela Randon.

Appendix

Appendix

Proof of Proposition 1

(Case with different prices)

  1. (a)

    Suppose that the price are unequal and such that: \(p_{x}=\alpha ,\) \( p_{y}=\beta \) and \((1-\alpha -\beta )=p_{z},\) with \(0<1-\alpha -\beta <1,\) and \(0<\alpha \ne \beta \ne \gamma <1\). The equilibrium conditions become:

    $$\begin{aligned} f_{y1}= & {} \frac{\alpha X_{1}+\beta Y_{1}+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{1}}{(1-\alpha ) }=1/2, \\ f_{x2}= & {} \frac{\alpha X_{2}+\beta Y_{2}+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{2}}{(1-\beta )} =1/2, \nonumber \end{aligned}$$
    (9)

    which imply:

    $$\begin{aligned} \alpha X_{1}+\beta Y_{1}+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{1}= & {} (1-\alpha )/2 \\ \alpha X_{2}+\beta Y_{2}+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{2}= & {} (1-\beta )/2 \end{aligned}$$
  2. (b)

    Conversely suppose the conditions (3) hold. Then we have to show that this implies that \(p_{x}=\alpha \); \(p_{y}=\beta .\) Again multiplying through (9), we get the linear system:

    $$\begin{aligned} p_{x}X_{1}+p_{y}Y_{1}+(1-p_{x}-p_{y})Z_{1}= & {} (1-p_{x})/2, \\ p_{x}X_{2}+p_{y}Y_{2}+(1-p_{x}-p_{y})Z_{2}= & {} (1-p_{y})/2. \end{aligned}$$

    Solving these linear equations we get:

    $$\begin{aligned} p_{y}= & {} -\frac{(-\frac{1}{2}X_{2}+Z_{1}X_{2}+\frac{1}{2}X_{1}-Z_{2}X_{1}- \frac{1}{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{4})}{(Y_{2}X_{1}-Y_{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{2} Y_{2}-Z_{2}X_{1}-\frac{1}{2}Z_{2}+\frac{1}{2}X_{1}-\frac{1}{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{ 4}+Y_{1}Z_{2}-Y_{1}X_{2}+Z_{1}X_{2})}, \nonumber \\ p_{x}= & {} \frac{(Y_{2}-Z_{2}+\frac{1}{4}-Z_{2}Z_{1}-\frac{1}{2} Y_{1}+Y_{1}Z_{2})}{(Y_{2}X_{1}-Y_{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{2}Y_{2}-Z_{2}X_{1}-\frac{1 }{2}Z_{2}+\frac{1}{2}X_{1}-\frac{1}{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{4} +Y_{1}Z_{2}-Y_{1}X_{2}+Z_{1}X_{2})}. \nonumber \\ \end{aligned}$$
    (10)

    This solution requires that the determinant condition

    $$\begin{aligned} \left( Y_{2}X_{1}-Y_{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{2}Y_{2}-Z_{2}X_{1}-\frac{1}{2}Z_{2}+\frac{1}{ 2}X_{1}-\frac{1}{2}Z_{1}+\frac{1}{4}+Y_{1}Z_{2}-Y_{1}X_{2}+Z_{1}X_{2}\right) \ne 0 \end{aligned}$$

    should hold. Recalling the general Hirota conditions (3):

    $$\begin{aligned} X_{1}=\left( \frac{-\beta Y_{1}-(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{1}+(1-\alpha )/2}{\alpha }\right) , \end{aligned}$$
    $$\begin{aligned} X_{2}=\left( \frac{-\beta Y_{2}-(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{2}+(1-\beta )/2}{\alpha }\right) , \end{aligned}$$

    and substituting them in (10) gives \(p_{x}=\alpha ;p_{y}=\beta \).

\(\square \)

The sufficient and necessary conditions to decentralise the other special cases of the interior Pareto optimum with (i) \(p_{y}\) costing twice \(p_{x}\), or (ii) \(p_{x}=p_{y}\) can be shown by simply assuming in the above proof respectively that (i) \(p_{x}=\alpha ,\) \(p_{y}=2\alpha \) and \(\alpha (X_{1}+2Y_{1})+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{1}=(1-\alpha )/2,\) \(\alpha (X_{2}+2Y_{2})+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{2}=(1-\beta )/2,\) (ii) \(p_{x}=p_{y}=\alpha ,\) \(\alpha (X_{1}+Y_{1})+(1-\alpha -\beta )Z_{1}=(1-\alpha )/2\) and \(\alpha (X_{2}+Y_{2})+(1-\alpha -\beta )\).

The sufficient and necessary conditions are derived using the same procedure as the Proof of Proposition 1 and imposing \(p_{x}=p_{y}=\alpha =\beta =1/3.\)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Randon, E., Simmons, P. A top dog tale with preference complementarities. J Econ 120, 47–63 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00712-016-0490-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00712-016-0490-8

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation