Skip to main content
Log in

Probabilistic Choice Induced by Strength of Preference

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Computational Brain & Behavior Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Just as we formulate detailed theories of utility or preference, so too should we theorize carefully about strength of preference. Likewise, because behavior is inherently uncertain, we need a theoretical framework for understanding choice probabilities. This paper fleshes out the simple premise that more strongly preferred options are more likely to be chosen. The resulting distribution-free Fechnerian models (DFMs) eschew convenience assumptions underlying popular models like the logit and probit, revealing which aspects of a core decision theory do or do not remain invariant across different ways of constructing strengths of preference, as well as across different monotonic links between those strengths of preference and choice probabilities. We formulate DFMs in a unifying polyhedral geometric space that allows for direct comparisons of theories that can be as categorically different as, say, regret theory, expected utility theory, and lexicographic semiorders. The geometric representation also provides a nuanced perspective on theoretical parsimony beyond parameter counting. Through a series of examples, we demonstrate the derivation and mathematical characterization of DFMs for decision theories with and without utilities and the inferences one can draw from data. We show how DFMs provide a multi-layered quantitative approach to the identifiability of hypothetical constructs. We highlight specific cases where DFMs protect the researcher against mistaken conclusions caused by overspecified models.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4
Fig. 5
Fig. 6
Fig. 7

Similar content being viewed by others

Data Availability

Not applicable.

Code Availability

Not applicable.

Notes

  1. Throughout, we use “double quotes” to indicate verbatim quotations or technical terms that are later defined formally, and we use ‘single quotes’ to acknowledge vague or ill-defined concepts.

  2. Division by \(1-r\) is necessary for increasing utility when \(r>1\). When \(r=1\), \(u_r(g) = q\times \ln (m)\).

  3. In many cases, in this paper, we consider open hypercubes \(]0,1[^d\). For ease of reading, we do not explicitly distinguish verbally between open and closed hypercubes.

  4. From here on, we omit the technical detail that when we refer to a convex hull, we mean the corresponding open set that excludes the vertices and faces.

  5. For a probability model that forms a convex polytope, the reciprocal of the volume of that polytope is the upper bound on the Bayes factor that one can obtain in comparing the model against an unconstrained reference (Klugkist and Hoijtink , 2007; Zwilling et al. , 2019). In particular, Constraint Set 14 characterizes a 2-dimensional polytope in 3-dimensional space, for \(r=1.017\). This polytope has volume zero in \(]0,1[^3\). This means that there is no upper limit as to how much evidence a very large, very well-fitting data set can provide in favor of the DFM for CRRA-EU restricted to \(r=1.017\).

  6. Other models taking the form of Eq. 7, with different assumptions about how strengths of preference are related to utilities, may also be regarded as logit specifications whenever F is a logistic CDF. Similarly, models of the form of Eq. 7 may be regarded as probit specifications whenever F is a normal CDF.

  7. The pictures approximate a continuous shape with a discrete set of points.

  8. Technically, moderate stochastic transitivity treats \(\mathcal {D}\) as the set of all ordered pairs of choice options from a master set of choice alternatives, even if some of those pairs were never used as stimuli.

  9. Eq. 20 also rules out some orders of strengths of preference with ties, which are not shown in Table 3. The corresponding lower dimensional polytopes are not included in the DFM.

  10. Technically, weak stochastic transitivity treats \(\mathcal {D}\) as the set of all ordered pairs of choice options from a master set of choice alternatives, even if some of those pairs were never used as stimuli.

  11. Retooling the same labels xyz for new options allows for a shared coordinate system across figures to compare the geometric structure.

  12. Throughout this example, for notational and conceptual simplicity, we omit universal quantifiers.

References

  • Alempaki, D., Canic, E., Mullett, T. L., Skylark, W. J., Starmer, C., Stewart, N., & Tufano, F. (2019). Reexamining how utility and weighting functions get their shapes: A quasi-adversarial collaboration providing a new interpretation. Management Science, 65(10), 4841–4862.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alós-Ferrer, C., Fehr, E., & Netzer, N. (2021). Time will tell: Recovering preferences when choices are noisy. Journal of Political Economy, 129(6), 1828–1877.

  • Alós-Ferrer, C., & Garagnani, M. (2021). Choice consistency and strength of preference. Economics Letters, 198, 109672.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alós-Ferrer, C., & Garagnani, M. (2022). The gradual nature of economic errors. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 200, 55–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Alós-Ferrer, C., & Garagnani, M. (2022). Strength of preference and decisions under risk. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 64, 309–329.

  • Becker, G. M., DeGroot, M. H., & Marschak, J. (1963). Stochastic models of choice behavior. Behavioral Science, 8, 41–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhatia, S., & Loomes, G. (2017). Noisy preferences in risky choice: A cautionary note. Psychological Review, 5(124), 678–687.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2007). Stochastic expected utility theory. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 34, 259–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P. (2014). Stronger utility. Theory and decision, 76(2), 265–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blavatskyy, P., & Pogrebna, G. (2010). Models of stochastic choice and decision theories: Why both are important for analyzing decisions. Journal of Applied Econometrics, 25, 963–986.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, H. D., & Marschak, J. (1960). Random orderings and stochastic theories of responses. In I. Olkin, S. Ghurye, H. Hoeffding, W. Madow, & H. Mann (Eds.), Contributions to Probability and Statistics (pp. 97–132). Stanford University Press: Stanford.

  • Broomell, S. B., & Bhatia, S. (2014). Parameter recovery for decision modeling using choice data. Decision, 1, 252–274.

  • Buschena, D., & Zilberman, D. (2000). Generalized expected utility, heteroscedastic error, and path dependence in risky choice. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 20(1), 67–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavagnaro, D. R., & Davis-Stober, C. P. (2014). Transitive in our preferences, but transitive in different ways: An analysis of choice variability. Decision, 1(2), 102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cavagnaro, D. R., Myung, J. I., Pitt, M. A., & Kujala, J. V. (2010). Adaptive design optimization: A mutual information-based approach to model discrimination in cognitive science. Neural computation, 22(4), 887–905.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Dai, J. (2017). Are intertemporal preferences transitive? A Bayesian analysis of repeated individual intertemporal choices. Decision, 4(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Debreu, G. (1958). Stochastic choice and cardinal utility. Econometrica: Journal of the Econometric Society, 26, 440–444.

  • Doignon, J. P., Fiorini, S., & Joret, G. (2006). Facets of the linear ordering polytope: A unification for the fence family through weighted graphs. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 50, 251–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Doignon, J. P., & Regenwetter, M. (1997). An approval-voting polytope for linear orders. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 41, 171–188.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Drichoutis, A. C., & Lusk, J. L. (2014). Judging statistical models of individual decision making under risk using in-and out-of-sample criteria. PloS One, 9(7), e102269.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Dunn, J. C., & Rao, L. L. (2019). Models of risky choice: A state-trace and signed difference analysis. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 90, 61–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fechner, G. T. (1860). Elemente der Psychophysik Elemente der Psychophysik. Leipzig: Breitkopf & Härtel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiorini, S. (2001). Determining the automorphism group of the linear ordering polytope. Discrete Applied Mathematics, 112, 121–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fiorini, S. (2004). A short proof of a theorem of Falmagne. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 48, 80–82.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Halff, H. M. (1976). Choice theories for differentially comparable alternatives. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 14, 244–246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harless, D. W., & Camerer, C. F. (1994). The predictive value of generalized expected utility theories. Econometrica, 62, 1251–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, J., & Natenzon, P. (2019). Moderate expected utility. Available at SSRN 3243657.

  • Heck, D., & Davis-Stober, C. (2019). Multinomial models with linear inequality constraints: Overview and improvements of computational methods for Bayesian inference. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 91, 70–87.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. D. (1995). Experimental investigations of errors in decision making under risk. European Economic Review, 39, 633–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hey, J. D. (2005). Why we should not be silent about noise. Experimental Economics, 8, 325–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kellen, D., Davis-Stober, C. P., Dunn, J. C., & Kalish, M. L. (2021). The problem of coordination and the pursuit of structural constraints in psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 16(4), 767–778.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Klugkist, I., & Hoijtink, H. (2007). The Bayes factor for inequality and about equality constrained models. Computational Statistics & Data Analysi, 51, 6367–6379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krefeld-Schwalb, A., Pachur, T., & Scheibehenne, B. (2021). Structural parameter interdependencies in computational models of cognition. Psychological Review, 129, 313–339

  • Loomes, G. (2010). Modeling choice and valuation in decision experiments. Psychological Review, 117, 902–924.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., Starmer, C., & Sugden, R. (1991). Observing violations of transitivity by experimental methods. Econometrica, 59, 425–439.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1982). Regret theory: An alternative theory of rational choice under uncertainty. Economic Journal, 92, 805–824.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Loomes, G., & Sugden, R. (1995). Incorporating a stochastic element into decision theories. European Economic Review, 39, 641–648.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D. (1956). Semiorders and a theory of utility discrimination. Econometrica, 24, 178–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D. (1959). Individual choice behavior: A theoretical analysis. New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luce, R. D., & Suppes, P. (1965). Preference, utility and subjective probability. In: R. D. Luce, R. R. Bush, & E. Galanter (Eds.), Handbook of Mathematical Psychology (Vol. III, pp. 249-410). New York, Wiley.

  • Marley, A. (2016). Choice, preference, and utility: Probabilistic and deterministic representations. In: W. Batcheler, H. Colonius, E. Dzhafarov, & J. Myung (Eds.), New Handbook of Mathematical Psychology: Foundations and Methodology (Vol. I, pp. 374-453). Cambridge University Press.

  • Marschak, J. (1960). Binary-choice constraints and random utility indicators. In: K. J. Arrow, S. Karlin, & P. Suppes (Eds.), Proceedings of the First Stanford Symposium on Mathematical Methods in the Social Sciences, 1959 (pp. 312-329). Stanford University Press.

  • Morrison, H. W. (1963). Testable conditions for triads of paired comparison choices. Psychometrika, 28, 369–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olschewski, S., Sirotkin, P., & Rieskamp, J. (2022). Empirical underidentification in estimating random utility models: The role of choice sets and standardizations. British Journal of Mathematical and Statistical Psychology, 75(2), 252–292.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, M. A., Kim, W., Navarro, D. J., & Myung, J. I. (2006). Global model analysis by parameter space partitioning. Psychological Review, 113(1), 57.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Quiggin, J. (1994). Regret theory with general choice sets. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 8, 153–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter, M., Cavagnaro, D., Popova, A., Guo, Y., Zwilling, C., Lim, S., & Stevens, J. (2017). Heterogeneity and parsimony in intertemporal choice. Decision, 5, 63–94.

  • Regenwetter, M., Cavagnaro, D., Popova, A., Guo, Y., Zwilling, C., Lim, S. H., & Stevens, J. (2018). Heterogeneity and parsimony in intertemporal choice. Decision, 5(2), 63–94.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter, M., & Cavagnaro, D. R. (2019). Tutorial on removing the shackles of regression analysis: How to stay true to your theory of binary response probabilities. Psychological Methods, 24(2), 135.

  • Regenwetter, M., Dana, J., & Davis-Stober, C. P. (2011). Transitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 118, 42–56.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter, M., & Davis-Stober, C. P. (2012). Behavioral variability of choices versus structural inconsistency of preferences. Psychological Review, 119(2), 408–416.

    Article  PubMed  PubMed Central  Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter, M., Davis-Stober, C. P., Lim, S. H., Guo, Y., Popova, A., Zwilling, C., & Messner, W. (2014). QTest: Quantitative testing of theories of binary choice. Decision, 1(1), 2–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Regenwetter, M., Robinson, M., & Wang, C. (2022). Four internal inconsistencies in Tversky and Kahneman’s (1992) Cumulative Prospect Theory article: A case study in ambiguous theoretical scope and ambiguous parsimony. Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science, 5. Open access: https://journals.sagepub.com/doi/pdf/10.1177/25152459221074653

  • Regenwetter, M., & Robinson, M. M. (2017). The construct-behavior gap in behavioral decision research: A challenge beyond replicability. Psychological Review, 124(5), 533.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Scholten, M., & Read, D. (2010). The psychology of intertemporal tradeoffs. Psychological Review, 117(3), 925–944.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Silvapulle, M. J., & Sen, P. K. (2011). Constrained statistical inference: Order, inequality, and shape constraints (vol 912). John Wiley & Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smeulders, B., Davis-Stober, C., Regenwetter, M., & Spieksma, F. (2017). Testing probabilistic models of choice using column generation. Computers & Operations Research, 95, 32–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stewart, N., Reimers, S., & Harris, A. J. (2014). On the origin of utility, weighting, and discounting functions: How they get their shapes and how to change their shapes. Management Science, 61(3), 687–705.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stott, H. (2006). Cumulative prospect theory’s functional menagerie. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 32, 101–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Thurstone, L. L. (1927). A law of comparative judgement. Psychological Review, 34, 273–286.

  • Tserenjigmid, G. (2021). The order-dependent Luce model. Management Science.

  • Tversky, A. (1969). Intransitivity of preferences. Psychological Review, 76, 31–48.

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1992). Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 5, 297–323.

  • Wakker, P. P., Erev, I., & Weber, E. U. (1994). Comonotonic independence: The critical test between classical and rank-dependent utility theories. Journal of Risk and Uncertainty, 9, 195-230

  • Wilcox, N. (2008) .Stochastic models for binary discrete choice under risk: A critical primer and econometric comparison. In: J. Cox, & G. Harrison (Eds.), Risk aversion in experiments (Vol 12, pp. 197–292). Emerald, Research in Experimental Economics, Bingley, UK.

  • Wilcox, N. (2011). Stochastically more risk averse: A contextual theory of stochastic discrete choice under risk. Journal of Econometrics, 162, 89–104.

  • Yellott, J. I. J. (1977). The relationship between Luce’s choice axiom, Thurstone’s theory of comparative judgement, and the double exponential distribution. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 15, 109–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zwilling, C., Cavagnaro, D., Regenwetter, M., Lim, S., Fields, B., & Zhang, Y. (2019). QTest 2.1: Quantitative testing of theories of binary choice using Bayesian inference. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 91, 176–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

In fond memory of William H. Batchelder (1940–2018). This project was born out of Bill’s stimulating questions about polyhedral representations for (standard) Fechnerian models at a U.C. Irvine-IMBS conference in 2014. The authors thank Meichai Chen, Brittney Currie, Yu Huang, and Emily Neu Line for helpful comments on an earlier version, and Anna Popova for her help with early work on this project.

Funding

Both authors’ work on this project was supported financially by National Science Foundation grant SES # 20-49896 to M. Regenwetter (PI) and D. Cavagnaro (Co-PI). NSF had no other role besides financial support.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Contributions

Both authors contributed equally to this project.

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Daniel R. Cavagnaro.

Ethics declarations

Ethics Approval

Not applicable.

Consent to Participate

Not applicable.

Consent for Publication

Not applicable.

Conflict of Interest

The authors declare no competing interests.

Appendices

Appendix 1. DFMs for more general decision theories

In this section, we illustrate how DFMs work for theories without utility functions. We walk the reader through examples ranging from DFMs for well-known core theories to ideas for novel axiomatizations of strengths of preference. We start with a case where a decision theory generates strengths of preference directly.

Example 14

We briefly consider regret theory, as spelled out by Loomes et al. (1991) with choice options that follow the blue-print of Loomes and Sugden’s Table I (p. 430). The bottom three rows of our Table 5 indicate three choice alternatives,Footnote 11x, y, z. The right three columns denote three different states of the world, \(SW_1, SW_2, SW_3\), and their probabilities. A decision maker who chooses x will receive $5 if the state of the world is \(SW_1\), which has probability 0.2 of occurring, and $2 otherwise. A person who chooses y receives $4 if states of the world \(SW_1\) or \(SW_2\) happen, or $1 if \(SW_3\) happens, which has a probability of 0.3 of occurring. Anyone who chooses z will receive $3 irrespective of the state of the world.

Let \(i_m\) and \(j_m\) denote the outcomes of options i and j in \(SW_m\), and let \(p_m\) denote the probability of the state \(SW_m\). According to this version of regret theory, letting \(\Psi \) be an odd function that is increasing in its first argument and that satisfies \({\Psi (a,c) > \Psi (a,b) + \Psi (b,c)}\), when \(a> b > c\) are monetary amounts, the strength of preference for i over j is \({S(ij) = \sum _{m = 1}^{3} p_m \Psi (i_m,j_m)}\). Consider \({\Psi (i_m,j_m)=(i_m-j_m)^3}\). This yields \({S(xy)=-3.5}\), \({S(xz)=0.8}\), and \({S(yz)=-1.7}\). The resulting DFM forms a tetrahedron, which, using the analogous coordinate system P(xy), P(xz), P(yz) as before, is characterized by the constraints

$$\begin{aligned}&1\ge 1-P(xy)> 1 - P(yz)> P(xz) > \frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$
(24)

These inequalities document how regret theory, on this domain, produces strengths of preference that are not compatible with the weak utility assumption. Namely, they imply \(P(xz)>\nicefrac {1}{2}\), \({P(zy)>\nicefrac {1}{2}}\), and \(P(yx)>\nicefrac {1}{2}\), which violates \(\mathcal {WST}\).

The inequalities in Condition 24 are the facet-defining inequalities of the tetrahedron in the upper-left panel of Fig. 8. That tetrahedron is nested in the half-unit cube shown in the upper-right panel of Fig. 8 (the same as the right panel of Fig. 1, in a different angle of view, which is also the majority specification of an intransitive preference pattern). It also has no overlap with \(\mathcal {WST}\), shown on the lower panels of Fig. 8, which we explain in Examples 15 and 16. The insight that this DFM is not contained in \(\mathcal {WST}\), together with the earlier insight that DFMs need not contain \(\mathcal {WST}\) (see, e.g., Fig. 1), implies the following formal result.

Proposition 7

Let \(\mathcal{M}_\mathcal{S}\) be a DFM as defined in Definition 6. In general, \( \mathcal {WST} \not \subseteq \mathcal{M}_\mathcal{S} \not \subseteq \mathcal {WST}\).

We proceed to DFMs for axiomatic theories that likewise need not evoke the concept of utility. We start with the axioms of transitivity and asymmetry. For the rest of this section, we assume that \(\mathcal{D}\) contains all pairs of options of a given finite choice set.

Table 5 Stimuli for regret theory

Let \(\mathcal {WST^*}\) denote \(\mathcal {WST}\) (Condition 23) with the added constraint that \(P(ij)\ne \nicefrac {1}{2}\) for all \(ij\in \mathcal {D}\). Defining, as before,

$$\begin{aligned} i \!\succ \! j \! \quad \! \Leftrightarrow \quad S(ij)\!>\!0 \! \quad \!\Leftrightarrow \quad P(ij) \!>\! \frac{1}{2}, \qquad \forall ij \in \mathcal{D}, \end{aligned}$$
(25)

it is well known that \(\mathcal {WST}^*\) is equivalent to transitivity of the preference relation \(\succ \), namely,

$$\begin{aligned} i \succ j \quad \wedge \quad j \succ k \quad \Rightarrow \quad i \succ k, \qquad \forall ij, jk, ik \in \mathcal{D}. \end{aligned}$$

Writing \(i \not \succ j\) to denote that \(i \succ j\) does not hold, since \({S(ij)>0\Rightarrow S(ji)\not > 0}\), the preference relation \(\succ \) defined in Condition 25 is asymmetric, i.e., \({i \succ j \Rightarrow j \not \succ i}\). This gives us the tools to better understand the geometry associated with \(\mathcal {WST}\) and \(\mathcal {WST^*}\), and axiomatic theories more broadly (for early related work, including geometric visualizations of \(\mathcal {WST}\) and other types of stochastic transitivity, see Morrison, 1963).

Example 15

If \(S(ij)~\ne ~0,~\forall ij \in \mathcal{D}\) then the preference relation \(\succ \) defined in Condition 25 is complete, i.e., for all distinct choice options ij it holds that either \(i \succ j\) or \(j \succ i\). A complete, asymmetric, transitive binary relation is a strict linear order (ranking, permutation) of the choice options. \(\mathcal {WST}^*\) rules out \(P(ij)=\nicefrac {1}{2}\), and therefore implies \(S(ij)~\ne ~0\) through Condition 25. As a consequence, \(\mathcal {WST}^*\) could be labeled the DFM for the collection of all strict linear orders through the lens of Condition 25. For three choice alternatives, this DFM forms a disjoint union of six open half-unit cubes (lower-left panel of Fig. 8). The figure uses the coordinate system P(xy), P(xz), P(yz). Characterizing the six component cubes of \(\mathcal {WST^*}\) involves facet-defining inequalities of the form \(P(ij)>\nicefrac {1}{2}\), or \(P(ij)>0\), or \(P(ij)<1\) (each with suitably selected ij).

While Example 15 constructed the DFM for complete, asymmetric, transitive preference relations, we now consider the DFM for a slightly different combination of axioms.

Example 16

When S(ij) is also allowed to be zero, the relation \(\succ \) need not be complete. A binary relation \(\succ \) is negatively transitive if and only if \(i \not \succ j \wedge j \not \succ k \Rightarrow i \not \succ k\), for all ijk. If \(\succ \) is defined as in Condition 25 then \(\mathcal {WST}\) holds if and only if \(\succ \) is negatively transitive. Asymmetric negatively transitive binary relations are strict weak orders. \(\mathcal {WST}\) allows \(P(ij)=\nicefrac {1}{2}\) for some pairs and therefore allows \(S(ij)=0\) for some pairs. Consequently, \(\mathcal {WST}\) could be labeled the DFM for the collection of all strict weak orders through the lens of Condition 25. In the case of three choice alternatives, there are 13 strict weak orders. Here, the DFM consists of the disjoint union of the six half-unit open cubes we just reviewed for the six strict linear orders, together with six open 2-dimensional half-unit squares and the point \((\nicefrac {1}{2}, \nicefrac {1}{2}, \nicefrac {1}{2})\). Figure 8 shows the 3-dimensional polytopes of this model in the lower-left panel, and the lower-dimensional polytopes in the lower-right panel, all in the coordinate system P(xy), P(xz), P(yz). Line segments of the form \({P(ij) = P(jk) = \nicefrac {1}{2}< P(ik) < 1}\) (written in a suitable coordinate system) are not included in this model because the corresponding preferences violate negative transitivity (i.e., \(i \not \succ j\) and \( j \not \succ k\) but \(i \succ k\)). These line segments represent “semiorders” with transitive preference and intransitive indifference (Luce , 1956), which we sketch in the next example. That example moves beyond all examples we have seen so far in that it explores how to convert axioms, here those for interval orders and semiorders, into novel axioms about strengths of preference.

Example 17

A binary relation \(\succ \) is an interval order if and onlyFootnote 12 if

$$\begin{aligned}{}[ i \succ j \quad \wedge \quad k \succ \ell ] \quad&\Rightarrow \quad [ i \succ \ell \quad \vee \quad k \succ j ]. \end{aligned}$$

An interval order \(\succ \) is a semiorder if and only if

$$\begin{aligned}{}[ i \succ j \quad \wedge \quad j \succ k ] \quad&\Rightarrow \quad [ i \succ \ell \quad \vee \quad \ell \succ k ]. \end{aligned}$$

These two axioms could inspire novel axioms about strengths of preference, such as

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} [ S(ij)> 0 \quad \wedge \quad S(k\ell ) > 0 ] \quad \Rightarrow \\ {}{} & {} \,\,\,\,\,\,\quad \quad \qquad \qquad \max (S(i\ell ), S(kj)) \ge \min (S(ij), S(k\ell )), \end{aligned}$$

respectively

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} [ S(ij)> 0 \quad \wedge \quad S(jk) > 0 ] \quad \Rightarrow \\ {}{} & {} \,\,\,\,\,\,\quad \quad \qquad \qquad \max (S(i\ell ), S(\ell k)) \ge \min (S(ij), S(jk)). \end{aligned}$$

We finish this section with a generalization of hierarchical decision strategies, such as “lexicographic semiorders” (see, e.g., Tversky, 1969).

Fig. 8
figure 8

Regret DFM of Example 14 (upper-left panel), half-unit cube for intransitive preference \(y\succ x\), \(x \succ z\), \(z \succ y\) (upper-right panel), and geometric representations of \(\mathcal {WST^*}\) (lower-left panel) and \(\mathcal {WST}\) (union of lower panels). Note. Dashed lines in the lower-right panel are for enhancing 3D visualization and have no special meaning

Example 18

One can readily imagine DFMs for various sorts of lexicographic decision processes, say in consumer choice. Consider a shopper comparing two computers or televisions who follows a hierarchy of attributes, say, price, then screen resolution, followed by screen size, etc. When considering an attribute, they stop the decision process when that attribute meets a stopping criterion, otherwise proceed to the next attribute. For instance, writing \(S_n(ij)\) for the strength of preference for i over j according to attribute n, suppose that

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} S_1(xy) = 2; \quad S_2(xy) = 0; \quad S_3(xy) = 1; \quad S_4(xy) = 50; \\ {}{} & {} S_5(xy) = -1; \quad S_6(xy) = -20; \end{aligned}$$

and

$$\begin{aligned}{} & {} S_1(wz) = 1; \quad S_2(wz) = 60; \quad S_3(wz) = 1; \\ {}{} & {} S_4(wz) = -30; \quad S_5(wz) = 15; \quad S_6(wz) = 10. \end{aligned}$$

Suppose the decision maker has some decision threshold \(\delta \) and sequentially, i.e., lexicographically, considers attributes until \(|S_m(ij)| > \delta \) for some m, then adopts the strength of preference according to that attribute. A decision maker with \(\delta = 0\) stops the search process at the first attribute for both \(\{x,y\}\) and \(\{w,z\}\), with overall strengths of preference \({S(xy) = S_1(xy) = 2}\) and \({S(wz) = S_1(wz) = 1}\) and, hence \(P(xy) > P(wz).\) A decision maker with \(\delta = 10\) has strengths of preference \({S(xy)= S_4(xy) = 50}\) and \({S(wz) = S_2(wz) = 60}\) and, hence \(P(xy) < P(wz).\) One can also design novel DFMs in which attribute-wise strengths of preference are somehow accumulated to weigh reasons in favor or against one option over another, similar to the “perceived relative argument” model of Loomes (2010).

Appendix 2. Proofs

Proof of Proposition 1

$$\begin{aligned} S(ij)> 0\Leftrightarrow & {} S(ji)<0 \\\Leftrightarrow & {} S(ji)< S(ij) \\\Leftrightarrow & {} P(ji)< P(ij) \\\Leftrightarrow & {} 1-P(ij) < P(ij) \\\Leftrightarrow & {} P(ij) > \frac{1}{2}. \end{aligned}$$

\(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 2

Let S be an odd, real-valued function on the domain \(\mathcal{D}\) and let \(\mathcal{D}'\) be any maximal subset of \(\mathcal{D}\), such that S is one-to-one on \(\mathcal{D}'\), i.e., for any distinct ij and \(k\ell \) in \(\mathcal{D}', S(ij) \ne S(k\ell )\). In particular, if S is a one-to-one function on \(\mathcal{D}\) then \(\mathcal{D}' = \mathcal{D}\). Let \(\mathcal{D}'_{S^+}~=~\{ij~\in ~\mathcal{{D}'}~|~S(ij)>0\}\). If \(ij \in \mathcal{D'}\) then \(S(ij) \ne 0\) and therefore \(ji \in \mathcal{D'}\), since \(S(ji) = -S(ij)\). Therefore, for each \(ij \in \mathcal{D'}\), exactly one of ij or ji is in \(\mathcal{D'}_{S^+}\). As a consequence, \(|\mathcal{D}'_{S^+}| = \frac{|\mathcal{D'}|}{2}\). We denote \(|\mathcal{D}'_{S^+}|\) as n. Since S is one-to-one on \(\mathcal{D}'\), there is a unique one-to-one function \(f: X = \{1,2,\ldots ,n\} \rightarrowtail \mathcal{D}'_{S^+}\), which orders the elements of \(\mathcal{D}'_{S^+}\) by decreasing strength of preference, i.e., such that \(S(f(x)) > S(f({x+1}) )\) for \(1 \le x \le n-1\). According to the Fechnerian property (6) for S, a binary choice vector P is in \(\mathcal{M}_S\) if and only if

$$\begin{aligned} 1> & {} P(f(1)), \end{aligned}$$
(26)
$$\begin{aligned} P(f(x))> & {} P(f(x+1)) \text { for } 1 \le x \le n-1, \end{aligned}$$
(27)
$$\begin{aligned} P\left( f(n)\right)> & {} \frac{1}{2}, \end{aligned}$$
(28)

by construction. Each of these \(n+1\) inequality constraints defines a half-space in \(\mathbb {R}^{n}\). The intersection of these half-spaces is contained in \(]0,1[^n\) and, therefore, forms a convex polytope of dimension n. Because they form \(n+1\) nonredundant constraints describing a convex polytope, Inequalities 2628 are facet-defining for that polytope. This construction of a polytope and of facets does not depend on the initial choice of \(\mathcal{D}'\). As \(\mathcal{D}'\) varies, the facet-defining inequalities (2628) are stated in terms of different coordinates in \(\mathbb {R}^{n}\), but in conjunction with the equivalence \(S(ij) = S(k\ell ) \Leftrightarrow P(ij)= P(k\ell )\), they form the same convex polytope in \(]0,1[^\mathcal{D}\). \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 3

Let \(S_1,S_2\in \mathcal{S}\) be strength-of-preference functions on \(\mathcal{D}\), and suppose \({P\in \mathcal{M}_{{S}_1} \cap \mathcal{M}_{{S}_2}}\). Then, by definition

$$\begin{aligned} S_1(ij)> S_1(k\ell ) \Leftrightarrow P(ij)> P(k\ell ) \Leftrightarrow S_2(ij) > S_2(k\ell ). \end{aligned}$$

Therefore, by the construction in the proof of Proposition 4, \(\mathcal{M}_{S_1}\) and \(\mathcal{M}_{S_2}\) form identical polytopes nested in  \(]0,1[^\mathcal{D}\). Since there are only finitely many rankings (with possible ties) of \(\frac{|\mathcal {D}|}{2}\) many choice probabilities from largest to smallest, there are also only finitely many such convex polytopes possible. \(\square \)

Proof of Proposition 4

Now, suppose that \(\mathcal{S}\) is maximal. Since we have already shown that the convex polytopes under consideration are disjoint, we only need to show that they form a complete partition of  \(]0,1[^\mathcal{{D}}\). Let \(P\in ~]0,1[^\mathcal{D}\) be a binary choice vector on \(\mathcal{D}\). To show that there exists a Fechnerian model family \(\mathcal{M}_S\) containing P, define a strength-of-preference function S on \(\mathcal{D}\) by \(S(ij)=P(ij)-1/2,\) for all \(ij\in \mathcal{D}\). Then P satisfies Condition 6, hence P is a Fechnerian model for S. \(\square \)

Appendix 3. Facet-defining inequalities for panels 3 and 4 of Fig. 2

In the third panel from the left, the left tetrahedron is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} 0< & {} P(xy)< P(xz)< P(yz)< \frac{1}{2}< P(zy)< P(zx) \\ {}< & {} P(yx) < 1, \end{aligned}$$

i.e., \(S(xy)< S(xz)< S(yz)< 0< S(zy)< S(zx) < S(yx)\). In that panel, the right tetrahedron is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} 0< & {} P(yz)< P(xz)< P(xy)< \frac{1}{2}< P(yx)< P(zx) \\ {}< & {} P(zy) < 1, \end{aligned}$$

i.e., \(S(yz)< S(xz)< S(xy)< 0< S(yx)< S(zx) < S(zy)\). These are on opposite sides of the line segment defined by \(0< P(yz) = P(xz) = P(xy) < \frac{1}{2}\), which is also the convex hull of \(\Big (0,0,0\Big )\) and \(\Big (\frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2},\frac{1}{2}\Big )\).

In the right-most panel of Fig. 2, the left tetrahedron is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} 0< & {} P(xy)< P(yz)< P(xz)< \frac{1}{2}< P(zx)< P(zy) \\ {}< & {} P(yx) < 1, \end{aligned}$$

i.e., \(S(xy)< S(yz)< S(xz)< 0< S(zx)< S(zy) < S(yx)\). In that panel, the left tetrahedron is defined by

$$\begin{aligned} 0< & {} P(yz)< P(xy)< P(xz)< \frac{1}{2}< P(zx)< P(yx) \\ {}< & {} P(zy) < 1, \end{aligned}$$

i.e., \(S(yz)< S(xy)< S(xz)< 0< S(zx)< S(yx) < S(zy).\) These are on opposite sides of the triangle defined by \(0< P(yz) = P(xy)< P(xz) < \frac{1}{2}\).

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Cavagnaro, D.R., Regenwetter, M. Probabilistic Choice Induced by Strength of Preference. Comput Brain Behav 6, 569–600 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s42113-023-00176-3

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s42113-023-00176-3

Keywords

Navigation