Skip to main content
Log in

Plausibility and Early Theory in Linguistics and Cognitive Science

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Computational Brain & Behavior Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Various notions of plausibility are used in cognitive science to argue for or against the “goodness of theories.” However, plausibility remains poorly understood and difficult to analyze. We review debates in the philosophy of science on uses of plausibility in the assessment of novel scientific theories as well as recent attempts to formalize, reform, or eliminate specific notions of plausibility. Although these discussions highlight important concerns behind plausibility claims, they fail to identify viable notions of plausibility that are sufficiently different from other criteria of “good theory,” such as prior probability or external coherence. We survey uses of plausibility in linguistics and cognitive science, confirming that plausibility is often a proxy for other criteria of good theory. We argue that the need remains for concepts of plausibility that can be employed to assess the quality of proposals at the early stages of theory development when other criteria are not yet applicable. We identify two such notions: one relating to formal constraints on theories and another capturing initial epistemic consensus, if not necessarily convergence on the truth, about the target system in a community of inquiry. We briefly assess the specificity and added value of these notions of plausibility relative to other criteria for good theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

No data or materials were used in this work.

Code Availability

No code was used in this work.

Notes

  1. Some philosophers of science may argue that there should not be any epistemic restrictions on pursuit: all proposals should be treated as equally viable forerunners of success. The concern is that “even the most seemingly trivial pursuitworthiness criterion would have inhibited some of the greatest scientific research programs in history” (Shaw 2022, 110). However, some scientific contexts, so-called “urgent science,” in which there is a practical or moral reason to obtain results within a particular time frame, may demand pursuitworthiness judgments. This is another point of difference between plausibility and pursuitworthiness.

  2. Belief change has been modeled in other frameworks, like AGM (after Alchourrón, Gärdenfors, and Makinson), but DEL has become popular because of its advantages over AGM. For example, it can account for higher-order beliefs and can be applied in multi-agent scenarios. However, the epistemic and dynamic operators that enrich the DEL framework with enough expressive power to model and reason about agents’ knowledge, beliefs, and actions come at a computational cost (Aucher & Schwarzentruber 2013): for instance, the satisfiability problem for individual agents in Public Announcement Logic (a fragment of DEL) is NP-complete (Lutz 2006). That said, DEL has been successfully used to model a range of problems, for example the complexity of theory of mind reasoning and related issues (e.g., van de Pol et al. 2018; Szymanik & Verbrugge, 2018).

  3. Conversely, to say that for a, world v is no less plausible than world w, we write wa v. If w is strictly more plausible than v for a, we write w >a v; if v is strictly more plausible than w, we write w <a v. If w and v are equally plausible for a, we write wa v (wa v and wa v hold).

  4. This picture is necessarily simplified but can be refined with tools and insights that are already available in the literature. For example, the way scientific communities assess the plausibility of early theories may depend on how the members of such communities are connected among each other. Network epistemology models have shown that well-connected groups tend to arrive at a consensus quicker, but this consensus may not be correct as members can be sharing misleading evidence that might lead the community to settle on poor theory. This phenomenon is known as the “Zollman effect.” Sparsely connected networks are more likely to settle on a consensus closer to the truth (Zollman 2007, 2010, 2013). Moreover, more realistic agents and interactions would need to be posited to model situations where a community is driven (e.g., by economic or other incentives) to converge on hypotheses not compatible with other criteria for good theory.

References

  • Abend, O., Kwiatkowski, T., Smith, N. J., Goldwater, S., & Steedman, M. (2017). Bootstrapping language acquisition. Cognition, 164, 116–143.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Achille, A., Rovere, M., & Soatto, S. (2019). Critical learning periods in deep neural networks. International Conference on Learning Representations (ICLR)

  • Achinstein, P. (1964). Models, analogies, and theories. Philosophy of Science, 31(4), 328–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Agassi, J. (2014). Proof, probability or plausibility. In: Mulligan, K., Kijania-Placek, K., & Placek, T. (eds) The History and Philosophy of Polish Logic, History of Analytic Philosophy. London: Palgrave Macmillan, London, pp. 117–127.

  • Aucher, G., & Schwarzentruber, F. (2013). On the complexity of dynamic epistemic logic. In B. C. Schipper (Ed.), Proceedings of the 14th Conference of Theoretical Aspects of Rationality and Knowledge (TARKXIV) (pp. 19–28). Chennai, India.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2006). Dynamic belief revision over multi-agent plausibility models. In Proceedings of LOFT (Vol. 6, pp. 11–24). University of Liverpool.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baltag, A., & Smets, S. (2008). Probabilistic dynamic belief revision. Synthese, 165, 179–202.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bartha, P. (2010). By parallel reasoning: the construction and evaluation of analogical arguments. Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barton, G. E., Berwick, R. C., & Ristad, E. S. (1987). Computational complexity and natural language. MIT press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bengio, Y., Simard, P., & Frasconi, P. (1994). Learning long-term dependencies with gradient descent is difficult. IEEE Transactions on Neural Networks, 5(2), 157–166.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. (2021). Understanding the replication crisis as a base rate fallacy. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 72(4), 965–993.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Branco, A., Rodrigues, J., Salawa, M., Branco, R., & Saedi, C. (2020). Comparative probing of lexical semantics theories for cognitive plausibility and technological usefulness. In Proceedings of the 28th International Conference on Computational Linguistics (pp. 4004–4019).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bremnes, H. S., Szymanik, J., & Baggio, G. (2022). Computational complexity explains neural differences in quantifier verification. Cognition, 223, 105013.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Bremnes, H. S., Szymanik, J., & Baggio, G. (2023). The interplay of computational complexity and memory load during quantifier verification. Language, Cognition and Neuroscience on-line first.

  • Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures. Mouton & Co.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chomsky, N. (1959). On certain formal properties of grammars. Information and Control, 2(2), 137–167.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cichy, R. M., & Kaiser, D. (2019). Deep neural networks as scientific models. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 23(4), 305–317.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • De Santo, A., & Drury, J. E. (2019). Encoding and verification effects of generalized quantifiers on working memory. Proceedings from the Annual Meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society, 55(1), 103–114.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Santo, A., & Rawski, J. (2022). Mathematical linguistics and cognitive complexity. In E. Danesi (Ed.), Handbook of Cognitive Mathematics (pp. 1–38). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dror, I. E., & Gallogly, D. P. (1999). Computational analyses in cognitive neuroscience: In defense of biological implausibility. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review, 6(2), 173–182.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Edelman, S. (1997). Computational theories of object recognition. Trends in cognitive sciences, 1(8), 296–304.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Garey, M. R., & Johnson, D. S. (1979). Computers and intractability: A guide to the theory of NP-completeness. W.H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goudge, T. A. (1966). Plausibility of new hypotheses. The Journal of Philosophy, 63(20), 621–624.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graf, T. (2022). Subregular linguistics: Bridging theoretical linguistics and formal grammar. Theoretical Linguistics, 48(3-4), 145–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossberg, S. (1987). Competitive learning: From interactive activation to adaptive resonance. Cognitive Science, 11(1), 23–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heinz, J., Kobele, G. M., & Riggle, J. (2009). Evaluating the complexity of optimality theory. Linguistic Inquiry, 40(2), 277–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooker, C. A. (1996). The scientific realism of Rom Harré. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 47(4).

  • Hopcroft, J. E., Motwani, R., & Ullman, J. D. (2001). Introduction to automata theory, languages, and computation (3rd ed.). Prentice-Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, K. (2015). Notational variants and invariance in linguistics. Mind & Language, 30(2), 162–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keenan, E. L., & Stabler, E. P. (2010). Language variation and linguistic invariants. Lingua, 120(12), 2680–2685.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kemp, C., Perfors, A., & Tenenbaum, J. B. (2004). Learning domain structures. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 26, 672–677.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kennedy, W. G. (2009). Cognitive plausibility in cognitive modeling, artificial intelligence, and social simulation. In Proceedings of the International Conference on Cognitive Modeling (ICCM) (pp. 24–26).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lambek, J. (1958). The mathematics of sentence structure. The American Mathematical Monthly, 65(3), 154–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • LeCun, Y., Bengio, Y., & Hinton, G. (2015). Deep learning. Nature, 521(7553), 436–444.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Love, B. C. (2021). Levels of biological plausibility. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B, 376(1815), 20190632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lutz, C. (2006). Complexity and succinctness of public announcement logic. In Proceedings of the Fifth International Joint Conference on Autonomous Agents and Multiagent Systems (pp. 137–143).

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Marr, D. (1982). Vision: A computational investigation into the human representation and processing of visual information. W.H. Freeman & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCulloch, W. S., & Pitts, W. (1943). A logical calculus of the ideas immanent in nervous activity. The Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 5, 115–133.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meehl, P. E. (1992a). Theoretical risks and tabular asterisks: Sir Karl, Sir Ronald, and the slow progress of soft psychology. In R. B. Miller (Ed.), The Restoration of Dialogue: Readings in the Philosophy of Clinical Psychology (pp. 523–555). American Psychological Association.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Meehl, P. E. (1992b). Cliometric metatheory: The actuarial approach to empirical, history-based philosophy of science. Psychological Reports, 71, 339–339.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meehl, P. E. (2002). Cliometric metatheory: II. Criteria scientists use in theory appraisal and why it is rational to do so. Psychological Reports, 91(2), 339–404.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Meehl, P. E. (2004). Cliometric metatheory III: Peircean consensus, verisimilitude and asymptotic method. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(4).

  • Merkx, D., & Frank, S. L. (2021). Human sentence processing: Recurrence or attention? In Proceedings of the Workshop on Cognitive Modeling and Computational Linguistics (pp. 12–22). Association for Computational Linguistics.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mewhort, D. J. (1990). Alice in wonderland, or psychology among the information sciences. Psychological Research, 52(2), 158–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelis, J. (2001). Transforming linear context-free rewriting systems into minimalist grammars. In In Proceedings of the 4th International Conference on Logical Aspects of Computational Linguistics (pp. 228–244).

    Google Scholar 

  • Michaelis, J. (2004). Observations on strict derivational minimalism. Electronic Notes in Theoretical Computer Science, 53, 192–209.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michaelov, J. A., Bardolph, M. D., Coulson, S., & Bergen, B. (2021). Different kinds of cognitive plausibility: Why are transformers better than RNNs at predicting N400 amplitude? Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 43, 300–306.

    Google Scholar 

  • Misak, C. J. (2004). Truth and the end of inquiry: A Peircean account of truth. Oxford University Press.

  • Nefdt, R. M., & Baggio, G. (2023). Notational variants and cognition: The case of dependency grammar. Erkenntnis, 1–31.

  • Niiniluoto, I. (1987). Truthlikeness. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nyrup, R. (2020). Of water drops and atomic nuclei: Analogies and pursuit worthiness in science. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 71(3), 881–903.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oota, S. R., Alexandre, F., & Hinaut, X. (2022). Long-term plausibility of language models and neural dynamics during narrative listening. Proceedings of the Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society, 44, 2462–2469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pentus, M. (2006). Lambek calculus is NP-complete. Theoretical Computer Science, 357(1-3), 186–201.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Perconti, P. (2017). The case for cognitive plausibility. In: La Mantia, F., Licata, I., & Perconti, P. (eds) Language in Complexity. Lecture Notes in Morphogenesis. Springer, Cham, pp. 73–79.

  • Perfors, A., Tenenbaum, J. B., Griffiths, T. L., & Xu, F. (2011). A tutorial introduction to Bayesian models of cognitive development. Cognition, 120(3), 302–321.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, L., & Pearl, L. (2015). The utility of cognitive plausibility in language acquisition modeling: Evidence from word segmentation. Cognitive Science, 39(8), 1824–1854.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1976). A note on verisimilitude. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 27(2), 147–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ramakrishnan, K., Scholte, S., Lamme, V., Smeulders, A., & Ghebreab, S. (2015). Convolutional neural networks in the brain: An fMRI study. Journal of Vision, 15(12), 371–371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, B. A., Lillicrap, T. P., Beaudoin, P., et al. (2019). A deep learning framework for neuroscience. Nature Neuroscience, 22(11), 1761–1770.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Ristad, E. S. (1993). The language complexity game. MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rogers, J., & Pullum, G. K. (2011). Aural pattern recognition experiments and the subregular hierarchy. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 20(3), 329–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rumelhart, D. E. (1989). The architecture of mind: A connectionist approach. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of Cognitive Science (pp. 133–159). MIT Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Sanborn, A. N., & Chater, N. (2016). Bayesian brains without probabilities. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 20(12), 883–893.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Savitch, W. J. (1993). Why it might pay to assume that languages are infinite. Annals of Mathematics and Artificial Intelligence, 8(1-2), 17–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Šešelja, D., & Straßer, C. (2013). Kuhn and the question of pursuit worthiness. Topoi, 32, 9–19.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapere, D. (1966). Plausibility and justification in the development of science. The Journal of Philosophy, 63(20), 611–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shaw, J. (2022). On the very idea of pursuitworthiness. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 91, 103–112.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1968). On judging the plausibility of theories. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics, 52, 439–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1990). Invariants of human behavior. Annual Review of Psychology, 41(1), 1–20.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Stenning, K., & van Lambalgen, M. (2010). The logical response to a noisy world. In M. Oaksford & N. Chater (Eds.), Cognition and Conditionals: Probability and Logic in Human Thinking (pp. 85–102). Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stinson, C. (2020). From implausible artificial neurons to idealized cognitive models: Rebooting philosophy of artificial intelligence. Philosophy of Science, 87(4), 590–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (2002). Representation and invariance of scientific structures. CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szymanik, J., & Verbrugge, R. (2018). Tractability and the computational mind. In M. Sprevak & M. Colombo (Eds.), The Routledge Handbook of the Computational Mind. Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1966). The plausibility of theories. The Journal of Philosophy, 63(20), 624–627.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding. Philosophy of Science, 69(2), 212–233.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsotsos, J. K. (1993). The role of computational complexity in perceptual theory. Advances in psychology, 99, 261–296.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van De Pol, I., Van Rooij, I., & Szymanik, J. (2018). Parameterized complexity of theory of mind reasoning in dynamic epistemic logic. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 27, 255–294.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, I. (2008). The tractable cognition thesis. Cognitive Science, 32(6), 939–984.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, I., & Baggio, G. (2020). Theory development requires an epistemological sea change. Psychological Inquiry, 31(4), 321–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, I., & Baggio, G. (2021). Theory before the test: How to build high-verisimilitude explanatory theories in psychological science. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16(4), 682–697.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • van Rooij, I., Blokpoel, M., Kwisthout, J., & Wareham, T. (2019). Cognition and intractability: A guide to classical and parameterized complexity analysis. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Velázquez-Quesada, F. R. (2014). Dynamic epistemic logic for implicit and explicit beliefs. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 23, 107–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wareham, H. T. (1996). The role of parameterized computational complexity theory in cognitive modeling. In AAAI-96 Workshop Working Notes: Computational Cognitive Modeling: Source of the Power.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wareham, T. (1999). Systematic parameterized complexity analysis in computational phonology. Ph.D. thesis, Department of Computer Science, University of Victoria, April 1999. Technical Report ROA-318-0599, Rutgers Optimality Archive.

  • Yang, G. R., & Wang, X. J. (2020). Artificial neural networks for neuroscientists: A primer. Neuron, 107(6), 1048–1070.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. S. (2007). The communication structure of epistemic communities. Philosophy of Science, 74(5), 574–587.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. S. (2010). The epistemic benefit of transient diversity. Erkenntnis, 72(1), 17–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. S. (2013). Network epistemology: Communication in epistemic communities. Philosophy Compass, 8(1), 15–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

GB, ADS, and NAN conceived and wrote the manuscript.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Giosuè Baggio.

Ethics declarations

Ethics Approval

Not applicable.

Consent to Participate

Not applicable.

Consent for Publication

The work presented in this article has not been published before; it is not under consideration elsewhere, and its submission has been approved by all co-authors.

Competing Interests

The authors declare no competing interests.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Baggio, G., De Santo, A. & Nuñez, N.A. Plausibility and Early Theory in Linguistics and Cognitive Science. Comput Brain Behav (2024). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42113-024-00196-7

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42113-024-00196-7

Keywords

Navigation