Skip to main content
Log in

Justification, critique and deliberative legitimacy: The limits of mini-publics

  • Article
  • Published:
Contemporary Political Theory Aims and scope

Abstract

I contend that the popular ‘mini-publics’ approach to implementing deliberation in practice is unable to realize deliberative democracy in a way that fulfills the deliberative democratic standard of legitimacy. Deliberative democratic legitimacy requires citizens to actively claim their right to justification against government authorities, which the capacity of mini-public deliberation to serve authorities sidelines or even undermines. I propose an alternative account of deliberative democracy with an eye specifically to legitimacy: deliberative democracy as a political culture. On this view, it is cultural aspects (the ethos, social norms and self-understandings that shape and constrain political processes), not institutional specificities, that are decisive for deliberation fulfilling its legitimacy ambition. Deliberative democratic theory ought to conceptualize ways of opening up social and political space for widespread citizen-led engagement and critical scrutiny of authorities, rather than striving for the development of institutional short-cuts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Note that, based on this definition of democratic legitimacy, legitimacy may not be the only norm democratic polities would or should be striving for. In particular, while the dimension of deliberative democracy I have outlined deems a certain degree of interrupting, indeed unsettling state authority to be imperative as a basic precondition for the (never fully achieved but temporarily acceptable degree of) legitimacy of this authority, this may simultaneously be undesirable from the perspective of ‘getting things done’, that is, responding to urgent political issues and ensuring a ‘smooth’ running of politics. This poses the question what the right balance ought to be between the norm of legitimacy and other norms such as efficiency or effectiveness of governance; a question which is, however, beyond the scope of this particular article and argument. Here, it suffices to note that in as much as legitimacy ought to be established in democratic polities, it demands critical scrutiny of authority by those subject to it; and where this may be seen to disrupt policymaking in undesirable ways, this opens up the question of the right balance between legitimacy and other norms, rather than implying (based on this reason alone) a need to revise the definition of legitimacy.

  2. Note that this ideal description refers to the overall cultural character of the polity; I am not here making an argument about whether specific instances of deliberation or justification ought to conform to the ideal type of not. Even if specific instances might take, for instance, activist (Young, 2001), partisan (White and Ypi, 2011), non-public (Chambers, 2004), or interested (Mansbridge et al., 2010) forms, they might, as these authors have highlighted, still contribute positively to a deliberative culture overall. However, since my argument is precisely that what matters is the overall cultural character of a society as a whole, considering such questions relating to specific instances of deliberation is beyond the scope of this article.

References

  • Aasen, M. and Vatn, A. (2013) Deliberation on GMOs: A study of how a citizens’ jury affects the citizens’ attitudes. Environmental Values 22(4): 461–481.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Appadurai, A. (2004) The capacity to aspire: Culture and the terms of recognition. In: V. Rao and M. Walton (eds.) Culture and Public Action. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, pp. 59–84.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (ed.) (1996) Toward a deliberative model of democratic legitimacy. In: Democracy and Difference. Contesting the Boundaries of the Political. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 67–94.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R.J. (1995) The retrieval of the democratic ethos. Review of Japanese Culture and Society 7: 1–12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Birch, A.H. (2001) The Concepts and Theories of Modern Democracy. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Brown, M.B. (2006) Survey article: Citizen panels and the concept of representation. Journal of Political Philosophy 14(2): 203–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Button, M. and Mattson, K. (1999) Deliberative democracy in practice: Challenges and prospects for civic deliberation. Polity 31(4): 609–637.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S. (2000) A culture of publicity. In: S. Chambers and A. Costain (eds.) Deliberation, Democracy, and the Media. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield, pp. 193–208.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S. (2004) Behind closed doors: Publicity, secrecy, and the quality of deliberation. Journal of Political Philosophy 12(4): 389–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S. (2009) Rhetoric and the public sphere: Has deliberative democracy abandoned mass democracy? Political Theory 37(3): 323–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S. (2010) Theories of political justification. Philosophy Compass 5(11): 893–903.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S.A. (2013) The Lessons of Rancière. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chambers, S.A. (2014) Bearing Society in Mind: Theories and Politics of the Social Formation. London: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chappell, Z. (2011) Justifying deliberative democracy: Are two heads always wiser than one? Contemporary Political Theory 10(1): 78–101.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, J. (1996) Procedure and substance in deliberative democracy. In: S. Benhabib (ed.) Democracy and Difference. Contesting the Boundaries of the Political. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 95–119.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delap, C. (2001) Citizens’ juries: Reflections on the UK experience. PLA Notes 40: 39–42, http://pubs.iied.org/pdfs/G01929.pdf, accessed 25 December 2015.

  • Dryzek, J.S. (1990) Discursive Democracy. Politics, Policy, and Political Science. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. (2000) Deliberative Democracy and Beyond. Liberals, Critics, Contestations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. (2001) Legitimacy and economy in deliberative democracy. Political Theory 29(5): 651–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. (2010) Foundations and Frontiers of Deliberative Governance. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S., Goodin, R.E., Tucker, A. and Reber, B. (2009) Promethean elites encounter precautionary publics: The case of GM foods. Science, Technology and Human Values 34(3): 263–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dryzek, J.S. and Tucker, A. (2008) Deliberative innovation to different effect: Consensus conferences in Denmark, France, and the United States. Public Administration Review 68(5): 864–876.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elstub, S. (2014) Mini-publics: Issues and cases. In: S. Elstub and P. McLaverty (eds.) Deliberative Democracy: Issues and Cases. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elstub, S. and McLaverty, P. (eds.) (2014) Introduction: Issues and cases in deliberative democracy. In: Deliberative Democracy: Issues and Cases. Edinburgh, UK: Edinburgh University Press, pp. 166–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • Escobar, O. (2015) Scripting deliberative policy-making: Dramaturgic policy analysis and engagement know-how. Journal of Comparative Policy Analysis 17(3): 269–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Estlund, D. (1997) Beyond fairness and deliberation: The epistemic dimension of democratic authority. In: J. Bohman and W. Rehg (eds.) Deliberative Democracy: Essays on Reason and Politics. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, pp. 173–204.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, J.S. (1999) Toward deliberative democracy: Experimenting with an ideal. In: S.L. Elkin and K.E. Soltan (eds.) Citizen Competence and Democratic Institutions. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press, pp. 279–290.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fishkin, J.S., Luskin, R.C. and Jowell, R. (2000) Deliberative polling and public consultation. Parliamentary Affairs 53(4): 657–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. (2001) The rule of reasons. Three models of deliberative democracy. Ratio Juris 14(4): 345–378.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forst, R. (2012) The Right to Justification. Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freschi, A.C. and Mete, V. (2009) The political meanings of institutional deliberative experiments: Findings on the Italian case. Sociologica 2(3): 1–54.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fung, A. (2003) Recipes for public spheres: Eight institutional choices and their consequences. Journal of Political Philosophy 11(3): 338–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fung, A. (2011) Minipublics: Designing institutions for effective deliberation and accountability. In: S. Odugbemi and T. Lee (eds.) Accountability through Public Opinion. From Inertia to Public Action. Washington DC: The World Bank, pp. 183–202.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fung, A. and Wright, E.O. (2001) Deepening democracy: Innovations in empowered participatory governance. Politics & Society 29(1): 5–41.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. (2008) Innovating Democracy. Democratic Theory and Practice After the Deliberative Turn. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. (2012) How can deliberative democracy get a grip? The Political Quarterly 83(4): 806–811.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodin, R.E. and Dryzek, J.S. (2006) Deliberative impacts: The macro-political uptake of mini-publics. Politics & Society 34(2): 219–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grönlund, K., Bächtiger, A. and Setälä, M. (2014) Deliberative Mini-Publics: Involving Citizens in the Democratic Process. Colchester, UK: ECPR Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grönlund, K., Setälä, M. and Herne, K. (2010) Deliberation and civic virtue: Lessons from a citizen deliberation experiment. European Political Science Review 2(1): 95–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gutmann, A. and Thompson, D. (1996) Democracy and Disagreement. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1996) Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, UK: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartz-Karp, J. and Carson, L. (2009) Putting the people into politics: The Australian citizens’ parliament. International Journal of Public Participation 3(1): 9–31.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendriks, C.M., Dryzek, J.S. and Hunold, C. (2007) Turning up the heat: Partisanship in deliberative innovation. Political Studies 55(2): 362–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Horkheimer, M. (1972) Critical Theory: Selected Essays. New York: Herder and Herder.

    Google Scholar 

  • Joly, P.-B., Marris, C., Assouline, G. and Lemarié, J. (1999) Quand les candides évaluent les OGM: nouveau modèle de « démocratie technique » ou mise en scène du débat public? Annales des Mines 14. Avril 12–21.

  • Karpowitz, C.F., Raphael, C. and Hammond, IV A.S. (2009) Deliberative democracy and inequality: Two cheers for enclave deliberation among the disempowered. Politics & Society 37(4): 576–615.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • King, C.S. (2013) Economic theories of democratic legitimacy and the normative role of an ideal consensus. Politics, Philosophy & Economics 12(2): 156–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knops, A. (2006) Delivering deliberation’s emancipatory potential. Political Theory 34(5): 594–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kompridis, N. (2006) Critique and Disclosure: Critical Theory between Past and Future. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafont, C. (2006) Is the ideal of deliberative democracy coherent? In: S. Besson and J.L. Martí (eds.) Deliberative Democracy and its Discontents. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate, pp. 3–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lafont, C. (2015) Deliberation, participation, and democratic legitimacy: Should deliberative mini-publics shape public policy? Journal of Political Philosophy 23(1): 40–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luskin, R.C., Fishkin, J.S. and Jowell, R. (2002) Considered opinions: Deliberative polling in Britain. British Journal of Political Science 32(3): 455–487.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, M.K. and Warren, M.E. (2014) Two trust-based uses of minipublics in democratic systems. In: J. Parkinson and J. Mansbridge (eds.) Deliberative Systems. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, pp. 95–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manin, B. (1987) On legitimacy and political deliberation. Political Theory 15(3): 338–368.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mansbridge, J. et al (2010) The place of self-interest and the role of power in deliberative democracy. Journal of Political Philosophy 18(1): 64–100.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Niemeyer, S. (2011) The emancipatory effect of deliberation: Empirical lessons from mini-publics. Politics & Society 39(1): 103–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Normann Andersen, V. and Hansen, K.M. (2007) How deliberation makes better citizens: The Danish deliberative poll on the euro. European Journal of Political Research 46(4): 531–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, J. (2003) Legitimacy problems in deliberative democracy. Political Studies 51(1): 180–196.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, J. (2006) Deliberating in the Real World: Problems of Legitimacy in Deliberative Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Parkinson, J. and Mansbridge, J. (eds.) (2012) Deliberative Systems. Deliberative Democracy at the Large Scale. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pateman, C. (2012) Participatory democracy revisited. Perspectives on Politics 10(1): 7–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rostbøll, C.F. (2008) Emancipation of accommodation? Habermasian vs. Rawlsian deliberative democracy. Philosophy & Social Criticism 34(7): 707–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rostbøll, C.F. (2009) Dissent, criticism, and transformative political action in deliberative democracy. Critical Review of International Social and Political Philosophy 12(1): 19–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rostbøll, C.F. (2011) Deliberative Freedom. Deliberative Democracy as Critical Theory. Albany, NY: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryfe, D.M. (2005) Does deliberative democracy work? Annual Review of Political Science 8: 49–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sanders, L.M. (1997) Against deliberation. Political Theory 25(3): 347–376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sass, J. and Dryzek, J.S. (2014) Deliberative cultures. Political Theory 42(1): 3–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Scheuerman, W.E. (1999) Between radicalism and resignation: Democratic theory in Habermas’s Between Facts and Norms. In: P. Dews (ed.) Habermas: A Critical Reader. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 153–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, I. (2003) The State of Democratic Theory. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simmons, A.J. (2001) Justification and Legitimacy. Essays on Rights and Obligations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, G. (2009) Democratic Innovations. Designing Institutions for Citizen Participation. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, G. and Wales, C. (2000) Citizens’ juries and deliberative democracy. Political Studies 48(1): 51–65.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steiner, J. (2008) Concept stretching: The case of deliberation. European Political Science 7(2): 186–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Susen, S. (2009) Between emancipation and domination: Habermasian reflections on the empowerment and disempowerment of the human subject. Pli 20: 80–110.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tucker, A. (2008) Pre-emptive democracy: Oligarchic tendencies in deliberative democracy. Political Studies 56(1): 127–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warren, M.E. (2009) Governance-driven democratization. Critical Policy Studies 3(1): 3–13.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, J. and Ypi, L. (2011) On partisan political justification. American Political Science Review 105(2): 381–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, I.M. (2000) Inclusion and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, I.M. (2001) Activist challenges to deliberative democracy. Political Theory 29(5): 670–690.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The author is grateful to Nicole Curato, John Dryzek, Fabian Freyenhagen, Bob Goodin, Avia Pasternak and Hugh Ward for valuable comments on previous versions of this article; as well as to all participants at the Australian National University Centre for Deliberative Democracy and Global Governance and the Sydney Political Theory Workshop (SPTW) seminars, especially Lyn Carson, Paul Patton and David Schlosberg, for their generous feedback on her presentations. She would also like to thank the editor and the two anonymous reviewers for Contemporary Political Theory for their very helpful remarks.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Böker, M. Justification, critique and deliberative legitimacy: The limits of mini-publics. Contemp Polit Theory 16, 19–40 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2016.11

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1057/cpt.2016.11

Keywords

Navigation