Skip to main content

Enlightenment Moral Theory and British Conservatism

  • Chapter
Conservatism and Pragmatism
  • 179 Accesses

Abstract

The thematic unity to the moral and political theory of the Enlightenment expresses itself as an extension of the method of the Scientific Revolution. The Scientific Revolution was paradigmatic for ethical theories which followed it. Once Greek teleology and metaphysics lost their general support, ethics underwent a revolution on par with cosmology. The modern era dispensed with Aristotle’s teleological account of humanity’s natural purpose and end in happiness. For Aristotle, the final cause of man was flourishing, and virtue was “an activity which completed or perfected the individual.”1 In place of this view, the Scientific Revolution posited a mechanistic view of man as a part of nature governed by universal and abstract laws. The ethical question became how to subsume any given act under the proper law or to find the proper law which guides any given act. Thus, the paradigm was of “discrete, individual events obeying absolute, universal laws.”2 Enlightenment moral theories of several sorts have this paradigm in common: they seek to apply universal moral principles to specific acts in order to count them as good or bad. Furthermore, they isolate the act from the general character of the actor and largely from the particular morally problematic situation. Thus, a moral life did not concern the happiness of the individual reflected by his character or virtuous activity over his lifetime, but would only be the “succession of events obeying a universal law.”3

The rules of morality … are not the conclusion of our reason

David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature.*

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. * David Hume, (2007) A Treatise of Human Nature, (Sioux Falls: NuVision Publications), p. 326

    Book  Google Scholar 

  2. Thomas Alexander, (1993) “John Dewey and the Moral Imagination: Beyond Putnam and Rorty Toward a Postmodern Ethics,” Transactions of the Charles Sanders Peirce Society, 29(3), p. 372.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Mary Warnock, Ed. (1938) Utilitarianism, On Liberty, Essay on Bentham: Together with Selected Writings of Jeremy Bentham and John Austin, (New York: New American Library,) p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Warnock cites paragraph 54 from Jeremy Bentham, (1938) Fragments on Government, in The Works of Jeremy Bentham, Ed. J. Bowring, (London: Publisher name).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Richard A. Posner, (1981) The Economics of Justice, (Boston: Harvard University Press) p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  6. John Stuart Mill, (1987) Utilitarianism, (Buffalo: Prometheus Books) p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Immanuel Kant, Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, Trans. Lewis Beck White, (Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall, 1997), p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Immanuel Kant, (1949) “On the Relation of Theory and Practice in Constitutional Law,” in The Philosophy of Kant: Immanuel Kant’s Moral and Political Writings, Ed. Carl Friedrich, (New York: The Modern Library) p. 414.

    Google Scholar 

  9. David Hume, A Treatise Concerning Human Nature, (Sioux Falls: NuVision Publications), p. 326.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Thomas Dixon, (2003) From Passions to Emotions: The Creation of a Secular Psychological Category, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press) p. 94.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  11. Peter Baumann, (1999) “The Scottish Pragmatist? The Dilemma of Common Sense and the Pragmatist Way Out,” Reid Studies, 2(2), p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Thomas Dixon, Ed. (2010) Thomas Brown Selected Philosophical Writings, (Exeter: Imprint) p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  13. George Santayana, (1968) “Tradition and Practice,” in Santayana in America, Ed. Richard Colton Lynn (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World) p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Steven J. Lenzner, (1991) “Strauss’s Three Burkes: The Problem of Edmund Burke in Natural Right and History,” Political Theory, 19(3), p. 367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. Edmund Burke, (1986) Reflections on the Revolution in France, (London: Penguin Books) p. 153.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Vincent Colapietro, (1997) “Tradition: First Steps Toward a Pragmatic Clarification,” in Philosophy in Experience, Eds Richard Hart and Douglas R. Anderson (New York: Fordham University Press) p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Copyright information

© 2014 Seth Vannatta

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Vannatta, S. (2014). Enlightenment Moral Theory and British Conservatism. In: Conservatism and Pragmatism. Palgrave Macmillan, London. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137466839_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics