1 Introduction

Three years after Catalonia’s attempt to split from Spain in October 2017, political relations between separatist Catalans and unionist Spanish are still in a complete deadlock. Though most politicians and commentators think that the dispute should be peacefully resolved through dialogue in accordance with (Spanish) law, a crucial question has mostly been left unanswered. Why should secessionist Catalans ever care to show obedience towards Spanish constitutional-legal institutions, now that those are precisely what they are politically trying to get rid of? The controversy has especially re-erupted since October 14, 2019, when the Spanish Supreme Court convicted several Catalan leaders for their role in the 2017 independence movement. Despite human rights complaints raised by the Catalan Ombudsman,Footnote 1Amnesty International,Footnote 2 the UN Working Group on Arbitrary Detention,Footnote 3 and International Trial Watch,Footnote 4 nine Catalan separatist leaders were convicted to 9 to 13 years in prison.Footnote 5 Popular protests followed, with hundreds of thousands of people to gathering on the streets in Barcelona and other places demanding freedom for (what the secessionists see as) the political prisoners. Although most protests happened peacefully, there were also riots. Within a week, there were 593 reported injuries.Footnote 6 In total, four people lost an eye due to rubber bullets fired by police forces, and 65 journalists were injured, leading to condemnations from the Council of Europe and Amnesty International.Footnote 7

Despite these excesses, it seems fair to say that the mainstream political voice does not share the core of the Catalan secessionist sentiments. Carmen Calvo, Spain’s Deputy Prime Minister, called the police interventions “very proportional” and urged the Catalan independence movement to stop “lying” about having a right to self-determination.Footnote 8 Likewise, Prime Minister Pedro Sánchez praised the “exemplary efforts and bravery of the Catalan police,” calling it “absurd” to denounce a police force for performing its duty.Footnote 9 The Supreme Court judgment that spurred all the anger, Spanish commentators assure us, was “not a political decision,”Footnote 10 and merely “enforcing the law.”Footnote 11 That fits a wider international pattern of deference to Spanish constitutional authority. With a few exceptions,Footnote 12 most influential European politicians (including Jean-Claude Juncker, Donald Tusk, Emmanuel Macron, Angela Merkel, and Boris Johnson) have spoken out in support of Spanish law enforcement. Similarly, many academic commentators lament Catalan anti-constitutional attitudes.Footnote 13 Indeed, scholars have criticized the Catalan secessionist movement for its mass-indoctrinating,Footnote 14 its anti-federalism,Footnote 15 and its nationalist identity politics.Footnote 16

The normative literature on the Catalan crisis is above all occupied with the conflict’s central legalistic problem: can we allow political units like Catalonia to disobey legal constraints?Footnote 17 This article does not engage with this procedural legitimacy question. Instead, it addresses another issue, which was already mentioned at the beginning of this section. Even if we accept that there are procedural constraints to legitimate secession, why should Catalan secessionists ever accept those specific constraints coercively imposed by Spanish legal authorities? Specifically, the piece focuses on the ideological role played by one important actor in the Spanish-Catalan dispute: the Spanish Constitutional Court (hereinafter: “SCC”). Between 2010 and 2017, the SCC repeatedly took a centralist-Spanish stance, blocking Catalan attempts to seize more autonomy. Why would those who believe in the project of an independent Catalan state care to obey the SCC’s directives, other than out of mere fear of repercussions? Dominant philosophical theories of authority, the article argues, cannot answer this question in a non-circular manner, because they seek to ground the concept in (prior) reason. That conceptualization misses the key decisionistic element to political authority: its capacity to constitute our reasons—i.e., to define the terms that give meaning to our evaluations.

In unpacking its argument, this piece proceeds as follows. First, it starts by offering a brief historical account of the dispute (Section 2). Over the years, I show, the SCC performed a key role in the constitutional conflict, declaring illegal several unilateral Catalan steps towards more autonomy. Subsequently, I argue that Joseph Raz’s framework of law as a claim to supreme authority possesses particular power in explaining the repressive role Spanish authorities played during the conflict (Section 3). In claiming legitimacy for itself, Raz’s account shows, law excludes (“preempts”) perspectives that are foreign to it. The question remains, however, why Catalans with separatist sympathies should ever accept Spanish law’s claim to legitimate authority. I propose there are roughly three candidate reasons. The first two—the “mutual benefit argument” and the “law and democracy argument”—offer useful insights, but do not suffice to give a credible grounding to Spanish authorities independently (Section 4). For this reason, the article argues that the Spanish perspective is best reconstructed as founded upon a “law and order argument” (Section 5). The need to safeguard political stability, the point is, can in itself be a meta-argument not to shake up existing constitutional arrangements in favor of purportedly more legitimate alternatives. Even when the ethical foundations of political society are shaking, there is still one proper role left for authority: to restore order and lead everybody to move into the same direction again. This is a crucial feature of authority, not only in times of crisis, but also under more ordinary circumstances (Section 6).

2 A History

Catalan nationalism as such is old and has prominently existed since the days of Francisco Franco and before. The broad support for secession, however, is a relatively recent phenomenon.Footnote 18 Before 2010, secessionism in Catalonia was relatively scarce, backed only by a minority of 20% of the domestic population of Catalonia or less.Footnote 19 But since then, popular support for independence over alternative constitutional arrangements has risen significantly, peaking at 48.5% in 2013.Footnote 20 This sudden trend may be ascribed to a variety of long-term developments, but some more proximate causes likely exerted influence. For example, the economic crisis of 2008 and the austerity measures pushed through by the central government may have triggered Catalan resentment, stimulating secessionist Catalan parties to exploit latent nationalist sentiments.Footnote 21 Or, more generally, Catalan populism may result from the unresponsiveness of the Spanish central government to demands for autonomy,Footnote 22 especially after the rise of Mariano Rajoy’s “anti-Catalan” People’s Party.Footnote 23 But one event has especially drawn much attention and is often cited as the direct cause for the present outrage: the judgment of the SCC regarding the Statute of Autonomy of Catalonia of 2006 (hereinafter: “the 2006 Statute”).Footnote 24

Also known as Organic Act 6/2006 of July 19,Footnote 25 the 2006 Statute concerns a reform of the older 1979 Statue and arranges the legal position of the Autonomous Community of Catalonia under the Spanish Constitution (hereinafter: “SC”). Drafted and passed by the Catalan Parliament (hereinafter: “CP”) in 2005, the general aim was to expand the symbolic and legal-political autonomy of Catalonia. Among other things, a more central place was assigned to the Catalan language (Art. 6.1), and independent tax-raising powers were attributed to the CP (Art. 218.2).Footnote 26 After extensive negotiations in Spanish parliament, an amended version of the draft was passed and ratified through a referendum back in Catalonia (78% voted in favor, 22% against). It was only after the Spanish People’s Party—one of the two parties voting against the reform—challenged the constitutionality of the 2006 Statute that the SCC came into play. Consequently, the latter was put in an extremely sensitive position, while being unable to rely on too much direct precedent.Footnote 27

The Court took 4 years to rule on the matter in 2010, a length of time which in itself was cause for frustration and rising tensions.Footnote 28 And although the SCC’s decision in and of itself displayed relatively little judicial activism, declaring unconstitutional “only” fourteen of the Statute’s 223 articles,Footnote 29 the political impact of the judgment was severe.Footnote 30 On crucial issues, the SCC overturned the 2006 Statute’s central ambitions, striking down provisions enabling Catalonia’s fiscal and judicial autonomy.Footnote 31 But perhaps more importantly, by interpreting the 2006 Statute in line with the SC, the SCC puts brackets around the entire symbolical project behind the document. For example, it decided that the Catalan language could not enjoy a preferential status for Catalonia’s public bodies.Footnote 32 Also, it insisted that whereas Catalonia may be a “nationality” in an informal sense, it is in no legally relevant sense a “nation”: “the Constitution does not recognize anything other than the Spanish Nation.”Footnote 33 In other words, formally speaking, the 2006 Statute was largely left intact by the SCC ruling. But effectively, the real intentions behind the document were certainly thwarted.Footnote 34

In the years that followed, the SCC blocked the secessionist agenda several times more. For example, in March 2014, it annulled claims to sovereignty the CP had made in January 2013 and explicitly ruled that Catalonia could not unilaterally hold a “referendum of self-determination.”Footnote 35 The Spanish central parliament, however, rejected a Catalan request for a bilateral referendum in April 2014. Therefore, the Catalan government (Generalitat) moved to ask the opinion of the people in less official form than a “referendum.” It helped set up a “non-referendum consultation” on November 9, 2014—or, as it was later strategically framed, a “citizen participation process.”Footnote 36 All involvement of the Generalitat in this unofficial plebiscite was later declared illegal by the SCC,Footnote 37 but the “harm” had already been done: of the 2.2 million people who took part in the consultation, more than 80% voted in favor of secession. Though they lost the popular vote, the separatists in Catalonia won a symbolically crucial parliamentary election in September 2015. The pro-secessionist train became unstoppable, even though the SCC subsequently tried to block every step the Catalans took to independence. Among other things, the Court struck down the CP’s “Declaration of the Initiation of the Process of Independence of Catalonia” of November 2015Footnote 38 and annulled the Catalan law approving the notorious October self-determination referendum.Footnote 39 Unfortunately, it was too late. A confrontation had become unavoidable.

On October 1, 2017, the self-determination referendum took place in defiance of the SCC’s prohibition and resulted in an overwhelming majority in favor of independence. On October 27, after a few weeks of threats back and forth, Catalonia’s parliament finally declared independence. That was immediately followed by the Spanish government’s invocation of Article 155 of the SC, suspending Catalan autonomy. With the Generalitat and CP being dissolved, new regional elections were necessary, which were again won by the separatists (again without winning the popular vote). Then, after months of political tension and quarrel, Catalonia ultimately managed to install a new government in June 2018, regaining constitutional self-government for the region. In Spain, there also was a change of government. Rajoy’s conservative People’s Party was replaced as the party of government by Pedro Sánchez’s moderate and left-wing Spanish Socialist Workers’ Party (PSOE)—incidentally, with the support of Catalan separatists.

In the meantime, as mentioned in Section 1, twelve Catalan political and civil society leaders have been tried and convicted by the Spanish Supreme Court. There is considerable discontent about this among secessionists and about the political “captivity” of Catalonia in Spain more broadly. Consequently, Catalan streets have been the stage to several mass protests, such as on September 11, 2018 (1 mln. people),Footnote 40 October 1, 2019 (180,000 people),Footnote 41 February 16, 2019 (200,000 people),Footnote 42 and on October 18 and 26, 2019 (500,000 and 350,000 protestors).Footnote 43 Using this momentum, Catalan President Quim Torra has gradually tried to intensify the political pressure on Spanish Prime Minister Sánchez. Opportunities may be there now that Sánchez’s January 2020 national coalition depends on the Catalan separatists’ political support, perhaps allowing the latter to force pro-secessionist concessions. It remains very much to be doubted, however, how far Sánchez will be willing to go. Catalan secessionism is highly unpopular in the Spanish mainland, with the two largest parties behind the PSOE (People’s Party and the newly spawned Vox) vehemently rallying against any concessions.

3 Spanish Law as a Claim to Supreme Authority

Considering the facts as they have been summarized so far, it seems fair to say that the Catalan crisis has thoroughly escalated over time. Step by step, the SCC became more entrenched in its role to reject Catalan attempts to unilaterally seize more autonomy. And day by day, the Catalan separatists became increasingly allergic to the SCC’s intransigent “no.” No matter how we evaluate the issue normatively, the SCC has unmistakably become a player in a game that is deeply political. The Court at some point lost its de facto mediating authority and was stuck taking sides in a dispute that cannot be resolved within the logic of the constitution itself.Footnote 44 But perhaps we can give somewhat more theoretical flesh to this observation? What is it that gives courts—and the law they claim to interpret—such a plausible claim to political authority in the first place?

The “service conception” developed by political and legal theorist Joseph Raz offers a useful starting point to examine the concept of political authority. Most importantly, it consists of the so-called normal justification thesis.Footnote 45 Authority is normally justified, Raz asserts, if

the alleged subject is likely better to comply with reasons which apply to him (other than the alleged authoritative directives) if he accepts the directives of the alleged authority as authoritatively binding and tries to follow them, rather than by trying to follow the reasons which apply to him directly.Footnote 46

In layman’s terms, if it is better to listen to someone or something than not to do so, that person (or thing) is expected to possess legitimate authority. For example, someone who is an expert in the works of Immanuel Kant presumably has special epistemic authority when talking about the Grundlegung zur Metaphysik der Sitten.Footnote 47 Similarly, we might attach special value to the words of our wise grandmother. The grandmother, we might loosely say, is an “authority” to us.

For Raz, however, the genuine exercise of authority requires the presence of another element: the instructions must be “preemptive.” That is, the instructions of a genuine authority are not “just another reason,” like one advice among others, but exclusionary. Following them means to put aside, or “replace,” whatever other reasons one might have that contradict the authoritative statement.Footnote 48 So when a parent exercises authority over his or her child, the child cannot choose to disregard its parent’s instructions. Or when a police officer tells you “Stop!,” that is not a piece of advice one can freely choose to ignore—even if there is no independent good reason to stop. The reason why is quite straightforward: police officers simply cannot do their job properly unless their instructions are largely abided by. That means that compliance cannot depend on any given individual’s assessment of whether there are good reasons to follow the police’s instructions. The point in having a police is that they make that choice.Footnote 49

As Raz famously argues, law itself constitutes a claim to authority similar to the police officer’s described above.Footnote 50 When a judge convicts a criminal to 20 years in jail, for example, it is not permissible to give him five, or thirty—even if that would strictly speaking have been more just. Relatedly, legal systems claim to be supreme: legal institutions are always supposed to have a higher claim to obedience than other institutions.Footnote 51 Law, the point is, cannot work properly unless its bindingness and priority are not dependent on its content, but rather on the fact that it is law.Footnote 52 Legal reasons therefore necessarily claim to be “protected reasons”: they cannot be overturned by considerations of ordinary morality (not, at least, according to legal point of view).Footnote 53 Now, of course, most (if not all) legal systems provide for exceptions to the bindingness of general rules, for example, by allowing for freedom of conscience or acknowledging specific instances of force majeure.Footnote 54 Notice, however, how this fact possibly only strengthens the theory that law constitutes an exclusionary claim: by stipulating what are legitimate grounds for disregarding existing rules, it also implies that non-stipulated grounds are not legitimate.Footnote 55

Time to apply Raz’s theory to the Catalan crisis. Can we indeed plausibly understand Spanish law as a claim to the preemptive kind of authority Raz theorizes about? The answer, I think, is evidently “yes.” Two constitutional articles have been especially important in the SCC’s judgments regarding Catalonia. First, there is Article 1.2 of the SC, stating that “[n]ational sovereignty belongs to the Spanish people, from whom all State powers emanate.”Footnote 56 According to the SCC, despite everything the CP claims, sovereignty does not belong to Catalonia.Footnote 57 Even more explicitly, in Article 2, the SC states that “[t]he Constitution is based on the indissoluble unity of the Spanish Nation, the common and indivisible homeland of all Spaniards.” As we know from Raz, if the constitution is to have any proper authority, this supreme rule cannot be disregarded. As the SCC put it: “Converting [political projects] into legislation or other manifestations of the public authority’s intent is only possible through the procedure for constitutional reform. To do otherwise would be to release the public authorities from any requirement to obey the law, irreparably damaging citizens’ freedoms.”Footnote 58

Notice that there are different ways in which the SCC has pushed the separatist-Catalan perspective away from the center of politics. First, there is the Razian point that any legal order must ultimately formally exclude external perspectives from its discourse if it is to have any guiding potential. Let us call this “formal-legal exclusion.” That does not necessarily pose a problem: in leaving significant room for self-governing communities, the SC is also crucially accommodating towards wishes for autonomy.Footnote 59 When we notice that the constitutional order’s supply of autonomy does not match the demand, however, tensions arise. The Catalan case exemplifies this. Catalan steps to self-government, even if executed through peaceful means, were repeatedly delegitimated by the law and pejoratively called “illegal.” We can dub this “substantive-legal exclusion.” And then, there is a third way in which the Spanish legal order quells Catalan secessionist ambitions: through the use of repressive public means. Label this “institutional-factual exclusion.”

One needs not to look far to see the ways in which institutional repression of the separatist movement is taking place. The Internet is swamped with footage of Spanish order troops hitting peaceful protesters and violently dragging Catalan voters out of polling stations on October 1, 2017.Footnote 60 According to the Generalitat, nearly 900 people were injured in the process. Leaders of the regional police (Mossos d’Esquadra), including chief Josep Lluís Trapero, who failed to cooperate with the violence now face charges of up to 11 years in jail. At the end of October 2017, President Carles Puigdemont left the country in fear of retaliation and fled to Brussels, taking a few of his ministers with him. A few months later, in February 2018, former politician and pro-independence spokeswoman Anna Gabriel also chose exile above prosecution and left for Switzerland, as did member of the CP Marta Rovira in March. Until July 2018, all were subject to an international arrest warrant. In the meantime, prosecutions in Spain have continued. And as mentioned, nine civil and political pro-independence leaders have been put into custody and later imprisoned, thereby not recognizing immunity for elected Member of European Parliament Oriol Junqueras.Footnote 61 Torra and his separatist allies will now think twice before they follow the example of their predecessors and embark on the same unilateral path towards independence as their predecessors. Do not mess with Spain’s constitutional order, the message is, or it will mess with you.

4 Mutual Benefit; Law and Democracy

As we concluded, Raz’s framework of law as a claim to preemptive authority is useful in conceptualizing the repressive attitude of Spanish political institutions towards separatist Catalonia. If we really want to understand what happened in those thrilling months in 2017, however, a more rigorous analysis is required. After all, to say that the SCC’s claims to have the authority to exclude Catalan appeals to independence from the public domain is one thing. But the fact that this claim is generally deemed plausible and acted upon is quite another. Surely the SCC (and those enforcement troops acting on its rulings) does not take themselves to be exercising mere coercive force over an unwilling Catalan population. As Raz’s normal justification thesis shows, an intelligible reconstruction of Spanish de facto authority involves an attempt to grasp the reasons underpinning its claim to obedience. I discuss three such candidate reasons. The first two of these (the “mutual benefit argument” and the “law and democracy argument”) are considered in this section, the third (“law and order argument”) in the next.

To start with the mutual benefit argument: it would simply be very bad for all parties involved if Catalonia separated from Spain. Bad for Spain, bad for Europe at large. And bad for Catalonia itself, too, especially if you consider the fact that it will be hard to leave Spain and still remain in the EU. Tariffs and physical borders would block trade and economic prosperity. Big businesses would leave the Barcelona metropolis. Catalonia would have to build an expensive state infrastructure with embassies, a central bank, and so forth. And “independent Catalonia would have to create its own currency with a devaluation between 30 percent and 50 percent; its GDP [gross domestic product] would be reduced by between 25 percent and 30 percent,” former Economy Minister Luis de Guindos adds. “[That] is so irrational that Europe does not see it as a viable scenario and the government of Spain will not allow this to happen.”Footnote 62

Could this essentially prudential line of argument underpin a Catalan duty to acknowledge the SCC’s judgment as authoritative? I doubt it. Remember that the argument in favor of the SCC’s authority cannot rest on considerations about the content of the decision itself—that would violate the principle that authority binds content independently. Rather, it must be an argument claiming that the SCC generally produces good judgments on this sort of issues and that that fact in itself generates a duty to obey. As far as this concerns protecting Catalonia’s own interests, that is not very convincing. A right to self-rule, which separatist Catalans seem to believe in, usually also involves a right to reach irresponsible decisions.Footnote 63 Besides, if leaving Spain would be a bad idea because Spain refuses to make proper trade agreements and pressures the EU not to allow Catalonia to enter, whose fault is that, really? Admittedly, to the extent that the mutual benefit argument stems from a concern for Spanish interests, the issue becomes more difficult. Indeed, perhaps there is a moral duty for Catalans to take care of their less wealthy Spanish brothers. The question remains, however, whether the moral force of this argument is properly captured in terms of Spanish benefit. Suppose, for example, that it would be good for Belgians if Luxembourg would become part of Belgium and that Belgian authorities are particularly competent in establishing this. Surely that would not entail a Luxembourgian obligation to obey Belgian authorities if they would declare Luxembourg to be a part of Belgium. Apparently, we need more than mere “benefit” to explain the alleged Catalan duties to obey Spanish authority.

For these reasons, those who favor the SCC’s point of view have another argument in store: the aforementioned “law and democracy argument.” The Catalan decision to secede, the idea is, was not a genuinely democratic decision, because it did not match the basic rules that are to be expected in a liberal democracy. Democracy does not exist in a vacuum. It needs to be given shape and empowered through a constitutional framework of legally mandated public institutions.Footnote 64 According to Article 168 SC, the union of Spain can only be broken by two consecutive two-thirds majority votes in both houses of parliament, and a subsequent referendum. The Catalan separatists are perfectly allowed to pursue such a majority in national parliament, and yet, they failed to do so.Footnote 65 What is more, the majority of the separatists in the CP in 2017 were only small, 72 out of 135 seats in parliament. Should there not be a larger majority for such an important decision as a declaration of independence—especially considering the aforementioned fact that the separatists did not even win the popular vote? The independence referendum law of September 2017 was rushed through virtually without prior notice, after a debate that lasted less than half a day. Perhaps even more problematically, the separatist majority refused to wait for an advisory opinion from the Council of Statutory Guarantees, even though the opposition was entitled to that opinion,Footnote 66 entitled by Catalan statutory law, by the way, not by Spanish law,Footnote 67 and then the independence referendum itself. Admittedly, almost 90% of the voters voted pro leave, but how reliable is such a result if most “remain” voters do not acknowledge the referendum’s legitimacy (and therefore presumably stayed at home)?

Those are all powerful and arguably insurmountable criticisms of the way the pro-secession politicians in Catalonia organized their campaign. “We want to talk, as well established democracies do,” Puigdemont wrote on October 16, 2017 in a letter to his colleague Rajoy.Footnote 68 But why is Puigdemont then so clearly violating democratic principles himself? That is a question well worth asking. Still, we must be careful not to conflate the claim that the Puigdemont administration acted undemocratically with the claim that the SCC’s judgments carry democratic authority. Most certainly, the events of September and October 2017 are no showcases of healthy democratic procedure, but do Spain’s national institutions go off the hook there? First of all, in a banal sense, it is hard to organize an orderly and successful referendum if Spanish law enforcement crushes in, walking around seizing ballot boxes and beating voters. More fundamentally, Catalan secessionist resentment is not likely to have arisen out of thin air. If you assume a principle of democratic self-rule, and consider the fact that separatists have consistently called for more autonomy, feelings of resentment are hardly surprising. The three Spanish powers of government—not only the SCC, but also the government and parliament—have hardly done anything else than simply to deny all requests. Indeed, a minority position as it is in Spain, Catalan separatism is likely never to gain support in two consecutive two-third majority votes in Spanish parliament in the foreseeable future. In such a case, it seems a principled attitude of non-accommodation fails to meet the normative requirements of democracy.Footnote 69 Democracy, to be sure, means more than mere majority rule.Footnote 70

Now, importantly, that all is not to say that the mutual benefit argument and the law and democracy argument are not grounded in normatively significant insights. Indeed, someone who is already disposed to view the SCC’s authority as legitimate may very well be strengthened in that disposition by considering mutual benefit or democracy-based arguments. Such a person may still occasionally choose to reject Spanish legal authority in particular instances, but is then likely to experience moral loss, flowing from the existence of a loyalty conflict.Footnote 71 Remember, however, that this article only has a limited ambition: to review the SCC’s authority claims from the perspective of someone who does not take its legitimacy for granted. From that point of view, my point is, the mutual benefit and democracy arguments will not look very satisfying. To put it more precisely, they do not present any second-order reasons to accept the SCC’s supreme authority—at least not independently. When fundamental questions of political identity are at stake, the mutual benefit argument seems too technocratic to persuade. Similarly, the law and democracy argument is not very likely to play the required mediating role. The SCC’s reasoning is essentially circular: if one accepts Spanish constitutional amendment as the only legitimate procedure to achieve more Catalan political autonomy, all other steps are illegal. But that circularity seems problematic. The dispute arises, after all, precisely due to a disagreement on the sovereignty question. The separatist Catalans could presumably at least temporarily have been contented with a referendum, such as organized in the UK for Scotland in 2014 (or regarding Brexit in 2016). But for both the SCC and the Spanish parliament, that demand evidently went a bridge too far.

5 The Law and Order Argument

To repeat, this all does not imply that the mutual benefit and democratic arguments are unreasonable, let alone that it would be a good idea for Catalonia to split off from Spain. We can stay agnostic regarding those matters and still establish that the benefit-based and democratic arguments are incapable to independently validate the SCC’s claim to authority. As I argue below, however, a version of the third “law and order argument” can be a valid argument, especially when it comes to legitimating the role the SCC has played. This section unpacks this law and order argument a little bit further.

As the name already indicates, the law and order argument puts special focus on the importance of values like stability and legal certainty. Though these may of course be considered just some political values among others, when functioning as the basis for an authority claim, the law and order argument usually appears as a meta-argument. No matter one’s political agenda or political-philosophical views, the idea is, in some cases, we are fundamentally not in the position to reject the legitimacy of existing political arrangements. Unlike with the mutual benefit argument, however, the reason is not that those specific political arrangements necessarily make our lives better. Rather, it is because we have no choice but to rely on them—even if we would rather live in a world without our current political institutions, now they are here, we do better to recognize their authority. That also signifies what distinguishes the law and order argument from the law and democracy argument discussed in the previous section. Whereas the latter tries to ground political obligation in abstract ideals of democratic representation, the former focuses on the de facto normative order that we encounter in our daily lives. Though it is true we did not precisely choose what political institutions (e.g., the Kingdom of Spain) are currently in place, the bare fact of their existence carries undeniable moral relevance.Footnote 72

Cut to its core, the law and order argument starts with a rejection of the philosophical anthropology of the political consumer as the center of the universe. Political life is not like a trip to the shopping mall, where one can freely roam about and choose to buy the products one happens to find an attractive supplement to what one already owns. Rather, it is like doing your shopping while simultaneously being responsible for the general maintenance of the mall and all the stores in it. Or to use Michael Oakeshott’s famous metaphor, it is like navigating a ship: one cannot do it without first making sure that the vessel keeps afloat.Footnote 73 Keeping afloat the existing system of government under the law, then, is something we are all responsible for, even if the ultimate foundations of that system are perhaps morally contingent and arbitrary. The reason is, quite simply, that the stability that existing law provides is something way too important to put on the line. On the one hand, law allows us to peacefully resolve disputes and coordinate collective plans,Footnote 74 uniting a diverse set of individuals under a common set of legal procedures. On the other hand, due to this procedural nature, law can help us to much more effectively monitor and constrain the exercise of collective action. It is a kind of societal pact—a contract, if you will. Legal institutions, such as courts, governments, and parliaments, are not allowed to exceed the powers vested in them by historically created law and constitution. In return, they get to ask compliance from citizens and subordinate institutions. It seems that the kind of respect for legality inherent in this reciprocal bond is implicit in any credible notion of the rule of law.Footnote 75

The important takeaway point here is that the rule of law is not a random artifact that exists independently of our actions. It is actually an enormous social achievement, generated by a collective commitment to fidelity to law. This commitment to legality, we must realize, becomes little more than incoherent folly if it is conditional on the accidental alignment of the law’s perspective with our own. That is the basic Hobbesian axiom: social order is something inherently worth protecting, because it is both too important and too fragile simply to take for granted. Asking why the Catalans should not try to unilaterally secede, one could say by analogy, is a bit like asking why we should not take someone else’s property without permission. The reason is not that the current scheme of property distribution (or political sovereignty distribution, for that matter) is in some way maximally just or maximally democratic. Rather, the point is that political order necessarily relies on certain historically grown rights and entitlements, generating stability and legitimate expectations. Indeed, even if there is no good reason of ahistorical justice that I have much more money than you, you are still not permitted to go ahead and steal my car.Footnote 76 Similarly, there might be no principle of ahistorical justice justifying that Catalonia is part of Spain. But still, there may be a relative wrong in unilaterally breaking the bond of sovereignty and seizing territory in order to create a separate state.Footnote 77

There is quite something at stake here. Notably, the notion of the “indissoluble unity of the Spanish Nation” (Art. 2 SC) is there for a reason. Yes, perhaps Spain as it is is not perfect, but at least it is—and building on institutions that are is a necessary precondition for political order. Suppose the SCC would recognize an “inalienable right to self-government” to any political entity claiming to be independent.Footnote 78 Or, even worse, imagine that the SCC would have backed down and approved of the CP’s claims to sovereignty and independence after it already ruled its 2010 judgment. What would that mean for the nation’s political stability? Separatist Catalans may want a diplomatic relationship with Spain as coequals, maintaining stable forms of economic and political cooperation. Such a wish is hardly coherent, however, if Spain is to be shred apart by calls for autonomy everywhere, such as in Galicia, the Basque Country, and other regions.Footnote 79 An independent Catalonia might desire to join the EU, but would that mean the regions of Flanders, Bavaria, and Padania should have the same right?Footnote 80 Quite surely, the line must be drawn somewhere if a governable political constellation is to remain operative at all. Besides, would separatist Catalans be evenly tolerant to claims to self-government if, say, the Catalan city of Girona would want to split off in its own right?

With the law and order argument, it finally appears there is an inherent reason to abide by the SCC’s judgments that even Catalan secessionists cannot decline to (at least) take seriously. Moreover, it can ground the moral force of the arguments named in the previous section. There, we concluded that the mutual benefit argument in itself does not justify the Spanish position, because the court has no special legitimacy in deciding on policy questions. And we rejected the law and democracy argument as a legitimation of the Spanish repression, because referring to existing constitutional arrangements does not justify the constitution itself. But viewed against the background of the law and order argument, the burden of proof is shifted. Why should we buy into utopian promises of a prosperous Catalan state if we currently have Spanish institutions, which at the moment appear to function comparatively well? Is that really something we want to put at risk? Democracies, we must remember, can only be consolidated if all parts are loyal to the whole, genuinely participating in common deliberations without threatening to shred it apart.Footnote 81

Now, to be clear, this all still does not necessarily mean that Catalan secessionism becomes an untenable position once one accepts the normative cogency of law and order considerations. Catalan separatists will obviously dispute the purported self-evidence of the existing Spanish order and rally for a reinterpretation of history to the effect of establishing that sovereignty lies with Catalonia.Footnote 82 When the discussion reaches that stage, it becomes a matter of word against word—or, more accurately, narrative against narrative: who has the rightful claim to legal authority here? In the ideological quarrel that follows, few measures are off limits, and much will be decided by (rhetorical and other) force. The reason is basically Darwinian and can readily be deduced from the previous paragraphs. If a political project is to subsist, it cannot be tolerant towards hostile forms of organizations that seek to lay its core normative underpinnings to waste. That is where the political rubber hits the road: once a law and order claim is successful, other political concerns are displaced and pushed to the background.

Remember, to avoid confusions, that the fact that a de facto political authority demands uncompromised attitudes of obedience does not necessarily mean that that demand will be accepted. Yes, Spanish unionist will claim that there are content-independent reasons to accept the SCC’s authority no matter what, but Catalan secessionists have reason to be unpersuaded. They might point out, for example, that the SCC is unduly biased in favor of the status quo and argue that its law and order claim illegitimately declares a constitutional state of emergency. From the more detached perspective of the analyst, we may summarize that constitutional crises like the one in Catalonia in 2017 are moments when two opposing logics of the public sphere meet. On the one hand, there is the thing Jacques Rancière would call “police,”Footnote 83 which concerns the need to uphold constitutional order. On the other hand, there more rare moments of what one might call constitutive moments, or “politics” proper: “whatever breaks the tangible configuration whereby parties … are defined.”Footnote 84

The Catalan bid for independence could well be understood as an attempt to open the political space, to make a political demand as to reform the existing police logic. That is to say, it is an attempt to question the boundaries of the public sphere, presenting a new constitutional logic as an alternative to the old one. At that moment, the SCC was forced to make a political choice: exclude the new constitutional claim (and maintain old law) or accommodate it (and thus redraw constitutional boundaries). Needless to say, the Court ultimately chose the first option and thus claimed restorative police power in the face of the political. Now, the point is not that the SCC could not or should not have done differently—indeed, there is no clear reason why the Court could not have drawn the line in a more accommodative fashion. Rather, the point is that the Court did not do differently. Once the Court had chosen to construe the SC in a more exclusive manner, there was no way back. The result was a split, a rupture. With the judgment of the SCC, the Spanish high priest had spoken: get back in line, or be an outlaw.

Notice how there is a sense in which this is quite different from how courts ordinarily function. Under the Razian model, judicial authority normally flows from a sense of constitutional dignity. We accept the judgments of courts because their conduct is governed by the glue of a shared legal procedures and standards.Footnote 85 But it is precisely this sense of constitutional glue or sharedness that is at stake in crises like the Catalan one.Footnote 86 The SC’s and SCC’s constitutional authority is no longer assumed, as in normal circumstances of legality, but rather asserted. That is what it means to truly exercise constitutional sovereignty in a Schmittian sense: “determining definitively what constitutes public order and security.”Footnote 87

6 Conclusion: Rethinking the Concept of Authority

One of the major perks of the Razian framework of authority is its power to conceptualize reasons people may have to accept the existence of a duty to obey specific authoritative claims. The theories of philosophical anarchists like Robert Paul Wolf and Hobbesians like Robert Ladenson are less suitable there. By denying that there is such a thing as legitimate authority,Footnote 88 or by denying that authority is linked to duty,Footnote 89 they fail to explain the phenomenology of juridico-political life. As Raz rightly observes, authority is more than a right to knock people over and exercise coercion, thereby treating them as mad dogs that need conditioning. Rather, to exercise authority is to ascribe duty—a moral expectation that one is to be obeyed.Footnote 90 Hence follows an important methodological axiom that has also underlain this article’s design. If we want to fully explicate how a de facto authority (like the SCC) appeals to its subjects, we need to look into the reasons we might have to acknowledge a duty to obey that authority.

In the general literature on authority, some doubts have been raised whether Raz’s own framework can actually do the job of explaining the existence of duties to obey. According to Raz’s aforementioned normal justification thesis, authority derives from “service”: a potential to better the conditions of subjects as individuals in acting on their reasons. As critics have noted in response, however, the foundations of political authority often rather seem collectively-procedural and distinctively relational. The rights of a ruling institution, for example, are not merely determined by the quality of its decision making, but also by its democratic legitimacy.Footnote 91 And the rights of, say, a parent vis-à-vis his or her child are distinctive for the parent-child relation, as only parents can exercise the rights of parental authority.Footnote 92 Both these procedural and relational objections essentially boil down to the same point. To recognize that it would be better to accept someone or something as an authority does not establish that person or thing actually is an authority. Even if another person would perhaps be a better parent for you, what usually counts is that it is simply not your parent. Similarly, even if I could compose adjudicative panels that would produce better judgments than the courts actually present, what matters is that those other courts are simply not legally assigned courts.Footnote 93

I would like to suggest that this tells us a lot about the moral texture of the Spanish-Catalan constitutional conflict. As we saw in Section 4, the mutual benefit argument does not suffice as a foundation for the SCC’s authority. The reason coincides with the general point spelled out in the previous paragraph: simple benefit (or “betterness”) cannot establish a proper moral bond of political duty. A somewhat different and yet related problem appeared with the law and democracy argument. To be sure, we might agree about the importance of ideals of legality and democracy, but the question what legality and whose democracy cannot be resolved on an abstract level. That is why Section 5 had to add a necessary supplement: the law and order argument. It provides a rational basis for what at first might look like a naturalistic fallacy: things are as they are, so let us keep them this way. Notice the paradox, however. Although any law and order claim must be grounded in an already valid set of constitutional documents or practices (the historical-relational element), strictly speaking, it never can be. After all, if a constitutional order were already considered to be the legitimate authority prior to any intervention, there would be no need to assert legitimacy. Apparently, in times of crisis, the authority of institutions in moments of crisis is self-constitutive: “Order is hereby restored, don’t jeopardize this achievement by disobeying!” Notice the phrasing here: order is restored. Once the authority claim successfully made, it is ipso facto already validated as a social reality. Who gets to successfully make these kinds of law and order claims can perhaps sometimes be predicted, but only legitimated after the claim has been made. The reason is that the intersubjective room in which this extraordinary form of authority exercise functions is not one of prior moral legitimation, but rather one of undeniable social presence.Footnote 94

So what is the upshot of all this for ordinary cases—circumstances under which the authority of our legal institutions is not put under existential question? Sure, there are always rare moments when constituted powers (like courts) become the object of constitutional controversy, temporarily making their political foundations unstable. Just like human beings become ill once in a while, legal systems have their pathologies, but are the moments of lack of pathology not much more telling?Footnote 95 Usually, we do not see the claims of constitutional agents (such as courts) as explicit claims to political authority. Rather, we experience their authority as part of the natural furniture of society. Still, the fact that political authority does not always have to be asserted explicitly does not mean that the continuous exercise of constitutive power is not there implicitly. Although commonly hidden beneath the moralized surface of a constitutional order, there always remains a decisionistic element of self-assertion in every authoritative judgment. Strictly speaking, even the technical case law produced by a lower administrative court could be seen as a reaffirmation of embedded hierarchies: “Order is hereby maintained, don’t jeopardize this achievement by disobeying!”

This leads me to leave a final note about the structure of the scholarly debate about authority. Produced largely in response to the anarchist’s challenge, perhaps contemporary attempts to understand the concept of authority got off on the wrong foot. Analyses of authority like Raz’s depart from what one could call a hypothetical non-existence test: would it be better if de facto authority X were not there? I would contend that there is quite a misleading account of political judgment implicit here. Usually, the choice is not between X and ¬X (e.g., having a dictator or not having a dictator), but rather between X and Y (e.g., supporting the dictator or supporting the countermovement). In the latter situation, the hypothetical non-existence test does not work. Instead, one needs an a posteriori contextual judgment: given all the claims to loyalty imposed on us, whom do we owe our fidelity to? Crucially, in such a circumstance, an assessment of the legitimacy (i.e., support-worthiness) of a claim to authority cannot be abstracted from the existence of the claim itself. We might not like, say, the composition of the US constitution, but since it is there, we better work with what we have. Similarly, we might not like the SCC’s judgment, but since it is there, it is impossible to ignore. That is the basic lesson from decisionism. Sure, de facto authorities may be critically evaluated as to make them responsive to reason, but at the same time, they constitute the very terms in which those evaluations will take place. We are, to put it in Bonnie Honig’s terms, always between decision and deliberation.Footnote 96