Skip to main content

Advertisement

Log in

Suboptimal decision criteria are predicted by subjectively weighted probabilities and rewards

  • Published:
Attention, Perception, & Psychophysics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Subjects performed a visual detection task in which the probability of target occurrence at each of the two possible locations, and the rewards for correct responses for each, were varied across conditions. To maximize monetary gain, observers should bias their responses, choosing one location more often than the other in line with the varied probabilities and rewards. Typically, and in our task, observers do not bias their responses to the extent they should, and instead distribute their responses more evenly across locations, a phenomenon referred to as ‘conservatism.’ We investigated several hypotheses regarding the source of the conservatism. We measured utility and probability weighting functions under Prospect Theory for each subject in an independent economic choice task and used the weighting-function parameters to calculate each subject’s subjective utility (SU(c)) as a function of the criterion c, and the corresponding weighted optimal criteria (wc opt ). Subjects’ criteria were not close to optimal relative to wc opt . The slope of SU(c) and of expected gain EG(c) at the neutral criterion corresponding to β = 1 were both predictive of the subjects’ criteria. The slope of SU(c) was a better predictor of observers’ decision criteria overall. Thus, rather than behaving optimally, subjects move their criterion away from the neutral criterion by estimating how much they stand to gain by such a change based on the slope of subjective gain as a function of criterion, using inherently distorted probabilities and values.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7
Fig. 8
Fig. 9
Fig. 10
Fig. 11
Fig. 12

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Allais, M. (1953). Le comportement de l’homme rationel devant le risque, critique des postulates et axiomes de l’ecole americaine. Econometrica, 21, 503–546.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allais, M. (1979). The so-called Allais paradox and rational decisions under uncertainty In Allais, M., & Hagen, O. (Eds.), Expected utility hypothesis and the Allais paradox, (pp. 437–681). Dordrecht: Reidel Publishing Company.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, B., Laurent, P., Yantis, S. (2011). Value driven attentional capture. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108, 10367–10371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Attneave, F. (1953). Psychological probability as a function of experienced frequency. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 46, 81–86.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bernoulli, D. (1954). Exposition of a new theory of risk [translation by L. Sommer of D. Bernoulli, 1738, specimen theoriae novae de mensura sortis, papers of the Imperial Academy of Science of Saint Petersburg, 175–192]. Econometrica, 22(1), 23–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carrasco, M. (2006). Covert attention increases contrast sensitivity: Psychophysical, neurophysiological, and neuroimaging studies In Martinez-Conde, S., Macknik, S., Martinez, L., Alonso, J., Tse, P. (Eds.), Visual Perception. Part I. Fundamentals of Vision: Low and Mid-Level Processes in Perception, Volume 154 of Progress in Brain Research, (pp. 33–70). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Carrasco, M. (2011). Visual attention: The past 25 years. Vision Research, 51, 1484–1525.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Cook, R. (1982). Residuals and influence in regression. New York: Chapman and Hall.

  • Coombs, C.H., Dawes, R.M., Tversky, A. (1970). Mathematical psychology: An elementary introduction. New York: Prentice Hall.

  • Cornelissen, F.W., Peters, E.M., Palmer, J (2002). The eyelink toolbox: Eye tracking with matlab and the psychophysics toolbox. Behavior Research Methods: Instruments & Computers, 34, 613–617.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Della Libera, C. (2006). Visual selective attention and the effects of monetary rewards. Psychological Science, 17, 222–227.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, K., Tambouret, R., Evered, A., Wilbur, D., Wolfe, J. (2011). Prevalence of abnormalities influences cytologists’ error rates in screening for cervical cancer. Archives of Pathology and Laboratory Medicine, 135, 1557–1560.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fox, C., & Poldrack, R. (2009). Prospect theory and the brain In Glimcher, P., Camerer, C., Fehr, E., Poldrack, R. (Eds.), Neuroeconomics: Decision Making and the Brain, (pp. 145–173). New York: Elsevier.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Galanter, E., & Holman, G (1967). Some invariances of the isosensitivity function and their implications for the utility function of money. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 73, 333–339.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, R., & Wu, G. (1999). On the shape of the probability weighting function. Cognitive Psychology, 38, 129–166.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Green, D., & Swets, J. (1966). Signal detection theory and psychophysics. New York: Kreiger Publishing Co.

  • Healy, A.F., & Kubovy, M (1978). The effects of payoffs and prior probabilities on indices of performance and cutoff location in recognition memory. Memory and Cognition, 6, 544–553.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Healy, A.F., & Kubovy, M (1981). Probability matching and the formation of conservative decision rules in a numerical analog of signal detection. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Learning and Memory, 7, 344–354.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hertwig, R., Barron, G., Weber, E., Erev, I. (2004). Decisions from experience and the effect of rare events in risky choice. Psychological Science, 15, 534–539.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1979). Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk. Econometrica, 4, 263–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kubovy, M. (1977). A possible basis for conservatism in signal detection and probabilistic categorization tasks. Perception and Psychophysics, 22, 277–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kubovy, M., & Healy, A (1977). The decision rule in probabilistic categorization: What it is and how it works. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General, 106, 427–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lee, W., & Janke, M. (1965). Categorizing externally distributed stimulus samples for unequal molar probabilities. Psychological Reports, 17, 79–90.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Maddox, W.T. (2002). Toward a unified theory of decision criterion learning in perceptual categorization. Journal of Experimental Analysis of Behavior, 78, 567–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maddox, W.T., & Bohil, C.J. (1998a). Base-rate and payoff effects in multidimensional perceptual organization. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 24, 1459–1482.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Maddox, W.T., & Dodd, J.L. (2001). On the relation between base-rate and cost-benefit learning in simulated medical diagnosis. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 27, 1367–1384.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Maloney, L.T., & Thomas, E.A.C (1991). Distributional assumptions and observed conservatism in the theory of signal detectability. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 35, 443–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Markman, A.B., Baldwin, G.C., Maddox, W. (2005). The interaction of payoff structure and regulatory focus in classification. Psychological Science, 16, 852–855.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Markovsky, I., & Van Huffel, S. (2007). Overview of total least squares methods. Signal Processing, 87, 2283–2302.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Petras, I., & Bednarova, D. (2010). Total least squares approach to modeling: A matlab toolbox. Acta Montanistica Slovaca, 15, 158–170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Preston, M., & Baratta, P. (1948). An experimental study of the auction-value of an uncertain outcome. The American Journal of Psychology, 61, 183–193.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rich, A., Kunar, M.A., Van Wert, M., Hidalgo-Sotelo, B., Horowitz, T., Wolfe, J. (2008). Why do we miss rare targets? Exploring the boundaries of the low prevalence effect. Journal of Vision, 8(15):15, 1–17.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Tanner, W. (1956). Theory of recognition. Journal of the Acoustical Society of America, 28, 882–888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thomas, E.A.C., & Legge, D. (1970). Probability matching as a basis for detection and recognition decisions. Psychological Review, 77, 65–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1986). Rational choice and the framing of decisions. The Journal of Business, 59(4), S251– S278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty . Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ulehla, Z.J. (1966). Optimality of perceptual decision criteria. Journal of Experimental Psychology, 71, 564–569.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Varey, C., Mellers, B., Birnbaum, M. (1990). Judgments of proportions. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 16, 613–625.

    PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, O. (1981). The economics of organization: The transaction cost approach. American Journal of Sociology, 87, 548–577.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Winterfeldt, D., & Edwards, W. (1982). Costs and payoffs in perceptual research. Psychological Bulletin, 91, 609–622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, J., & Van Wert, M. (2010). Varying target prevalence reveals two dissociable decision criteria in visual search. Current Biology, 20, 121–124.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfe, J.M., Horowitz, T., Kenner, N. (2005). Rare items often missed in visual searches. Nature, 435, 439–440.

    Article  PubMed Central  PubMed  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

This work was supported in part by NIH grant EY08266.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael S. Landy.

Appendix

Appendix

Experiment 1 - Contrast Threshold Measurement

Experiment 1 was completed in a single session. We used a 2AFC detection task to determine the Gabor contrasts corresponding to d′ = .5 and 1 for each subject for use in Experiment 3. The trial sequence is shown in Fig. 13. Each block began with a nine-point calibration of the eyetracker. On each trial, the subject fixated a central cross-flanked at 10 deg of eccentricity by 3 deg diameter disks containing noise patches. They initiated the trial by key press. Following a random ISI of 300–700 ms, the target stimulus appeared on the left or right side, chosen at random, and remained visible for 200 ms. The target stimulus disappeared leaving only the noise image (the same noise image was used throughout the trial). Trials in which the subject broke fixation between initiation of the trial and offset of the target were discontinued and rerun later on a randomly selected trial. If fixation was maintained, a small question mark appeared in place of the fixation cross instructing the observer to indicate the side on which the target stimulus appeared by key press. Subjects received auditory feedback on each trial in the form of a high tone for a correct and a low tone for an incorrect response.

Fig. 13
figure 13

Trial sequence for Experiment 1

Stimulus contrast on each trial was determined by one of two staircases (1-up/3-down, 1-up/2-down) selected at random independently of the side on which the target appeared. Contrasts were sampled from 25 logarithmically spaced values ranging from .01−.95. The initial stepsize for each staircase was three. The step size was decreased by one after the first and second reversals. Each subject completed two blocks of 200 trials each in a single session. The staircases were initiated at the beginning of each block. The first block served to stabilize the subjects’ performance in the task. Only the 200 trials of the second block (100 per staircase) were analyzed. Each subject’s data were pooled across the two staircases. Probability correct as a function of contrast was modeled using a Weibull function fit to the data by maximum likelihood. Peak contrasts corresponding to d′ = .5 and 1 were estimated from the fit curve. These contrast values ranged from .04 to .08 (d′ = .5), and .06 to .09 (d′ = 1).

Experiment 2 - Weighting Function Parameter Measurement

As mentioned above, observers’ preferences for a reward, V, given the probability of receiving it, p, deviate from those predicted by assuming the observer maximizes expected gain. They are well predicted by a model that assumes non-linear weighting of probabilities, w(p), and rewards, u(V). Here we assume standard functional forms for w and u (Tversky & Kahneman, 1992; Fox & Poldrack, 2009):

$$ w(p) = \frac{p^{\gamma}}{\left(p^{\gamma}+(1-p)^{\gamma}\right)^{\frac{1}{\gamma}}} $$
$$ u(V) = V^{\alpha}, $$

and estimate the values of the parameters, γ and α, by modeling observers’ preferences for particular probability/reward pairs, i.e., prospects.

On each trial, observers were presented with a choice between a pair of prospects of the form (Fig. 14):

$$(p_{i},X;(1-p_{i}),0)\quad\quad\quad \text{or}\quad\quad\quad ((1-p_{i})V_{i,j};p_{i},0), $$

where X is a value that is held constant across trials, and V is a value that changes on each trial. They were instructed to choose which ‘gamble’ they would prefer. It was explained to the subjects that the dollar values, X and V, were amounts they could actually win and that the probabilities represented the chance of “blindly reaching into a box containing a huge number of lottery tickets, some with the dollar value on them, some with $0 on them, and selecting a winning ticket.” All subjects indicated that they understood the task. Upon completion, a prospect was selected at random from all those chosen by the subject and the outcome of the gamble was generated pseudo-randomly by computer. The subject received the payoff, which ranged from $0-$50 across subjects.

Fig. 14
figure 14

Sample display from Experiment 2. See text for description

On each trial, the value of p i was selected at random from: {.1, .18, .28, .4}. The value of X was fixed at $50. For each value of p i , five values of V i, j were employed corresponding to five values of the psychometric function, {.2,.35,.5,.65,.8}, that gives probability, P(choose V), of choosing the prospect containing V i, j (as a function of only V i, j ) given the current estimates of the parameters γ and α.

An additional parameter, δ, was added to account for patterns of choice observed in piloting Experiment 2. In piloting the experiment, we found that subjects’ choices were consistent with an additional weighting of the changing value, δV i, j (for δ > 1), such that increases in its value are subjectively exaggerated. Experiment 2 results in data to which four psychometric functions (each corresponding to one of the four values of p i ), giving P(choose V) as a function of V i, j , are fit. The parameters γ and α determine the relative spacing of the four psychometric functions. Increasing values of δ shift the four functions uniformly toward lower values of V i, j . The addition of δ led to a substantial reduction in the error of the fits. The method for selecting the values of V i, j is explained below.

Under prospect theory, as modified by the additional δ parameter, the subject will choose the lottery containing V i, j when:

$$w(1-p_{i})u(\delta V_{i,j})>w(p_{i})u(X). $$

Putting this in terms of the unweighted value of V i, j and rearranging the terms, we obtain:

$$ \text{choose \textit{V} when: } V_{i,j}>\left(\frac{p_{i}}{1-p_{i}}\right)^{\frac{\gamma}{\alpha}}\frac{X}{\delta} $$

and equivalently:

$$ \text{choose \textit{V} when: }\frac{V_{i,j}}{\left(\frac{p_{i}}{1-p_{i}}\right)^{\frac{\gamma}{\alpha}}\frac{X}{\delta}}>1 $$

and taking the log of each side:

$$\text{choose \textit{V} when: } \ln(V_{i,j})-\ln\left(\left(\frac{p_{i}}{1-p_{i}}\right)^{\frac{\gamma}{\alpha}}\frac{X}{\delta}\right)>0. $$

We assume that the subject’s internal representation of the difference on the left of the inequality is corrupted by noise drawn as a random sample from a normal distribution with mean=0. Furthermore, we assume under Weber’s law that the SD of the distribution for each value of i is equal in log value. The probability of choosing the lottery containing V i, j is thus given by:

$$P_{i}(\text{choose }\textit{V}) = {\Phi}\left(\frac{\ln(V_{i,j})-\ln\left(\left(\frac{p_{i}}{1-p_{i}}\right)^{\frac{\gamma}{\alpha}}\frac{X}{\delta}\right)}{\sigma}\right). $$

Initial values for V i, j were derived by choosing five values for P i (choose V) that span the psychometric function: {.2, .35, .5, .65, .8}, and then solving:

$$V_{i,j}=\left(\frac{p_{i}}{1-p_{i}}\right)^{\frac{\gamma}{\alpha}} \frac{X}{\delta} \exp{\left(\sigma{\Phi}^{-1}\left(P_{i}(\text{choose }V)\right)\right)} $$

with parameter values: α = .65, γ = .5, and σ = .2 chosen to represent reasonable parameter estimates given a survey of estimates across many studies (Fox & Poldrack, 2009), and the initial value of δ set to 1. The maximum value of V i, j never exceeded $50 so that the prospect containing V i, j was never stochastically dominant.

Prospects were presented using the method of constant stimuli. Values of p i and their corresponding V i, j were chosen at random from each of the four probability and five value levels with equal numbers of trials from each level (i.e., five trials per probability/value pair) within each block. To avoid stereotyped responses, displayed values of V i, j were randomly jittered by an amount no more than ±1/4 of the minimum difference between any two values of V for the given block. To avoid response-side bias, the side with the lottery containing V was selected at random on each trial. Subjects indicated their preferred prospect on each trial by key press.

Subjects completed four 100-trial blocks in a single session. At the end of each block, estimated α, γ, σ, and δ were fit to the binned data from all preceding blocks by maximum likelihood where the estimated probability of choosing the prospect containing V i, j is given by:

$$\hat P_{i}(V_{i,j}) = {\Phi}\left(\frac{ln(V_{i,j})-ln\left(\left(\frac{p_{i}}{1-p_{i}}\right)^{\frac{\gamma}{\alpha}}\frac{X}{\delta}\right)}{\sigma}\right). $$

The resulting estimates of α, γ, σ, and δ were used to select new values of V i, j for use in the subsequent block. The fit parameters and weighting functions for each subject are shown in Fig. 2.

All subjects were debriefed following the task as to any strategy they may have employed. One subject indicated that they had merely calculated the expected gain of the prospects. Their data were excluded from the analyses and they did not continue with Experiment 3. In addition, five subjects employed ad hoc strategies for which the model above cannot account. Two subjects chose the lottery containing the higher probability and lower value, V, on more than 90 % of trials, a strategy which effectively ignores values. Three subjects chose the lottery containing the constant value X on the majority of trials when the probabilities associated with V and X were nearly equal, i.e., when p = .4, but seemed to employ more typical weightings of probabilities and values for other probability levels. These subjects’ data were also excluded and their participation was discontinued since the model above cannot account for these strategies nor can we make valid estimates of decision criteria in the subsequent experiment if such strategies are being employed. Note that these subjects were excluded not because they used strategies that are alternative to calculating the subjective utility of the prospects. Rather, we assume that all subjects, under general circumstances, subjectively weight probabilities and values in the way described by prospect theory. The ad hoc strategies employed simply make it impossible to measure their weighting functions without increasing the complexity of the model to account for idiosyncratic strategies.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Ackermann, J.F., Landy, M.S. Suboptimal decision criteria are predicted by subjectively weighted probabilities and rewards. Atten Percept Psychophys 77, 638–658 (2015). https://doi.org/10.3758/s13414-014-0779-z

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.3758/s13414-014-0779-z

Keywords

Navigation