Skip to main content
Log in

A causal argument for physicalism

  • Article Symposium
  • Published:
Asian Journal of Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Although physicalism is a dominant position in contemporary philosophy of mind and metaphysics, there are surprisingly very few serious arguments for physicalism, which may contribute to the revival of anti-physicalism in recent decades. In this article, I develop a causal argument for physicalism in general, inspired by the causal argument for reductive physicalism. By comparing each pair of premises, I argue that, while the causal argument for reductive physicalism is controversial, the causal argument for physicalism simpliciter is promising.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Very unlikely a single elementary particle posited by ideal physics is able to instantiate mental phenomena; only the aggregations and configurations of elementary particles can do so. Hence, the grounding bases of mental properties (and other higher-level properties) should be the aggregations and configurations of elementary physical properties—or in Jaegwon Kim’s words, “micro-based properties” (Kim, 1998: 84). Although configurations of elementary physical properties are macroscopic, they are still physical properties in the narrow sense, conceptually distinct from those properties studied by special sciences (e.g., biological, neurological, and physiological properties).

  2. When an event c that instantiates a property F causes an effect e in virtue of having F, I will say that F is causally relevant to e. Here, I assume that properties play a significant role in causation—to assume so is not to deny the causal efficacy of other categories (events, objects, tropes). I myself accept an ecumenist view of causation, according to which causation involves the cooperation of tokens and types.

  3. I use the term “causal overdetermination” in a broad way: A and B causally overdetermine the effect E if and only if A and B are, or figure in, two distinct and sufficient causes of E.

  4. An earlier version of this argument is briefly mentioned in my (2020b).

  5. In this article, I leave it open whether all kinds of mental properties (sensations, perceptions, beliefs, desires) are causally efficacious. The soundness of the two causal arguments requires only that at least some mental properties are causally relevant to the effects.

  6. Physical processes are not necessary for causation, either. Consider some examples of negative causation: a person’s suffering heart damage causes her to die; and kicking over a chair causes a bottle on the chair to fall. Those examples are robust cases of causation. But in such cases, the causal processes ineliminably involve negative states of affairs (the lack of oxygen and the absence of support, respectively), which cannot transfer physical quantities such as energy and momentum (see Schaffer, 2000).

  7. It is interesting to note that although Closure* is more plausible than Closure, the former is not logically weaker than the latter.

  8. I want to note in passing a third causal argument, which aims to establish Identity* by appeal to the premises of Closure, Interaction, and Exclusion* (for a similar suggestion, see Stoljar, 2022). But as I have argued, Closure* and Interaction* are more plausible than Closure and Interaction. Hence, the causal argument A2 is preferable.

References

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: in search of a fundamental theory. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. (2001). Elements of mind: An introduction to the philosophy of mind. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation. Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. (1989). Making mind matter more. Philosophical Topics, 17, 59–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2010). Closure principles and the laws of conservation of energy and momentum. Dialectica, 64, 363–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gibb, S. (2012). Non-reductive physicalism and the problem of strong closure. American Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 29–42.

  • Heil, J. (2019). Philosophy of mind: A contemporary introduction (4th ed.). Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1998). Mind in a physical world. MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354–361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Causation. Journal of Philosophy, 70, 556–567.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • List, C., & Menzies, P. (2009). Nonreductive physicalism and the limits of the exclusion principle. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 475–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, D. (2001). The rise of physicalism. In C. Gillett & B. Loewer (Eds.), Physicalism and its discontents (pp. 3–36). Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, J. (2000). Causation by Disconnection. Philosophy of Science, 67, 285–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shoemaker, S. (2007). Physical realization. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Stoljar, D. (2022). Physicalism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2022/entries/physicalism/

  • Wilson, J. (1999). How superduper does a physicalist supervenience need to be? The Philosophical Quarterly, 49, 33–52.

  • Wilson, J. (2011). Nonreductive realization and the powers-based subset strategy. The Monist, 94, 121–154.

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2015). Interventionism and causal exclusion. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 91, 303–347.

  • Yablo, S. (1992). Mental causation. Philosophical Review, 101, 245–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhong, L. (2014). Sophisticated exclusion and sophisticated causation. Journal of Philosophy, 111, 341–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhong, L. (2020a). Intervention, fixation, and supervenient causation. Journal of Philosophy, 117, 293–314.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zhong, L. (2020b). Taking emergentism seriously. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 98, 31–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

I would like to thank the editors of Asian Journal of Philosophy for the invitation to contribute a lead paper for article symposium. I am also grateful to an anonymous referee for this journal and the audience of my talk at Beijing Normal University for helpful comments on earlier versions of this article.

Funding

This work was supported by the RGC Research Fellow Scheme (No.: RFS2122-4H03) and the General Research Fund (No.: 14602321) of Hong Kong Research Grants Council.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lei Zhong.

Ethics declarations

Competing Interests

Not applicable.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Zhong, L. A causal argument for physicalism. AJPH 2, 71 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-023-00110-1

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s44204-023-00110-1

Keywords

Navigation