Advertisement

Biology and Philosophy

, Volume 2, Issue 4, pp 397–414 | Cite as

Individuality, pluralism, and the phylogenetic species concept

  • Brent D. Mishler
  • Robert N. Brandon
Article

Abstract

The concept of individuality as applied to species, an important advance in the philosophy of evolutionary biology, is nevertheless in need of refinement. Four important subparts of this concept must be recognized: spatial boundaries, temporal boundaries, integration, and cohesion. Not all species necessarily meet all of these. Two very different types of “pluralism” have been advocated with respect to species, only one of which is satisfactory. An often unrecognized distinction between “grouping” and “ranking” components of any species concept is necessary. A phylogenetic species concept is advocated that uses a (monistic) grouping criterion of monophyly in a cladistic sense, and a (pluralistic) ranking criterion based on those causal processes that are most important in producing and maintaining lineages in a particular case. Such causal processes can include actual interbreeding, selective constraints, and developmental canalization. The widespread use of the “biological species concept” is flawed for two reasons: because of a failure to distinguish grouping from ranking criteria and because of an unwarranted emphasis on the importance of interbreeding as a universal causal factor controlling evolutionary diversification. The potential to interbreed is not in itself a process; it is instead a result of a diversity of processes which result in shared selective environments and common developmental programs. These types of processes act in both sexual and asexual organisms, thus the phylogenetic species concept can reflect an underlying unity that the biological species concept can not.

Key words

Species concepts individuality pluralism monophyly cladistics phylogeny 

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Avise, J. C.: 1986, ‘Mitochondrial DNA and the Evolutionary Genetics of Higher Animals’, Phil. Trans. R. Soc. Lond. B 312, 325–342.Google Scholar
  2. Beatty, J.: 1985, ‘Pluralism and Panselectionism’, in Asquith, P. D. and Kitcher, P. (eds.), PSA 1984 2, 113–128.Google Scholar
  3. Bernier, R.: 1984, ‘The Species as Individual: Facing Essentialism’, Syst. Zool. 33, 460–469.Google Scholar
  4. Bernstein, H., Byerly, H. C., Hopf, F. A., and Michod, R. E.: 1985, ‘Sex and the Emergence of Species’, J. Theor. Biol. 117, 665–690.Google Scholar
  5. Bremer, K. and Wanntorp, H.-E.: 1979, ‘Geographical Populations or Biological Species in Phylogeny Reconstruction??’, Syst. Zool. 28, 220–224.Google Scholar
  6. Cracraft, J.: 1983, ‘Species Concepts and Speciation Analysis’, Cur. Ornith. 1, 159–187.Google Scholar
  7. Donoghue, M. J.: 1985, ‘A Critique of the Biological Species Concept and Recommendations for a Phylogenetic Alternative’, Bryologist 88, 172–181.Google Scholar
  8. Eldredge, N.: 1985, Unfinished Synthesis: Biological Hierarchies and Modern Evolutionary Thought, Oxford University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  9. Ghiselin, M. J.: 1974, ‘A Radical Solution to the Species Problem’, Syst. Zool. 23, 536–544.Google Scholar
  10. Ghiselin, M. J.: 1987, ‘Species Concepts, Individuality, and Objectivity’, Biology and Philosophy 2, 127–143.Google Scholar
  11. Gould, S. J.: 1980, ‘Is a New and General Theory of Evolusion Emerging?’ Paleobiology 6, 119–130.Google Scholar
  12. Gould, S. J. and Lewontin, R. C.: 1979, ‘ The Spandrels of San Marco and the Panglossian Paradigm: A Critique of the Adaptationist Programme’, Proc. Roy. Soc. Lond. B 205, 581–598.Google Scholar
  13. Haffer, J.: 1986, ‘Superspecies and Species Limits in Vertebrates’, Zeit. Zool. Syst. Evolut.-forsch. 24, 169–190.Google Scholar
  14. Hennig, W.: 1966, Phylogenetic Systematics, Univer. Ill. Press, Urbana.Google Scholar
  15. Holsinger, K. E.: 1984, ‘The Nature of Biological Species’, Phil. Sci. 51, 293–307.Google Scholar
  16. Holsinger, K. E.: (in press), ‘Discussion: Pluralism and Species Concept s, or When Must We Agree With Each Other?’, Phil. Sci. Google Scholar
  17. Hull, D. L.: 1976, ‘Are Species Really Individuals?’ Syst. Zool. 25, 174–191.Google Scholar
  18. Hull, D. L.: 1978, ‘A Matter of Individuality’, Phil. Sci. 45, 335–360.Google Scholar
  19. Hull, D. L.: 1984, ‘Can Kripke Alone Save Essentialism? A Reply to Kitts’, Syst. Zool. 33, 110–112.Google Scholar
  20. Hull, D. L.: 1987, ‘Genealogical Actors in Ecological Roles’, Biology and Philosophy 2, 168–184.Google Scholar
  21. Jablonski, D.: 1986, ‘Background and Mass Extinctions: The Alternation of Macroevolutionary Regimes’, Science 231, 129–133.Google Scholar
  22. Kitcher, P.: 1984a, ‘Species’, Phil. Sci. 51, 308–333.Google Scholar
  23. Kitcher, P.: 1984b, ‘Against the Monism of the Moment’, Phil. Sci. 51, 616–630.Google Scholar
  24. Kitts, D. B.: 1983, ‘Can Baptism Alone Save a Species?’, Syst. Zool. 32, 27–33.Google Scholar
  25. Kitts, D. B.: 1984, ‘The Names of Species: A Reply to Hull’, Syst. Zool. 33, 112–115.Google Scholar
  26. Mayr, E.: 1982, The Growth of Biological Thought, Harvard University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  27. Mayr, E.: 1987, ‘The Ontological Status of Species’, Biology and Philosophy 2, 145–166.Google Scholar
  28. Mishler, B. D.: 1985, ‘The Morphological, Developmental, and Phylogenetic Basis of Species Concepts in Bryophytes’, Bryologist 88, 207–214.Google Scholar
  29. Mishler, B. D. and Donoghue, M. J.: 1982, ‘Species Concepts: A Case For Pluralism’, Syst. Zool. 31, 491–503.Google Scholar
  30. Nelson, G. and Platnick, N. I.: 1981, Systematics and Biogeography: Cladistics and Vicariance, Columbia University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  31. Paterson, H. E. H.: 1985, ‘The Recognition Concept of Species’, in Vrba, E. S. (ed.), Species and Speciation, Transvaal Museum Monograph No. 4, Pretoria, pp. 21–29.Google Scholar
  32. Rieppel, O.: 1986, ‘Species are Individuals: A Review and Critique of the Argument’, Evol. Biol. 20, 283–317.Google Scholar
  33. Rosen, D. E.: 1979, ‘Fishes From the Uplands and Intermontane Basins of Guatemala: Revisionary Studies and Comparative Geography’, Bull. Amer. Mus. Nat. Hist. 162, 267–376.Google Scholar
  34. Ruse, M.: (in press), ‘Species: Natural Kinds, Individuals, or What?’, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. Google Scholar
  35. Simpson, G. G.: 1961, Principles of Animal Taxonomy, Columbia University Press, New York.Google Scholar
  36. Sober, E.: 1984, ‘Discussion: Sets, Species, and Evolution: Comments on Philip Kitcher's “Species”’, Phil. Sci. 51, 334–341.Google Scholar
  37. Van Valen, L. M.: 1982, ‘Integration of Species: Stasis and Biogeography’, Evol. Theory. 6, 99–112.Google Scholar
  38. Wiley, E. O.: 1978, ‘The Evolutionary Species Concept Reconsidered’, Syst. Zool. 27, 17–26.Google Scholar
  39. Wiley, E. O.: 1980, ‘Is the Evolutionary Species fiction? — A Consideration of Classes, Individuals, and Historical Entities’, Syst. Zool. 29, 76–80.Google Scholar
  40. Wiley, E. O.: 1981, Phylogenetics: The Theory and Practice of Phylogenetic Systematics, John Wiley, New York.Google Scholar
  41. Williams, M. B.: 1970, ‘Deducting the Consequences of Evolution: A Mathematical Model’, J. Theor. Biol. 29, 343–385.Google Scholar
  42. Williams, M. B.: 1985, ‘Species are Individuals: Theoretical Foundations for the Claim’, Phil. Sci. 52, 578–590.Google Scholar
  43. Wilson, D. S.: 1980, The Natural Selection of Populations and Communities Benjamin/Cummings, Menlo Park.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company 1987

Authors and Affiliations

  • Brent D. Mishler
    • 1
  • Robert N. Brandon
    • 2
  1. 1.Department of BotanyDuke UniversityDurhamU.S.A.
  2. 2.Department of PhilosophyDuke UniversityDurhamU.S.A.

Personalised recommendations