Theoretical Medicine

, Volume 7, Issue 3, pp 329–353 | Cite as

Deduction, inference and illation

  • Edmond A. Murphy
  • E. Manuel Rossell
  • Magdalena I. Rosell
Special Articles

Abstract

From the standpoint of the theory of medicine, a formulation is given of three types of reasoning used by physicians. The first is deduction from probability models (as in prognosis or genetic counseling for Mendelian disorders). It is a branch of mathematics that leads to predictive statements about outcomes of individual events in terms of known formal assumptions and parameters. The second type is inference (as in interpreting clinical trials). In it the arguments from replications of the same process (‘data’) lead to conclusions about the parameters of a system, without calling into question either the probabilistic model or the criteria of evidence. The third is illation (as in the elucidation of symptoms in a patient). It is a process whereby, in the light of the total evidence and the conclusions from the other types of reasoning, one may modify, expand, simplify or demolish a conceptual framework proposed for deductions, and modify the nature of the evidence sought, the criteriology, the axioms, and the surmised complexity of the scientific theory. (The process of diagnosis as applied to a patient may in extreme cases lead to the discovery of an entirely new disease with its own, quite new, set of diagnostic criteria. This course cannot be accommodated inside either of the other two types of reasoning.) Illation has something of the character of Kuhn's ‘scientific revolution’ in physics; but it differs in that it is the nature, not the degree or frequency of change that distinguishes it from Kuhn's ‘normal science.’

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. [1]
    Stalones, R. A.: 1980, ‘The rise and fall of ischemic heart disease’, Scientific Amer. 242, November, 53–59.Google Scholar
  2. [2]
    Lindley, D. W.: 1965, Introduction to Probability and Statistics, Cambridge, England, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  3. [3]
    De Finetti, B.: 1972, Probability, Induction and Statistics. The Art of Guessing, New York, Wiley.Google Scholar
  4. [4]
    Popper, K. R.: 1963, Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. New York, Harper.Google Scholar
  5. [5]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1979, ‘Quantitative genetics: A critique’, Social Biol. 26, 121–44.Google Scholar
  6. [6]
    Sacher, G. A.: 1959, ‘Relation of lifespan to brain weight and body weight in mammals’, in Wolstenholm, G. E. W. and O'Connor, M. (eds.), Ciba Foundation Colloquia on Ageing. 5. The Lifespan of Animals. Boston, Little Brown.Google Scholar
  7. [7]
    Cutler, R. G.: 1975, ‘Evolution of human longevity and the genetic complexity governing aging rate’, Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. (U.S.A.) 72, 4664–4668.Google Scholar
  8. [8]
    Abbott, M. H., Abbey, H., Bolling, D. R., and Murphy, E. A.: 1978, ‘The familial component in longevity: A study of offspring of nonagenarians. III. Intrafamilial studies’, Amer. J. Med. Genet. 2, 105–120.Google Scholar
  9. [9]
    Philippe, P.: 1978, ‘Familial correlation of longevity: An isolate-based study’, Amer. J. Med, Genet. 2, 121–129.Google Scholar
  10. [10]
    Kuhn, T. S.: 1970, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. Chicago, University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  11. [11]
    Murphy, E. A. 1981, ‘The genetic dynamics of disease’, Amer. J. Med. Genet. 8, 35–52.Google Scholar
  12. [12]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1981, ‘Only authorized persons admitted: The quantitative genetics of health and disease’, Johns Hopk. Med. J. 148, 114–22.Google Scholar
  13. [13]
    Murphy, E. A., and Bolling, D. R.: 1967, ‘Testing of single locus hypotheses where there is incomplete separation of the phenotypes’, Amer. J. Hum. Genet. 19, 322–334.Google Scholar
  14. [14]
    Edwards, A. E. F.: 1972, Likelihood. An Account of the Statistical Concept of Likelihood and Its Application to Scientific Inference, Cambridge, England, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  15. [15]
    Kwiterovich, P. O., Frederickson, D. S., and Levy, R. I.: 1974, ‘Familial hypercholesterolemia (one form of familial type II hyperlipoproteinemia)’, J. Clin. Invest. 53, 1237–1248.Google Scholar
  16. [16]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1976, The Logic of Medicine. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  17. [17]
    Hacking, I. M.: 1966, Logic of Statistical Inference. Cambridge, England, Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  18. [18]
    Plante, A.: 1971, ‘Counter-examples and likelihood’, in Godambe, V. P. and Sprott, D. A. (eds.), Foundations of Statistical Inference, Toronto, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 357–371.Google Scholar
  19. [19]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1982, Biostatistics in Medicine, Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  20. [20]
    Newman, J. H.: 1955, An Essay on the Grammar of Assent 1870, reprinted New York, Image.Google Scholar
  21. [21]
    Rubin, H.: 1971, ‘Occam's razor needs new blades’, in Godambe, V. P. and Sprott, D. A. (eds.), Foundations of Statistical Inference. Toronto, Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 372–74.Google Scholar
  22. [22]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1981, Skepsis, Dogma and Belief. Uses and Abuses in Medicine. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  23. [23]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1977, ‘Classification and its alternatives’, in Engelhardt, H. T., Spicker, S. F., and Towers, B. (eds.), Clinical Judgment: A Critical Appraisal. Dordrecht, Holland, Reidel, pp. 59–85.Google Scholar
  24. [24]
    Ingram, V. M.: 1957, ‘Gene mutations in human haemoglobin. The clinical difference between normal and sickle haemoglobin’, Nature 180, 326–28.Google Scholar
  25. [25]
    Conway, J. H., cited in Gardner, M.: 1971, ‘On cellular automata, self reproduction, the Garden of Eden and the game of “life.”’ Scientific Amer. 224, February, 112–117.Google Scholar
  26. [26]
    Schrandt, R. G. and Ulam, S. M.: 1970, ‘On recursively defined geometrical objects and patterns of growth’, in Burks, A. W. (ed.), Essays on Cellular Automata. Urbana Illinois, University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
  27. [27]
    Farmer, D., Toffoli, T., and Wolfram, S. (eds.): 1984, Cellular Automata. Proceedings of an Interdisciplinary Workshop, Los Alamos, New Mexico. New York, North Holland Physics Publications.Google Scholar
  28. [28]
    Passmore, J. A.: 1966, A Hundred Years of Philosophy, revised ed. New York, Basic Books.Google Scholar
  29. [29]
    Cohen, M. L., Heine, V., and Phillips, J. C.: 1982, ‘The quantum mechanics of materials’, Scientific Amer. 246, June, 82–102.Google Scholar
  30. [30]
    Lyon, M. F.: 1972, ‘X-chromosome inactivation and developmental patterns in mammals’, Biol. Rev. Cambridge Phil. Soc. 47, 1–25.Google Scholar
  31. [31]
    Moreno, A. and Murphy, E. A.: 1981, ‘Inheritance of Kartagener syndrome’, Amer. J. Med. Genet. 8, 305–313.Google Scholar
  32. [32]
    Cantor, C. R. and Schimmel, P. R.: 1980, Biophysical Chemistry. San Francisco, Freeman, esp. pp. 1075–1107.Google Scholar
  33. [33]
    Leder, P.: 1982, ‘The genetics of antibody diversity’, Scientific Amer. 246, May, 102–115.Google Scholar
  34. [34]
    Murphy, E. A., Torjak, J. E., Hou, W., and Rohde, C. A.: 1981, ‘The bingo model of survivorship. 1. Probabilistic aspects’, Amer. J. Med. Genet. 10, 261–277.Google Scholar
  35. [35]
    McKusick, V. A.: 1983, Mendelian Inheritance in Man, 6th ed. Baltimore, Johns Hopkins University Press.Google Scholar
  36. [36]
    Paigen, K.: 1979, ‘Acid hydrolases as models of genetic control’, Ann. Rev. Genet. 13, 417–466.Google Scholar
  37. [37]
    Murphy, E. A.: 1972, ‘The diagnostic process and multiple screening techniques’, Meth. Inf. Med. 11, 8–14.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company 1986

Authors and Affiliations

  • Edmond A. Murphy
    • 1
  • E. Manuel Rossell
    • 1
  • Magdalena I. Rosell
    • 1
  1. 1.Division of Medical GeneticsJohns Hopkins School of MedicineBaltimoreUSA

Personalised recommendations