Skip to main content
Log in

Animal mindreading: what’s the problem?

  • Theoretical Review
  • Published:
Psychonomic Bulletin & Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Research on mindreading in animals has the potential to address fundamental questions about the nature and origins of the human capacity to ascribe mental states, but it is a research programme that seems to be in trouble. Between 1978 and 2000 several groups used a range of methods, some with considerable promise, to ask whether animals can understand a variety of mental states. Since that time, many enthusiasts have become sceptics, empirical methods have become more limited, and it is no longer clear what research on animal mindreading is trying to find. In this article I suggest that the problems are theoretical and methodological: there is difficulty in conceptualising alternatives to ‘full-blown’ mindreading, and reluctance to use the kinds of empirical methods necessary to distinguish mindreading from other psychological mechanisms. I also suggest ways of tackling the theoretical and methodological problems that draw on recent studies of mindreading in humans, and the resources of experimental psychology more generally. In combination with the use of inanimate control stimuli, species that are unlikely to be capable of mindreading, and the ‘goggles method’, these approaches could restore both vigour and rigour to research on animal mindreading.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Woodruff and Premack (1979) also tested for comprehension of deceptive communications.

  2. The first studies using the competitive feeding paradigm were published in the previous year (Hare et al. 2000). I have focussed on the article published in 2001 because it reported procedures that have been used in many subsequent experiments.

  3. The published report (Hare et al. 2001) does not indicate clearly which of the contrasts were statistically significant because the conditions were not labelled consistently in the methods and results sections of the report.

  4. A third experiment reported by Hare et al. (2001) is not discussed here because it had null results.

  5. The Leipzig group has recently used a more carefully controlled “back-and-forth” competitive feeding paradigm in an attempt to rebut this “evil eye” hypothesis (Schmelz et al. 2011, 2013). The methods and results have not been reported in sufficient detail to establish whether the back-and-forth procedure has been successful in this respect. Even if it has, the possibility remains that the choice behaviour of subject chimpanzees in these studies depends, not on the ascription of preferences to others, but on learning – during or before the experiment—that inhibition of a prepotent response is rewarded under delayed test conditions.

  6. The situation may be exacerbated by a socioeconomic problem: due to changes in the social structure of research on animal mindreading, the theoretical and methodological problems are less likely to be solved because fewer minds are working on them, and new ideas are less likely to be honed by disagreement.

  7. One could also ask what is meant by ‘understanding’, but this uncertainty is not specific to perception-goal psychology. It is now commonplace in research on animal and infant cognition to discuss what participants ‘understand’ without explaining what this term implies.

  8. Buckner (2013) argues persuasively that the core problem in contemporary research on animal mindreading is semantic; the field is concerned with ‘concepts’ and ‘representations’ of mental states, entities that are defined by their content, and yet researchers—both enthusiasts and skeptics—do not specify or defend their assumptions concerning how we should decide what a representation is about. On this view, both the intervening variable and minimal mindreading solutions are potential answers to the semantic problem.

  9. Buckner (2013) suggests that whether or not there is a distinctive logical problem at the heart of research on mindreading depends on one’s theory of representation, and that researchers seldom make explicit their theories of representation. If this is correct, it raises the possibility that researchers sometimes express contradictory views—that the problem is logical and that it can be solved by clever experiments – because they do not consistently apply a single, implicit theory of representation.

  10. Chimpanzees remain the modal subjects in research on animal mindreading (Whiten, 2013), but in the last 15 years it has become increasingly common to test birds of the corvid family.

  11. Experiment 1 in Bugnyar (2011) also included a condition where one of the competitors saw both caching events and the other saw neither caching event. This ‘stay treatment’ was not crucial to the interpretation of the results and therefore, for the sake of simplicity and brevity, I have not included it in this summary.

  12. Lurz (2009) suggests that his concept of ‘direct line of sight’ is equivalent to my concept of ‘eye-object line’ (Heyes 1998), but this is not correct. An agent has eye-object line when there is “an unobstructed, notional straight line between their eyes” and the object (Heyes 1998, p 113, emphasis added). That is, when there are no objects interposed between the agent’s eyes and a focal object. In contrast, on Lurz’s account, an agent can have direct line of sight when there is an object between the agent and the focal object, as long as the interposed object is transparent.

References

  • Apperly, I. A. (2011). Mindreaders: The cognitive basis of “theory of mind”. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bräuer, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2007). Chimpanzees really know what others can see in a competitive situation. Animal Cognition, 10(4), 439–448.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Buckner, C. (2013). The semantic problem (s) with research on animal mindreading. Mind & Language, (in press).

  • Bugnyar, T. (2011). Knower–guesser differentiation in ravens: Others’ viewpoints matter. Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences, 278(1705), 634–640.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Butterfill, S. A., & Apperly, I. A. (2013). How to construct a minimal theory of mind. Mind & Language, 28(5), 606–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(5), 187–192.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1954). Operational delineation of “what is learned” via the transposition experiment. Psychological Review, 67(3), 167–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheney, D., & Seyfarth, R. (1990). Attending to behaviour versus attending to knowledge: Examining monkeys’ attribution of mental states. Animal Behaviour, 40(4), 742–753.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cheney, D., Seyfarth, R., & Smuts, B. (1986). Social relationships and social cognition in nonhuman primates. Science, 234, 1361–1366.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, N. S., Dally, J. M., & Emery, N. J. (2007). Social cognition by food-caching corvids. The western scrub-jay as a natural psychologist. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B: Biological Sciences, 362(1480), 507–522.

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2006). Simulating minds: The philosophy, psychology, and neuroscience of mindreading. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, G. (1991). Perceptual and associative learning. Oxford: Clarendon /Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59(4), 771–785.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2001). Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? Animal Behaviour, 61(1), 139–151.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (1993). Anecdotes, training, trapping and triangulating: Do animals attribute mental states? Animal Behaviour, 46(1), 177–188.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (1998). Theory of mind in nonhuman primates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 21(1), 101–114.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2012). Simple minds: A qualified defence of associative learning. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B: Biological Sciences, 367(1603), 2695–2703.

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2014a). False belief in infancy: A fresh look. Developmental Science. doi:10.1111/desc.12148

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C. (2014b). Submentalizing: I’m not really reading your mind. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 9, 131–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heyes, C., & Frith, C. D. (2014). The cultural evolution of mind reading. Science, 344, 1243091. doi:10.1126/science.1243091

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Honey, R. C., & Hall, G. (1989). Acquired equivalence and distinctiveness of cues. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Animal Behavior Processes, 15(4), 338.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Hurley, S. L., & Nudds, M. (2006). The questions of animal rationality: Theory and evidence. In S. L. Hurley & M. Nudds (Eds.), Rational animals? Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Karin-D’Arcy, R. M., & Povinelli, D. J. (2002). Do chimpanzees know what each other see? A closer look. International Journal of Comparative Psychology, 15(1), 21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lurz, R. (2009). If chimpanzees are mindreaders, could behavioral science tell? Toward a solution of the logical problem. Philosophical Psychology, 22(3), 305–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lurz, R. (2011). Belief attribution in animals: On how to move forward conceptually and empirically. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 2(1), 19–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meltzoff, A. N., & Brooks, R. (2008). Self-experience as a mechanism for learning about others: A training study in social cognition. Developmental Psychology, 44(5), 1257.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Novey, M. S. (1975). The development of knowledge of others’ ability to see. [Unpublished doctoral dissertation, Harvard University.].

  • Papineau, D., & Heyes, C. (2006). Rational or associative? Imitation in Japanese quail. Rational Animals (pp. 198–216).

  • Pearce, J. M. (2008). Animal learning and cognition: An introduction. Hove: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D. C., & Povinelli, D. J. (2007). On the lack of evidence that non-human animals possess anything remotely resembling a ‘theory of mind’. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society, B: Biological Sciences, 362(1480), 731–744.

    Article  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Penn, D. C., & Povinelli, D. J. (2013). The comparative delusion: The behaviorstic/mentalistic dichotomy in comparative theory of mind research. In J. Metcalfe & H. S. Terrace (Eds.), Agency and joint attention (pp. 62–78). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (2010). Who took the cog out of cognitive science? International Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1, 241.

    Google Scholar 

  • Perner, J. (2012). MiniMeta: In search of minimal criteria for metacognition. Foundations of Metacognition (pp. 94–116).

  • Povinelli, D. J. (1987). Monkeys, apes, mirrors and minds: The evolution of self-awareness in primates. Human Evolution, 2(6), 493–509.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J. (1994). Comparative studies of animal mental state attribution: A reply to Heyes. Animal Behaviour, 48, 239–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., Nelson, K. E., & Boysen, S. T. (1990). Inferences about guessing and knowing by chimpanzees (Pan troglodytes). Journal of Comparative Psychology, 104(3), 203.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., Nelson, K. E., & Boysen, S. T. (1992). Comprehension of role reversal in chimpanzees: Evidence of empathy? Animal Behaviour, 43(4), 633–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Povinelli, D. J., & Vonk, J. (2004). We don’t need a microscope to explore the chimpanzee’s mind. Mind & Language, 19(1), 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Premack, D., & Woodruff, G. (1978). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 1(04), 515–526.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Qureshi, A. W., Apperly, I. A., & Samson, D. (2010). Executive function is necessary for perspective selection, not level-1 visual perspective calculation: Evidence from a dual-task study of adults. Cognition, 117(2), 230–236.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rizley, R. C., & Rescorla, R. A. (1972). Associations in second-order conditioning and sensory preconditioning. Journal of Comparative and Physiological Psychology, 81(1), 1.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Samson, D., Apperly, I. A., Braithwaite, J. J., Andrews, B. J., & Bodley Scott, S. E. (2010). Seeing it their way: Evidence for rapid and involuntary computation of what other people see. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 36(5), 1255.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Santiesteban, I., Catmur, C., Coughlan Hopkins, S., Bird, G., & Heyes, C. (2013). Avatars and arrows: Implicit mentalizing or domain-general processing? Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance. doi:10.1037/a0035175

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Schmelz, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2011). Chimpanzees know that others make inferences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 108(7), 3077–3079.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Schmelz, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2013). Chimpanzees predict that a competitor’s preference will match their own. Biology Letters, 9(1), 20120829.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Senju, A., Southgate, V., Snape, C., Leonard, M., & Csibra, G. (2011). Do 18-month-olds really attribute mental states to others? Psychological Science, 22(7), 878–880.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Seyfarth, R. M., & Cheney, D. L. (2012). Animal cognition: Chimpanzee alarm calls depend on what others know. Current Biology, 22(2), R51–R52.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stanford, K. (2013). Underdetermination of scientific theory. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encylopedia of philosophy.

  • Teufel, C., Alexis, D. M., Clayton, N. S., & Davis, G. (2010). Mental-state attribution drives rapid, reflexive gaze following. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 72(3), 695–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tipples, J. (2002). Eye gaze is not unique: Automatic orienting in response to uninformative arrows. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 9(2), 314–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tipples, J. (2008). Orienting to counterpredictive gaze and arrow cues. Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics, 70(1), 77–87.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M., Savage-Rumbaugh, S., & Kruger, A. C. (1993). Imitative learning of actions on objects by children, chimpanzees, and enculturated chimpanzees. Child Development, 64(6), 1688–1705.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Topal, J., Miklosi, A., Gacsi, M., Doka, A., Pongracz, P., Kubinyi, E.,Csanyi, V. (2009). The dog as a model for understanding human social behavior. Advances in the Study of Behaviour, 39, 71–116.

  • Tulving, E. (1983). Elements of episodic memory. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vonk, J., & Povinelli, D. J. (2011). Social and physical reasoning in human-reared chimpanzees: preliminary studies. In J. Roessler, H. Lerman, N. Eilan (Eds.) Perception, causation and objectivity. Oxford Scholarship Online. doi:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199692040.003.0019

  • Whiten, A. (1994). Grades of mindreading. In C. Lewis & P. Mitchell (Eds.), Children’s early understanding of mind. Origins and development (pp. 47–70). Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A. (2013). Humans are not alone in computing how others see the world. Animal Behaviour, 86(2), 213–221.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Whiten, A., & Byrne, R. W. (1988). Tactical deception in primates. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 11(02), 233–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodruff, G., & Premack, D. (1979). Intentional communication in the chimpanzee: The development of deception. Cognition, 7(4), 333–362.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Ian Apperly, Cameron Buckner, Thomas Bugnyar, Martin Eimer, Nick Shea and an anonymous referee for their thoughtful comments on an earlier draft of this article.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Cecilia Heyes.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Heyes, C. Animal mindreading: what’s the problem?. Psychon Bull Rev 22, 313–327 (2015). https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-014-0704-4

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-014-0704-4

Keywords

Navigation