Skip to main content
Log in

Challenging the association of Hegel with political realism: the contribution of Hegel’s methodological insights to a critique of realism and a richer understanding of war and statehood

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Journal of International Relations and Development Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper challenges the association of Hegel with political realism. Many approaches rely predominantly on the Philosophy of Right’s third part (the State) and on the Phenomenology of Spirit’s ‘master‒slave’ dialectic, classifying Hegel as a political realist who praises the state, glorifies war and dismisses international law. However, this oversimplifies Hegel’s thought and misinterprets his methodology. The thesis of this paper is that these misperceptions can be avoided once: (i) Hegel’s corpus is considered coherently; (ii) the context of his philosophical thought is taken into account; and (iii) his insights cease to be applied in a descriptive or prescriptive way. Hegel’s contribution will be revisited by way of treating the Phenomenology of Spirit as the point of departure to comprehend the Philosophy of Right. Approaching the Philosophy of Right through the Phenomenology’s emphasis on the forms of consciousness, spirit (Geist) and ethical life (Sittlichkeit), reveals the intellectual wealth of Hegel’s methodology while exposing the methodological flaws of realism.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an interesting interpretation of Hegel’s philosophy of history as linear yet unfamiliar, which associates Hegel with constructivism and postmodernism, see McKay and LaRoche (2017).

  2. Scholars such as Taylor adopt a ‘metaphysical’ interpretation of Hegel which associates the realm of nature with the human historical world of spirit according to which existence and truth derive from a cosmic substance ‘for the inner truth of things is that they flow from thought, that they are structured by rational necessity’ (Taylor 1975, p. 298). On the other hand, scholars such as Pippin and Pinkard adopt a ‘non-metaphysical’ interpretation. The former draws a distinction between nature and spirit which understates the metaphysical dimension of Hegel’s work arguing that ‘contrary to the rationalist tradition, human reason can attain non-empirical knowledge about what has come to be called recently our conceptual scheme and the concepts required for a scheme to count as one at all’ (Pippin 1989, p. 8).

  3. The approach this paper adopts is closer to Pinkard’s treatment of spirit as a form of social space. Specifically, Pinkard notes that ‘Spirit is a self-conscious form of life, it is a form of life which has developed various social practices for reflecting on what it takes to be authoritative for itself in terms of whether these practices live their own claims and achieve the aims that they set for themselves’ (Pinkard 1996, pp. 8‒9).

  4. Realism is often considered to describe the ‘world as it is, not as it ought to be’ (Jorgensen 2010, p. 78); therefore, the perception of realism as a normative (in an ethical sense) account of international relations might appear unconvincing. Nevertheless, the present study considers that realism accommodates a normative dimension. Normative is a broad term which refers to theories which tend to be prescriptive and concerned with changing or improving the world. Realism has a normative dimension if we focus on its ontological dimension. Specifically, the ontological component of (classical) realism is comprised of both an empirical (verifiable facts) and a metaphysical dimension which refers to ‘truths’ regarding our existence. The metaphysical one is premised on the claim that human nature is essentially bad (e.g. Hobbes) and a teleological or repetitive pattern of human history according to which states aspire to maximise their power (e.g. Morgenthau 1975). Both metaphysical claims affect a realist’s understanding of interstate relations and international law. As Hutchings notes, ‘the prescriptive element of normative international theory follows from its ontological and methodological claims’ (Hutchings 1999, p. 5). Furthermore, in spite of the fact that realism does not constitute ‘a single theoretical tradition but an interconnected series of themes […] elements of which can be found in the work of Niebuhr, Morgenthau and Carr […] they have all worked to reinforce a particular set of claims about the right way to organize and conduct international politics’ (ibid., p. 15) in a normative fashion.

  5. For a realist constructivist reading of Hegel, see also McKay and Levin (2015).

  6. Instead, Mansfield observed how, for Machiavelli, the notion of morality cannot be absent from politics but is context specific and such a critical understanding of morality should determine the actions of the political leader, reviving this as ‘a virtue which brings success in politics’ (Mansfield 1996, p. xiii). Carr who is often celebrated as a realist, yet his thought is much deeper and complicated, also makes another reference to morality. Carr writes that realism ‘lacked a finite goal, an emotional appeal and a right of moral judgment and a ground for action’ (Carr 2001, p. 89).

  7. In par. 29 (Hegel 1977, p. 17), Hegel argues that ‘Science sets forth this formative process in all its details and necessity, exposing the mature configuration of everything which has already been reduced to a moment and property of Spirit. But the length of this part has to be endured because each moment is necessary and further each moment has to be lingered over because each is itself a complete individual shape and one is only viewed in absolute perspective when its determinateness is regarded as a concrete whole’.

  8. To use Hegel’s words in par. 81, Zusatz 2, ‘[true philosophy] includes the sceptical principle as a subordinate function of its own in the shape of the dialectic. In contradiction to scepticism however, philosophy does not remain content with the purely negative result of the dialectic […] the negative as the result of the dialectic is at the same time the positive, it contains what it results from absorbed into itself and does not exist without it’. See Hegel (2010).

  9. ‘[T]he refutation must not come from the outside, that is it must not proceed from assumptions lying outside the system in question and which it does not accord with. The genuine refutation must penetrate the opponent’s stronghold and meet him on his own ground. No advantage is gained by attacking him somewhere else and meeting him where he is not’ (Hegel 1969, pp. 580‒581).

  10. A similar approach which defends a phenomenological reading of the Philosophy of Right was advanced by Hutchings (1999, pp. 98‒99).

  11. It should be reminded here that Hegel’s thought attracted diverse interpretations. Notably, scholars like McDowell (2007) and Taylor (1980) adopt a metaphysical interpretation of Hegel, whereas Pippin (1989) and Pinkard (1996) a non-metaphysical one.

  12. In the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, par. 131, Hegel argues that ‘appearance does not get away from Essence, but contains it as “show” […]. The essence is, in the first place, the sum total of the showing itself, shining in itself (inwardly); but, far from abiding in this inwardness, it comes as a ground forward into existence; and this existence being grounded not in itself, but on something else, is just appearance’ (Hegel 1991, p. 191).

  13. In the Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences, appearance and reality are examined from the prism of the form and content. According to Hegel, form and content are a unity of opposites. Unlike Fichte, Hegel does not identify the content with a ‘formless’ matter and form with the structure of that matter, since such a concept reduces content to a wholly abstract ‘thing-in-itself’ which is conducive to an idealist understanding of things. As Hegel (1991, p. 193) stresses in par. 133, ‘the essential point to keep in mind about the opposition of Form and Content is that the content is not formless, but has the form in its own self, quite as much as the form is external to it […]. We are here in presence, implicitly, of the absolute correlation of content and form: their reciprocal revulsion, so that content is nothing but the revulsion of form into content, and form nothing but the revulsion of content into form. This mutual revulsion is one of the most important laws of thought’.

  14. Fukuyama argued that evolution and historical progress are stimulated on two accounts. The first relates to the modern natural science which develops ‘a changing horizon of production capabilities for which capitalism proved to be the most efficient means’. The second is associated to the struggle of human beings for recognition which culminated in the French Declaration of the Rights of Man and Citizen, see Fukuyama (1989).

  15. It is worth noting that Fukuyama has indeed been influenced by Kojeve, but their approaches differ. In contrast to Kojeve, Fukuyama in his early work (1989) places substantive emphasis on liberal democracy and argues that the development of history resulted in a liberal state linked to capitalist economy. In his latest work Fukuyama insists that liberal democracies are the final form of human government, yet they can decay or go backwards, highlighting the role of identity politics which ‘can be used to divide but can also be used to integrate’ (Fukuyama 2018, p. 163).

  16. Reference should also be made here to Suzan Buck-Morss’ book Hegel, Haiti and Universal History (2009). Unlike Kojeve, one of the main arguments of Buck-Morss’ book is that Hegel’s master‒slave dialectic was inspired by the Haitian revolution when the former slaves declared their independence from Napoleon’s France.

  17. Terry Pinkard elaborates further on the link between the development of our consciousness with history, treating the contingency of history as ‘the infinite end of collective self-comprehension and different ways of being a human subject’ (Pinkard 2017, p. 167).

  18. There are certainly exceptions: military conscription still exists in countries like Israel and Greece.

  19. On the importance of context in the study of war see e.g. Van Ingen (2016).

References

  • Barton, Benjamin. 2017. Political Trust and the Politics of Security Engagement: China and the European Union in Africa. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bauman, Zygmut. 2001. Liquid Modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beitz, Charles R. 1999. Political Theory and International Relations. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentley, Lorne William. 2012. Clausewitz and German Idealism: The Influence of G.W.F. Hegel on ‘On War’. Berlin: BiblioScholar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, Thom. 2004. Hegel’s Theory of International Politics: A Reply to Jaeger. Review of International Studies 30 (1): 149–152.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, Thom. 2013. Hegel’s Political Philosophy: A Systematic Reading of The Philosophy of Right. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, Chris. 2009. Structural Realism, Classical Realism and Human Nature. International Relations 23 (2): 257–270.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchwalter, Andrew. 2012. Hegel and Global Justice. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buck-Morss, Suzan. 2009. Hegel, Haiti and Universal History. Pittsburch: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bull, Hedley. 1977. Anarchical Society. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, E.H. 2001. Twenty Years Crisis 1919‒1939: Introduction to the Study of International Relations. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coker, Christopher. 2005. The Unhappy Warrior. RUSI Journal 150 (6): 10–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cormier, Youri. 2014. Hegel and Clausewitz: Convergence on Method, Divergence on Ethics. International History Review 36 (2): 419–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, Michael. 2000. Realism and International Relations. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, C., T. Lindemann, and O. Jacob Sending. 2018. Frustrated sovereigns: the agency that makes the world go around. Review of International Studies 44 (5): 787–804.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiott, Daniel. 2013. Realist Thought and Humanitarian Intervention. International History Review 35 (4): 766–782.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, Francis. 1989. The End of History? National Interest 16: 3–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fukuyama, Francis. 2018. Identity: The Demand for Dignity and the Politics of Resentment. New York: MacMillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gat, Azar. 2001. The Origins of Military Thought: From the Enlightenment to Clausewitz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenhil, Brian. 2008. Recognition and Collective Identity Formation in International Politics. European Journal of International Relations 14: 343–368.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guzzini, Stefano. 2004. The Enduring Dilemmas of Realism in International Relations. European Journal of International Relations 10 (4): 533–568.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haslam, Jonathan. 2002. No Virtue like Necessity: Realist Thought in International Relations since Machiavelli. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 1949. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, translated by T.M. Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 1967. Hegel’s Philosophy of Right, translated by T.M. Knox. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 1969. Science of Logic, translated by A.V. Miller. London: Allen and Unwin.

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit, translated by A. V. Miller. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 1991. Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 2001. The Philosophy of History. Ontario: Batoche Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, Georg W.F. 2010. Encyclopedia of the Philosophical Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1995. The Struggle for Recognition. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchings, Kimberly. 1999. International Political Theory: Rethinking Ethics in a Global Era. London: SAGE Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jaeger, Hans-Martin. 2002. Hegel’s Reluctant Realism and the Transnationalism of Civil Society. Review of International Studies 28 (3): 497–517.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jorgensen, Knud Erik. 2010. International Relations Theory: A New Introduction. London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaldor, Mary. 2001. New & Old Wars: Organized Violence in a Global Era. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kalyvas, Stathis. 2006. The Logic of Violence in Civil War. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kappis, Vassilis. 2017. Greek-Israeli Security Cooperation: Dissonance in the EU CFSP? In Solidarity in the European Union: Challenges and Perspectives, ed. Angelos Giannakopoulos, 95–107. Tel-Aviv: Daniel Abraham Center for International and Regional Studies, Tel-Aviv University.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kojeve, Alexandre. 1980. Introduction to the Reading of Hegel, translated by James Nichols, Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

  • Krause, Keith, and Michael Williams. 1997. Critical Security Studies: Concepts and Cases. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacina, Bethany, and Nils Peter Gleditsch. 2005. Monitoring Trends in Global Combat. European Journal of Population 21 (2–3): 145–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebow, Richard Ned. 2008. Cultural Theory of International Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lebow, Richard Ned. 2010. Classical Realism. In International Relations Theories: Discipline and Diversity, ed. Tim Dunne, Milja Kurki, and Steve Smith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mansfield, Harvey. 1996. Machiavelli’s Virtue. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marx, Karl. 1993. Grundrisse. London Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John. 2007. The Apperceptive I and the Empirical Self: Towards a Heterodox Reading of “Lordship and Bondage” in Hegel’s Phenomenology. In Hegel: New Directions, ed. Katerina Deligiorgi, 33–48. Chesham: Acumen.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, Joseph, and Christopher David LaRoche. 2017. The Conduct of history in International Relations: Rethinking Philosophy of History in IR Theory. International Theory 9 (2): 203–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • McKay, Joseph, and Jamie Levin. 2015. A Hegelian Realist Constructivist Account of War, Identity, and State Formation. Journal of International Relations and Development 21 (1): 75–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mearsheimer, John. 1990. Back to the Future: Instability in Europe After the Cold War. International Security 15 (1): 5–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgenthau, Hans. 1975. Politics Among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace. New York: Alfred Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moskos, Charles. 1998. The American Soldier After the Cold War: Towards a Post-Modern Military?. Evaston: U.S. Army Research Institute for the Behavioral Social Sciences.

    Google Scholar 

  • Munkler, Herfried. 2004. The Wars of the 21st Century. ICRC 85 (849): 7–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neumann, Iver. 1996. Self and Other in International Relations. European Journal of International Relations 2 (2): 139–174.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, Edward. 2004. The New Wars Debate: A Historical Perspective is Needed. Security Dialogue 35 (2): 173–189.

    Google Scholar 

  • Onuf, Nicholas. 2013. Making Sense, Making Worlds: Constructivism in Social Theory and International Relations. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paipais, Vassilios. 2011. Self and Other in Critical International Theory: Assimilation, Incommensurability and the Paradox of Critique. Review of International Studies 37 (1): 121–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paret, Peter. 1976. Clausewitz and the State: The Man his Theories and his Times. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinkard, Terry. 1996. Hegel’s Phenomenology: The Sociality of Reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinkard, Terry. 2017. Does History Make Sense? Hegel on the Historical Shapes of Justice. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pippin, Robert B. 1989. Hegel’s Idealism: The Satisfaction of Self-consciousness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, Martin. 2005. War and Genocide: Organised Killing in Modern Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singer, Peter. 2001. Hegel: A Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stace, W.T. 1924. The Philosophy of Hegel: A Systematic Exposition. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1975. Hegel. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1980. Hegel and Modern Society. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Ingen, Michiel. 2016. Conflict Studies and Causality: Critical Realism and the Nomothetic/Idiographic Divide in the Study of Civil War. Civil Wars 18 (4): 387–416.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vincent, Andrew. 1983. The Hegelian State, and International Politics. Review of International Studies 9 (3): 191–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walker, R.B.J. 1993. Inside/Outside: International Relations as Political Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, Kenneth. 1979. Theory of International Politics. London: McGraw-Hill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waltz, Kenneth. 1988. The Origins of War in Neorealist Theory. Journal of Interdisciplinary History 18 (4): 615–628.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, Alexander. 1995. Constructing International Politics. International Security 20 (1): 71–81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendt, Alexander. 2003. Why a World State is Inevitable. European Journal of International Relations 9 (4): 491–542.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Robert R. 1997. Hegel’s Ethics of Recognition. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank Alex Callinicos, Kimberly Hutchings, Gary Browning and Bill Bowring who offered invaluable feedback at an early stage. Moreover, I would like to thank Richard Ned Lebow, Tarak Barkawi and Adrian Blau who had the patience to read the manuscript and provide me with comments that improved it. Importantly, I would also like to thank Chris Blunt who had the patience to read the manuscript thoroughly, prompting me to proceed to a number of important corrections. Finally, I would like to thank the editor and the anonymous reviewers for their insights.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Athanasios Gkoutzioulis.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Gkoutzioulis, A. Challenging the association of Hegel with political realism: the contribution of Hegel’s methodological insights to a critique of realism and a richer understanding of war and statehood. J Int Relat Dev 23, 970–995 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1057/s41268-019-00177-5

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/s41268-019-00177-5

Keywords

Navigation