Skip to main content
Log in

Consumer default with complete markets: default-based pricing and finite punishment

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Economic Theory Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper studies economies with complete markets where there is positive default on consumer debt. In a simple tractable two-period model, households can default partially, at a finite punishment cost, and competitive intermediaries price loans of different sizes separately. This environment yields only partial insurance. The default-based pricing of debt makes it too costly for the borrower to achieve full insurance, and there is too little trade in securities. This framework is in contrast to existing literature. Unlike the literature with default, there are no restrictions on the set of state contingent securities that are issued. Unlike the literature on lack of commitment, limited trade arises without need of debt constraints that rule default out. Compared with the latter, the present approach appears to imply more consumption inequality. An extended model with an infinite horizon, idiosyncratic risk and more realistic assumptions is used to demonstrate the general validity of this approach and its main implications.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. An early word on terminology is in order. Here, as in much literature on limited commitment (e.g., Kehoe and Levine 1993; Alvarez and Jermann 2000), we speak of complete markets as the availability of securities spanning the space of states of nature. This is a narrower notion than in Dubey et al. (2005) where tradeable assets are defined also over the level of default punishments, possibly including infinite penalties. Another difference is that that paper associates each type of asset with a specific debt constraint; in our case, each type of asset is associated with one level of debt. See below for further discussion.

  2. This is the theme of recent empirical and theoretical studies in Dawsey and Ausubel (2004), Dawsey et al. (2008) and Benjamin and Mateos-Planas (2012), Chatterjee (2010) and Herkenhoff (2012). In the Survey of Consumer Finances 2007, about 1 % of the U.S. population had filed under Chapter 7, whereas over 5 % held delinquent loans. See Díaz-Giménez et al. (2011).

  3. A point taken up in Arellano et al. (2013). Yet, previous analyses of sovereign debt since Eaton and Gersovitz (1981), including more recently Arellano (2008), Benjamin and Wright (2009) and Yue (2010), appear to consider default only as a binary choice.

  4. Since the outcome under each contingency is always perfectly anticipated, a possible question is whether this default does really represent a failure to fulfill the contract. The implications of the theory for measured observable default might thus need to be interpreted with caution. Here, we simply note that incomplete-markets models with rational expectations would not be totally immune to this observation. In any event, it would not detract from the significance of the theory for observable variables like consumption, a central point of this paper.

  5. In models with a complete set of contingent assets like the present one, as the agent attempts to insure consumption, income and debt liabilities tend to be positively associated ex-post. The emergence of something resembling standard debt contracts would in principle require asymmetric information and monitoring costs as in Diamond (1984). An open question that we will not pursue here is whether the present model could deliver a similar outcome via a specific structure of default penalties. We thank a referee for suggesting this avenue.

  6. In this case, default would not be meaningful, as the model would be equivalent to a model without default and debt determined by the portion repaid in the model with default.

  7. In an interesting paper, Koeppl (2007) endogenizes the level of enforcement in dynamic risk-sharing problems.

  8. There is also a literature on endogenous limits with incomplete markets that similarly rules out positive default in equilibrium. This includes Zhang (1997), Mateos-Planas and Seccia (2006), Ábrahám and Cárceles-Poveda (2010), Andolfatto and Gervais (2008) and Wang (2011).

  9. Kehoe and Levine (2006) brings together the two streams by studying an economy with incomplete markets and collateral constraints in a way that reconciles the outcomes of a debt-constrained model with complete markets.

  10. This is their Theorem 3.

  11. Their Example 1 considers the effect of finite penalties with full span of payoffs but assumes pooling. Examples 2 and 3 consider pooling and a restricted set of tradeable promises. Example 4 studies assets with different debt limits but with restrictions on the set of tradeable promises.

  12. This is not unlike Dubey et al. (2005)’s refinement to prevent the existence of markets being ruled out by excessively pessimistic expectations.

  13. Portfolios for an individual could not have both \(l_{s}^{i}\) and \(a_{s}^{i}\) positive. For the two (interior) conditions (2) and (3) to hold, it is required that \(q_{s}^{i}/p_{s}>1-d_{s}^{i}\), a contradiction with (7).

  14. Proofs of propositions 1, 2 and 3 are in the “Appendix.”

  15. Note this figure holds the variables \(c_{0}^{j_{-}}\) and \(c_{0}^{j}\) fixed. This is correct as the analysis here considers differences across states within the same equilibrium and, therefore, the same initial consumption allocations.

  16. Also a feature of models with debt constraints in the vein of Kehoe and Levine (1993).

  17. State-dependent penalties are also typical of models of sovereign debt like Arellano (2008) or Chatterjee and Eyigungor (2012).

  18. See their examples 1, 2 and 3.

  19. See Cordoba (2008) and Broer (2011) for further analysis of the evidence.

  20. Therefore, if default happens in this case, it will be at a rate of 100 %. Therefore, using the cost parameter \(\eta 1^{\gamma }=\eta \) is defensible as the choice congruent with the punishment technology assumed in the default-pricing model. Choosing a smaller cost for the debt-constrained economy, while interesting, is more arbitrary. On the other hand, this debt-constrained economy can also be seen as a special case of the model where we are merely setting the elasticity of the punishment \(\gamma \) to 0.

  21. Naturally, we will be supposing that the condition for existence discussed earlier \(\gamma -1-d/(1-d)>0\) holds.

  22. At high enough \(d\), indicated as d max, the borrowing cost condition will not be well defined and existence would fail.

  23. In the vein of the literature studying risk sharing and default like Krueger and Perri (2006) or Chatterjee et al. (2007).

  24. We are dispensing with the convex smooth function of previous sections.

  25. Besides deadweight costs, Livshits et al. (2010) also consider costs that recover loans for the lender which, for present purposes, we omit. A cost proportional to the total value of debt defaulted has been considered but not pursued further as it has some problematic implications for the pricing mappings.

  26. One could equivalently split insurers and lenders into separate operations who lend or borrow in a riskless bond. In any event, since individual risk is uncorrelated, we have to assume intermediaries can pool risks.

  27. This results in about 0.10 variance of the log of earnings, close to estimates of the transitory component of residual wages for the most recent periods in Heathcote et al. (2010), and of the same order as the 0.14 of the three-state process for earnings in Fernandez-Villaverde and Krueger (2011).

  28. For example, Livshits et al. (2010).

  29. In this way \(p_{s}/\pi _{s}\) is the inverse of the risk-free rate on a redundant bond. Like in Krueger and Perri (2006), this will be making idiosyncratic risk fully insured, rather than uninsurable, in the case when there is perfect enforcement.

  30. This fixed cost is non-pecuniary. A financial cost works to exactly the same effect but will require additional notation.

  31. The probability of credit exclusion when defaulting \(1-\exp (-\gamma _{\delta })\) goes from 63.2 % in the previous cases down to 39.3 %.

  32. A similar point is made in the recent quantitative analysis of a model à la Kehoe-Levine in Broer (2011).

  33. This setting for the prices of securities will cause lack of insurance for reasons unrelated to the default mechanism emphasized in this paper. The interest here, however, is not in risk sharing but rather in how the model stands as an account of household default and debt, leaving aside this time the issue of market-clearing equilibrium.

  34. See, for example, Benjamin and Mateos-Planas (2012) and Mateos-Planas and Ríos-Rull (2013). Livshits et al. (2010) and Chatterjee et al. (2007) consider also figures for debt around 10 %.

  35. See Benjamin and Mateos-Planas (2012) or Díaz-Giménez et al. (2011).

  36. See Díaz-Giménez et al. (2011), Table 15 and Table 7.

  37. Additionally, in these examples the proportion of debtors is around 20 % so reassuringly only a fraction of debtors default. On the other hand, the measured proportion of debt defaulted varies between 4 and 7 %, not far from the charge-off rate used in, for example, Livshits et al. (2010).

References

  • Ábrahám, Á., Cárceles-Poveda, E.: Endogenous trading constraints with incomplete asset markets. J. Econ. Theory 145(3), 974–1004 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, F., Jermann, U.: Efficiency, equilibrium, and asset pricing with risk of default. Econometrica 68(4), 775–797 (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  • Andolfatto, D., Gervais, M.: Endogenous debt constraints in a life-cycle model with an application to social security. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 32(12), 3745–3759 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Araujo, A.P., Páscoa, M.R.: Bancruptcy in a model of unsecured claims. Econ. Theory 20(3), 455–481 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Araujo, A., Monteiro, P., Páscoa, M.: Incomplete markets, continuum of states and default. Econ. Theory 11(1), 205–213 (1998)

    Google Scholar 

  • Arellano, C.: Default risk and income fluctuations in emerging economies. Am. Econ. Rev. 98(3), 690–712 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Arellano, C., Mateos-Planas, X., Ríos-Rull J.V.: Partial Default. Manuscript (2013)

  • Athreya, K., Tam, X., Young, E.: Unsecured credit markets are not insurance markets. J. Monet. Econ. 56(1), 83–103 (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, D., Mateos-Planas, X.: Formal Versus Informal Default in Consumer Credit. Manuscript (2012)

  • Benjamin, D., Wright, M.: Recovery Before Redemption: A Theory of Delays in Sovereign Debt Renegotiations, Working Paper (2009)

  • Broer, T.: The Wrong Shape of Insurance? What Cross-Sectional Distributions Tell Us About Models of Consumption-Smoothing, CEPR Discussion Paper No. DP8701 (2011)

  • Chatterjee, S.: An equilibrium model of the timing of bankruptcy filings. Presented at Credit, Default and Bankruptcy Conference, LAEF, UCSB (2010)

  • Chatterjee, S., Eyigungor, B.: Maturity, indebtedness, and default risk. Am. Econ. Rev. 102(6), 2674–99 (2012)

    Google Scholar 

  • Chatterjee, S., Corbae, D., Nakajima, M., Ríos-Rull, J.: A quantitative theory of unsecured consumer credit with risk of default. Econometrica 75(6), 1525–1589 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Cordoba, J.: US inequality: debt constraints or incomplete asset markets? J. Monet. Econ. 55(2), 350–364 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dawsey, A., Ausubel, L.: Informal Bankruptcy, unpublished (2004)

  • Dawsey, A., Hynes, R., Ausubel, L.: The Regulation of Non-judicial Debt Collection and the Consumer’s Choice Among Repayment, Bankruptcy and Informal Bankruptcy, University of Virginia Legal Working Paper Series, p. 42 (2008)

  • Diamond, D.W.: Financial intermediation and delegated monitoring. Rev. Econ. Stud. 51(3), 393–414 (1984)

    Google Scholar 

  • Díaz-Giménez, J., Glover, A., Ríos-Rull, J.: Facts on the distributions of earnings, income, and wealth in the United States: 2007 update. Fed. Reserve Bank Minneap. Q. Rev. 34(1), 2–31 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Dubey, P., Geanakoplos, J., Shubik, M.: Default and punishment in general equilibrium1. Econometrica 73(1), 1–37 (2005)

    Google Scholar 

  • Eaton, J., Gersovitz, M.: Debt with potential repudiation: theoretical and empirical analysis. Rev. Econ. Stud. 48(2), 289–309 (1981)

    Google Scholar 

  • Fernandez-Villaverde, J., Krueger, D.: Consumption and saving over the life cycle: how important are consumer durables? Macroecon. Dyn. 15(5), 725 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Heathcote, J., Storesletten, K., Violante, G.L.: The macroeconomic implications of rising wage inequality in the United States. J. Polit. Econ. 118(4), 681–722 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Herkenhoff, K.: Informal Unemployment Insurance and Labor Market Dynamics. FRB of St, Louis Working Paper No (2012)

  • Kaplan, G., Violante, G.: How much consumption insurance beyond self insurance? Am. Econ. J.: Macroecon. 38(2), 53–87 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kehoe, T., Levine, D.: Debt-constrained asset markets. Rev. Econ. Stud. 60(4), 865–888 (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kehoe, T., Levine, D.: Liquidity constrained markets versus debt constrained markets. Econometrica 69(3), 575–598 (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kehoe, T., Levine, D.: Bankruptcy and Collateral in Debt Constrained Markets, NBER Working Paper (2006)

  • Kehoe, P., Perri, F.: International business cycles with endogenous incomplete markets. Econometrica 70(3), 907–928 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kilenthong, W.T.: Collateral premia and risk sharing under limited commitment. Econ. Theory 46(3), 475–501 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Koeppl, T.V.: Optimal dynamic risk sharing when enforcement is a decision variable. J. Econ. Theory 134(1), 34–60 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, D., Perri, F.: Does income inequality lead to consumption inequality? Evidence and theory1. Rev. Econ. Stud. 73(1), 163–193 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Livshits, I., MacGee, J., Tertilt, M.: Consumer bankruptcy: a fresh start. Am. Econ. Rev. 97(1), 402–418 (2007)

    Google Scholar 

  • Livshits, I., MacGee, J., Tertilt, M.: Accounting for the rise in consumer bankruptcies. Am. Econ. J. Macroecon. 2(2), 165–193 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateos-Planas, X.: Credit limits and bankruptcy. Econ. Lett. 121(3), 469–472 (2013)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mateos-Planas, X., Ríos-Rull, J.V.: Credit Lines, Manuscript (2013)

  • Mateos-Planas, X., Seccia, G.: Welfare implications of endogenous credit limits with bankruptcy. J. Econ. Dyn. Control 30(11), 2081–2115 (2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Peiris, M.U., Vardoulakis, A.P.: Savings and default. Econ. Theory 54(1), 1–28 (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  • Poblete-Cazenave, R., Torres-Martínez, J.P.: Equilibrium with limited-recourse collateralized loans. Econ. Theory 53(1), 1–31 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, M.: Optimal education policies under endogenous borrowing constraints. Econ. Theory, 1–25 (2011). doi:10.1007/s00199-013-0743-5

  • Yue, V.: Sovereign default and debt renegotiation. J. Int. Econ. 80(2), 176–187 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zame, W.: Efficiency and the role of default when security markets are incomplete. Am. Econ. Rev. 83(5), 1142–1164 (1993)

    Google Scholar 

  • Zhang, H.: Endogenous borrowing constraints with incomplete markets. J. Financ. 52(5), 2187–2209 (1997)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Xavier Mateos-Planas.

Additional information

Thanks to seminar participants at the University of Edinburgh, REDg Barcelona 2011, KIER (Kyoto), Canon Institute for Global Studies (Tokyo), City University London, ESEM Oslo 2011, SED Meeting Ghent 2011, the Minneapolis Federal Reserve Bank 2010, the European Economic Association Congress in Glasgow 2010, the University of Bath and the University of Southampton. Thanks for comments to A. Abraham, S. Chatterjee, M. Gervais, Chiaki Hara, J. Heathcote, Atsushi Kajii, T. Kehoe, J. Knowles, N. Pavoni, F. Perri, J. Pijoan, Sevi Rodríguez-Mora, K. Storesletten and, particularly, V. Ríos-Rull, and two anonymous referees. Part of this research has been funded by the ESRC (UK) through grant RES-000-22-1149.

Appendices

Appendix A: Propositions 1, 2 and 3

Proof of Proposition 1

The problem is \(\max _{d} W(d)\equiv u(y_{s}^{i}-(1-d)l)-\eta d^{\gamma }\) subject to \(d\in [0,1]\) and \(y_{s}^{i}-(1-d)l\ge 0\), for some \(l>0\). The objective is continuous and the choice set is compact, so a solution exists. The objective is differentiable in the interior of the choice set, with the first and second derivatives \(W'(d)=l u'(y_{s}^{i}-(1-d)l)-z'(d)\) and \(W''(d)=l^{2} u''(y_{s}^{i}-(1-d)l)-z''(d)\). Given \(\gamma >1\), the objective is thus strictly concave and the solution is unique. The derivative of the objective at the lowest feasible value is positive: If \(y_{s}^{i}>l\), then \(W'(0)=l/(y_{s}^{i}-l)>0\); otherwise, \(W'(1-y_{s}^{i}/l)=+\infty \). At the other extreme, \(W'(1)=l/y_{s}^{i}-\eta \gamma \). Therefore, if \(l<y_{s}^{i}\eta \gamma 0\), the solution is interior and given by \(W'(d)=0\). Otherwise, if \(l/y_{s}^{i}-\eta \gamma <0\), the solution is at the corner with \(d=1\).

In an interior solution, \(W'(d)\) increases with \(l\); concavity implies that it decreases with \(d\). Therefore, the optimal \(d\) rises with \(l\). As \(l\) approaches \(l/y_{s}^{i}-\eta \gamma \) from the left, the optimal \(d\) approaches 1. So \(d\) is continuous in \(l\), and differentiable except at \(l=y \eta \gamma \).

Proof of Proposition 2

The first part is a direct implication of the properties of \(D_{s}^{i}(.)\) in the previous proposition and the determination of the price schedule in Eq. (6). Using (6) and (4) to differentiate implicitly \(Q_{s}^{i}(l)l\), the resulting derivative is

$$\begin{aligned} {Q_{s}^{i}}'(l)l+Q_{s}^{i}(l)&= p_{s}{{\gamma \eta (\gamma -1){D_{s}^{i}(l)}^{-1}-\gamma \eta \gamma } \over {\gamma \eta (\gamma -1){D_{s}^{i}(l)}^{-1}+\gamma \eta l/(y_{s}^{i}-l(1-D_{s}^{i}(l)))}}\\&= p_{s}{{\gamma \eta (\gamma -1){D_{s}^{i}(l)}^{-1}- \gamma \eta \gamma }\over {\gamma \eta (\gamma -1){D_{s}^{i}(l)}^{-1} +\gamma \eta \gamma \eta {D_{s}^{i}(l)}^{\gamma -1}}}, \end{aligned}$$

where the equality uses (4) again. This shows that \(Q_{s}^{i}(l)l\) is increasing only when \(l\) is such that \(D_{s}^{i}(l)<(\gamma -1)/\gamma \); that \(D_{s}^{i}(.)\) is increasing implies the slope result. Concavity follows from the fact that as \(D_{s}^{i}(.)\) is increasing, the value \({Q_{s}^{i}}'(l)l+Q_{s}^{i}(l)\) decreases with \(l\).

Proof of Proposition 3

The shape of the pricing schedule means that in equilibrium the household will only choose \(l_{s}^{i}<y_{s}^{i} \eta \gamma \). Therefore, default is less than full, and the default and pricing functions are differentiable. Then condition (5) holds because, by proposition 1, (5) is satisfied and point (iv) of the definition holds. Consider the household’s utility as a function of \(l_{s}^{i}\) with default determined by \(D_{s}^{i}(l_{s}^{i})\). Calculate the first and second derivatives, using the envelope property and second-order condition on default \(D(l)\). Because \(Q_{s}^{i}(l)l_{s}^{i}\) is concave from proposition 2, this objective is also concave. That \(l_{s}^{i}\) is positive means the derivative is initially positive; that \(l_{s}^{i}\) eventually leads to full default and zero price means the derivative becomes negative for \(l_{s}^{i}\) large enough, and the unique solution is given by the first-order condition (2). Note that this optimal solution requires \(q_{s}^{i}+{Q_{s}^{i}}'(l_{s}^{i})l_{s}^{i}\) to be positive which, by proposition 2, implies the upper bound for default.

Appendix B: Characterization of the equilibrium in Sect. 5.1

Symmetric fundamentals mean \(y_{1}^{A}=y_{2}^{B}\) and \(y_{1}^{B}=y_{2}^{A}\). We can suppose, without any loss of generality, that \(y_{1}^{A}=y_{2}^{B}>y_{1}^{B}=y_{2}^{A}\). We want to argue first that debts are held in the good state so \(l_{1}^{A}>0\) and \(l_{2}^{B}>0\), that an equilibrium can be characterized by symmetric allocations and that aggregate variables are then state independent. We consider only equilibria where there is some trade.

Debts held in high-income states. One can first argue that consistency with consumer constraints and market clearing in (8) and savers’ optimality (3) requires that debts are held either in the individual bad states or in the good states. That is, either \(l_{1}^{A}>0\) and \(l_{2}^{B}>0\) or \(l_{2}^{A}>0\) and \(l_{1}^{B}>0\). For example, suppose, by way of contradiction, \(l_{1}^{A}>0\) and \(l_{2}^{B}=0\). Then (8b) implies \(c_{1}^{A}<y_{1}^{A}\), and thus, market clearing requires \(c_{1}^{B}>y_{1}^{B}\). That \(l_{2}^{B}=0\) implies, by (8b), \(c_{2}^{A}=y_{2}^{A}\) hence, by market clearing, \(c_{2}^{B}=y_{2}^{B}\), and, by (8b), \(l_{2}^{A}=0\). By (3), \(c_{0}^{A}=c_{0}^{B}\). But then, the constraints in (8a) imply \(c_{0}^{A}>c_{0}^{B}\), a contradiction. Specifically, we can establish that \(l_{1}^{A}>0\) and \(l_{2}^{B}>0\) will be the case. By (8), this amounts to showing that \(c_{1}^{A}<y_{1}^{A}\) and \(c_{2}^{B}<y_{2}^{B}\). Suppose, by way of contradiction and given the first result above, that \(c_{1}^{A}>y_{1}^{A}\) and \(c_{2}^{B}>y_{2}^{B}\). By market clearing in (8) and (7), it follows that \(c_{1}^{B}<y_{1}^{B}\) and \(c_{2}^{A}<y_{2}^{A}\). Therefore, \(c_{2}^{A}<c_{1}^{A}\) and then \(u(c_{2}^{A})/u(c_{1}^{A})>[q_{2}^{A}+{Q_{2}^{A}}'(l_{2}^{A})l_{2}^{A}]/(p_{2}(1-d_{2}^{A})\), which violates optimality conditions (2) and (3), a contradiction.

Symmetric allocations. Suppose \(p_{1}=p_{2}\), then (4) and (6) imply \(Q_{1}^{A}(.)=Q_{2}^{B}(.)\). Suppose also \(q_{1}^{A}=q_{2}^{B}\). Now consider the optimality conditions (2), (3), (5), (7), (8a) and (8b) for \(i=A\), involving \(c_{0}^{A}, c_{1}^{A}, c_{2}^{A}, l_{1}^{A}\) and \(d_{1}^{A}\). Given the symmetry of prices, conditions (2), (3), (5), (7), (8a) and (8b) for \(i=B\) are satisfied for \(c_{0}^{B}, c_{2}^{B}, c_{1}^{B}, l_{2}^{B}\) and \(d_{2}^{B}\) equating, respectively, \(c_{0}^{A}, c_{1}^{A}, c_{2}^{A}, l_{1}^{A}\) and \(d_{1}^{A}\). Finally, as the equilibrium condition (8c) holds for \(c_{2}^{A}\), symmetric allocations also imply that it holds for \(c_{1}^{B}\). So the equalization of prices assumed \(p_{1}=p_{2}\) and \(q_{1}^{A}=q_{2}^{B}\) satisfies all the equilibrium conditions.

Constant values. Given the symmetric allocations, aggregate variables in Sect. 5.1 are labeled as \(y_{l}=y_{1}^{A}=y_{2}^{B}, c_{l}=c_{1}^{A}=c_{2}^{B}, y_{a}=y_{2}^{A}=y_{1}^{B}, c_{a}=c_{2}^{A}=c_{1}^{B}, l=l_{1}^{A}=l_{2}^{B}>0\) and \(d=d_{1}^{A}=d_{2}^{B}>0\), and \(p=p_{1}=p_{2}\) and \(q=q_{1}^{A}=q_{2}^{B}\). Clearly, these values remain invariant to the state \(s=1,2\).

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Mateos-Planas, X., Seccia, G. Consumer default with complete markets: default-based pricing and finite punishment. Econ Theory 56, 549–583 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-013-0792-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s00199-013-0792-9

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation