Skip to main content

Recognition, Identity and Subjectivity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory

Part of the book series: Political Philosophy and Public Purpose ((POPHPUPU))

Abstract

The term “recognition” has in the last two or three decades become the centre point of an extraordinary amount of theoretical activity among critical theorists and social and political philosophers. It is also at the centre of a great deal of conceptual ambivalence and often theoretical confusion as not all authors mean the same thing with the term and as there is often inadequate attention to the different concepts at stake. In this chapter, the author maps central parts of the conceptual and theoretical landscape around the term “recognition”, which is relevant for critical theory, and discuss some of the main contemporary authors on the theme: Axel Honneth, Charles Taylor, Nancy Fraser and Judith Butler.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 189.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 249.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Williams (1992, 1997) and Ikäheimo (2007, 2014).

  2. 2.

    See Hegel’s famous story of “the master and slave” in Hegel (1979: 111–119); and Hegel (2007: 152–164). For an interpretation, see Ikäheimo (2014).

  3. 3.

    When someone I love is happy, this makes me happy too, but this does not mean that my happiness is my reason to love her.

  4. 4.

    There can be informal normative expectations or norms for example that parents ought to love their children, but this does not mean that they should to love their children because of these normative expectations or norms. On the contrary: if a parent would say that he loves his children because there is a norm that one ought to, he would likely, and justifiably, be scolded for not really loving his children.

  5. 5.

    This is to say that gratitude is the appropriate response to love. On gratitude as a form of recognition, see Ricoeur (2005, 232–263).

  6. 6.

    On the “first”, “second” and “third generation” of the Frankfurt School, see Anderson (1995).

  7. 7.

    Honneth’s theory has since The Struggle for Recognition gone through various phases of experimentation and development, most importantly in his debate with Nancy Fraser (Fraser and Honneth 2003), where he starts conceiving of forms of recognition in a more historicist vein, as bound up with historically and culturally varying norms of recognition or “recognition orders”; in Reification (Honneth 2008), where Honneth introduces “below” the three forms or spheres of recognition a more foundational form of recognition; and in Freedom’s Right (Honneth 2014), where the concept of recognition is replaced by the concept of “social freedom” as the critical master concept. See Zurn (2015).

  8. 8.

    See also Taylor (1989).

  9. 9.

    See Taylor (1995: 71, note 41).

  10. 10.

    See however Zurn’s criticism of Honneth in this regard in Zurn (2000: 121).

  11. 11.

    Fraser and Honneth engaged in an extensive critical debate on the strengths and weaknesses of their respective theories in Fraser and Honneth (2003). On Honneth’s, Taylor’s and Fraser’s accounts of recognition, see also Thompson (2006). On Fraser, see Olson (2008).

  12. 12.

    Both examples, with minor modification from Honneth (2007): 325.

  13. 13.

    Butler follows Alexandre Kojève’s interpretation of Hegel according to which all human desire is “desire for recognition” (Butler 1987: 76, 2004: 2, 31, 236). For a critique of this Kojèvean line of interpretation, see Williams (1992: 366–412).

  14. 14.

    For example, whereas in The Psychic Life of Power (Butler 1997) Butler thinks of this partly in terms of Nietzschean and Foucauldian ideas of guilt so that “recognition” can only result from or be earned through an acceptance of guilt and thus internalization of the “law” according to which one is guilty, in Giving an Account of Oneself (Butler 2005: 15) Butler distances herself from this “punitive scene”.

  15. 15.

    Butler 1997, pp. 6–8.

  16. 16.

    How does this relate to the distinction made above between horizontal “recognition mediated by norms” on the one hand, and “purely intersubjective” recognition? Though purely intersubjective recognition such as love in the exact sense discussed above is not recognition of someone as a bearer of a right to love prescribed by a norm and thus not mediated by norms in this way, there may be other ways in which it is mediated by norms affecting the “loveability” of individuals or influencing people’s perceptions of and reaction patterns towards each other and thus the likelihood that they will develop attitudes of love towards each other. Note that Butler’s own use of the term “love” is broader than the one used in this article (see Butler 2004: 57–74).

  17. 17.

    Since vertical upwards recognition of norms implies or is more or less the same thing as recognizing or “respecting” others as bearers of the rights, duties and other deontic powers that the norms prescribe, the basic structure of norm-governed life thus includes: (a) vertical upwards recognition of norms (whether institutionalized or informal), (b) horizontal recognition mediated by norms between individuals and (c) horizontal purely intersubjective recognition between individuals as authorities of the norms.

  18. 18.

    For more on recognition and critical theory, see Schmidt am Busch (2011). On recognition and social ontology, see Ikäheimo and Laitinen (2011).

Bibliography

  • Althusser, Louis. 1971 [1969]. Ideology and ideological state apparatuses. In Lenin and philosophy and other essays. New York/London: Monthly Review Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anderson, Joel. 1995. Translator’s introduction. In The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts, ed. Axel Honneth, x–xxi. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making it explicit—Reasoning, representing and discursive commitment. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 1987. Subjects of desire—Hegelian Reflections in twentieth-century France. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. The psychic life of power. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Undoing gender. New York/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Giving an account of oneself. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Deranty, Jean-Philippe. 2009. Beyond communication—A critical study of Axel Honneth’s social philosophy. Leiden: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fraser, Nancy, and Axel Honneth. 2003. Redistribution or recognition? A political-philosophical exchange. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, Martin, and Axel Honneth. 2006. Paradoxes of capitalism. Constellations 13(1): 41–58.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegel, G.W.F. 1979 [1807]. Phenomenology of spirit. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007 [1831]. Hegel’s philosophy of mind. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honneth, Axel. 1995 [1992]. The struggle for recognition—The moral grammar of social conflicts. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Recognition as ideology. In Recognition and power: Axel Honneth and the tradition of critical theory, ed. Bert van den Brink and David Owen. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Reification—A new look at an old idea. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014 [2011]. Freedom’s right—The social foundations of democratic life. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikäheimo, Heikki. 2007. Recognizing persons. Journal of Consciousness Studies 14(5–6): 224–247.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Hegel’s concept of recognition—What is it? In Recognition—German idealism as an ongoing challenge, ed. Christian Krijnen, 11–38. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ikäheimo, Heikki, and Arto Laitinen. 2011. Recognition and social ontology. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • McNay, Lois. 2008. Against recognition. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olson, Kevin (ed.). (2008) Adding insult to injury. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinkard, Terry. 1994. Hegel’s phenomenology—The sociality of reason. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, Paul. 2005. The course of recognition. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmidt am Busch, Hans-Christoph. 2011. Anerkennung als Prinzip der kritischen Theorie. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John. 1995. The construction of social reality. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Making the social world—The structure of human civilization. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Siep, Ludwig. 2014 [1979]. Anerkennung als Prinzip der praktischen Philosophie. Hamburg: Felix Meiner.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, Charles. 1989. The sources of the self—The making of the modern identity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. The politics of recognition. In Multiculturalism—Examining the politics of recognition, ed. Amy Guttman. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, Simon. 2006. The political theory of recognition—A critical introduction. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, Robert. 1992. Recognition: Fichte and Hegel on the other. New York: Suny Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Hegel’s ethics of recognition. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurn, Christopher. 2000. Anthropology and normativity: A critique of Axel Honneth’s ‘formal conception of ethical life’. Philosophy and Social Criticism 26(1): 115–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Axel Honneth—A critical theory of the social. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ikäheimo, H. (2017). Recognition, Identity and Subjectivity. In: Thompson, M. (eds) The Palgrave Handbook of Critical Theory. Political Philosophy and Public Purpose. Palgrave Macmillan, New York. https://doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-55801-5_26

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics