Skip to main content

Defining and Implementing a Law of Persons

  • Chapter
Radicalizing Rawls

Part of the book series: Philosophy, Public Policy, and Transnational Law ((PPPTL))

  • 118 Accesses

Abstract

A cosmopolitan approach to global justice of the kind I have sought to begin elaborating here offers a distinctive perspective on human rights, toleration, and the use of force. The heart of a Law of Persons embraced by cosmopolitan deliberators would be a substantial array of human rights protections, including safeguards for “liberal” human rights—the Rawlsian equal basic liberties, several further guarantees, and a general presumption of liberty (Part II). These protections would likely impose more extensive limits on the use of force than Rawls’s Law of Peoples (Part III). Thus, they would constrain the methods liberals could reasonably use to influence the behavior of nonliberals—precluding sanctions and military interventions—even as they also clearly limited liberal tolerance of nonliberal societies (Part IV). A Law of Persons would exhibit significant similarities with, but also significant differences from, a Rawlsian Law of Peoples (Part V).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 19.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 29.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Samuel Freeman, The Law of Peoples, Social Cooperation, Human Rights, and Distributive Justice, in Justice and Global Politics 29, 38 (Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller Jr. & Jeffrey Paul eds., 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  2. John RawlS, The Law of Peoples, in Collected Papers 529, 554–55 (Samuel Freeman ed., 1999).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See, e.g., James W. Nickel, Are Human Rights Mainly Implemented by Intervention?, in Rawls’s Law of Peoples: A Realistic Utopia? at 263 (Rex Martin & David A. Reidy eds., 2006).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. David Luban, A Theory of Crimes against Humanity, 29 YaLe J. Int’ll. 85 (2004).

    Google Scholar 

  5. There is also a plausible case to be made that globally (but also, surely, domestically) specific “prohibitions on theft and fraud, provisions for enforcing contracts,” and other protections for voluntary exchange might be embraced in an original position not unlike Rawls’s; see Leif Wenar, Contractualism and Global Economic Justice, in GloBAl JusticE 76, 89 (Thomas W. Pogge ed., 2001). Wenar’s focus is on a global original position in which people are represented as consumers, producers, and owners, and he envisions a range of other, more specific, economic regulations that might also be endorsed. It is plausible to think that a number of the constraints Wenar contemplates might be embraced as natural duties in a Rawlsian original position; even though people in such an original position would surely think of themselves in more than narrowly economic terms, they would recognize the centrality of economic interactions to the achievement of their other goals and might well proceed accordingly.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. Howard F. Chang, The Economics of International Labor Migration and the Case for Global Distributive Justice in Liberal Political Theory, 41 Cornell Int’L L.J. 1, 20–24 (2008) (responding to Rawlsian and related worries about open immigration policies

    Google Scholar 

  7. Fernando R. Tesôn, Brain Drain, 45 San Diego L. Rev. 899 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Michelle A. Mckinley, Conviviality, Cosmopolitan Citizenship, and Hospitality, 5 UNbouNd 55, 64–68 (2009).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See John M. Finnis, Reason, Revelation, Universality, and Particularity in Ethics, 53 Am. J. Juris. 23, 42–45 (2008).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Richard W. Miller, The Interests of the Governed and the Interests of Humanity: The Moral Importance of Borders, 90 B.U.L. Rev. 1785, 1801 n. 35 (2010).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Contra Leif Wenar, Why Rawls Is Not a Cosmopolitan Liberal, in RAwLs’s LAw oF PeopLes: A ReAListic UtopiA? 95, 109 (Rex Martin & David A. Reidy eds., 2006); cf. id. at 113 n.42. Wenar apparently expects the reader to regard the US government’s invasion of Iraq as obviously appropriate, so that a principle that ruled it out, or that precluded actions reasonably undertaken in connection with it, would seem uncontroversially mistaken.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Darrell Cole, 09.11.01: Death before Dishonor or Dishonor before Death: Christian Just War, Terrorism, and Supreme Emergency, 16 Notre DAme J.L. Ethics & Pub. PoL’y 81, 93–98 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  13. cf. David S. Koller, The Moral Imperative: Toward a Human Rights-Based Law of War, 46 Harv. Int’L L.J. 231 (2005).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Even if tactical nuclear weapons proved easier to deliver or less costly than conventional weapons, it seems clear that individual deliberators would not regard these considerations as at least ordinarily justifying their use, given the risks their employment could pose to noncombatants. Cf. Lionel K. McPherson, Excessive Force in War: A “Golden Rule” Test, 7 Theoretical Inq. L. 81 (2006).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Alec Walen, The Significance of Rawls’s Law of Peoples, 6 Int’l Legal Theory 51, 53 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Cf. Thomas W. Pogge, Rawls on International Justice, 51 PhiL. Q. 246, 248 (2001).

    Google Scholar 

  17. David Schmidtz, Separateness, Suffering, and Moral Theory, in Person, PoLis, Planet: EssAys in AppLied Philosophy 145 (2008)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Neera K. Badhwar, International Aid: When Giving Becomes a Vice, in Justice and Global PoLitics 69 (Ellen Frankel Paul, Fred D. Miller Jr. & Jeffrey Paul eds., 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  19. This is likely to be particularly true with respect to the interests of women; cf. Catherine Powell, Lifting Our Veil of Ignorance: Culture, Constitutionalism, and Women’s Human Rights in Post-September 11 America, 57 Hastings L.J. 331 (2005).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Which is not to say that this is an option Rawls would necessarily endorse; see, e.g., A. John Simmons, Disobedience and Its Objects, 90 B.U.L. REv. 1805, 1827 n.103 (2010).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Of course, nonliberals might offer incentives to liberals to encourage them to adopt their ways of life; see Mortimer Sellers, The Law of Peoples, 6 Int’l LegaL Theory 44, 48–49 (2000).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Copyright information

© 2014 Gary Chartier

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Chartier, G. (2014). Defining and Implementing a Law of Persons. In: Radicalizing Rawls. Philosophy, Public Policy, and Transnational Law. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/9781137382979_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics