Skip to main content
Log in

Dictator choice and causal attribution of recipient endowment

  • Article
  • Published:
Indian Economic Review Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a laboratory experiment, two dictators give serially to a common recipient. In all treatment conditions, the second dictator knows the outcome in the first game. We vary the nature of the dictator in the first game across different treatments. We ask if the resulting variation in the attribution of intent to the prior causal dictator affects giving in the second game. We find that causal attribution has no effect on average giving, but may impact marginal giving. In particular, giving in the second game is negatively correlated with that in the first only when the first dictator has self-interest. We further find that giving is not affected by knowledge of recipient endowment and falls over the sequence of games.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This compensatory effect is similar in form to the crowding out of private charitable giving by governmental redistribution schemes as identified first by Warr (1982).

  2. Potential recipients are sometimes classified as ‘deserving’ or ‘undeserving’ (Bridges 2017), according to the extent to which they can be blamed for their condition. All recipients in our experiment are by default ‘deserving’, concomitant of them being anonymous and non-differentiated as subjects. Our results indicate that even when individuals cannot be blamed for their economic condition, some may still be by the nature of the process that got them to a particular endowment found to be more deserving for assistance than others.

  3. A condition where a computer program is used to select divisions using a random rule, and the rule is announced to the subjects, was not conducted: see Sect. 4.3 for a discussion of this issue.

  4. This includes a show-up fee of INR 50. USD 1 was approximately PPP equivalent to INR 17.81 in 2017, as per the World Bank International Comparison Program database (https://data.worldbank.org/indicator/pa.nus.ppp).

  5. We found negligible difference across sessions for any condition. All reported results use data pooled across sessions.

  6. Comparisons of second game giving across Human and Human3R, or Human3R and CompU for example are not useful for us as the two groups compared differ in terms of both personality and allocation rule.

  7. This effect is stronger in the Tobit formulation (coefficient on Recipient Endowment* HumanN = − 0.36).

  8. We assume that C’s utility does not depend on A’s wealth. Note that the effects of A’s payoff and B’s endowment on C’s decision are not separately identifiable in our data, as the sum of these is constant.

  9. Allowing for the possibility of \({\alpha }^{j\text{'}}<0\) would have led to a norm potentially admitting mimicry, with giving by C increasing in B’s prior receipt. We do not permit this option, as it is not supported by our data (see below).

  10. Variation in the norm or adjustment factor with respect to condition or situation j is consistent with prior results on empathic responses (e.g., Eckel and Grossman 1996; Klimecki et al., 2016; Thunström et al., 2016), showing that dictators take into account social attributes of the recipient when deciding to give.

  11. Separability, assumed throughout the paper, eases calculations. Conclusions presented remain valid if separability is relaxed, provided that appropriate restrictions are imposed on certain cross partials.

  12. A’s payoff is unaffected by and fixed at the time of C’s decision. Additionally, C is aware that A was not aware at the time of her own choice that C would be taking a decision in the future. For this reason, we assume in this and following models that C’s utility is not affected by payoff accruing separately to A. See also fn. 6.

  13. See Sect. 3 in Falk and Fischbacher (2006).

  14. See Sect. 4.3.3 in Falk and Fischbacher (2006) and Sect. 8.6 in Falk and Fischbacher (2006).

  15. While sequential dictator games have been studied in the literature (e.g., Cason and Mui 1998; Potters and Xu 2018), we are not aware of any prior study where the same recipient faces different dictators.

  16. Equivalent Tobit censored regressions are run for all OLS regressions discussed in the paper. Results are qualitatively identical across OLS and tobit models. We do not report the tobit output in any case for brevity.

References

  • Andreoni, J. (1989). Giving with impure altruism: Applications to charity and Ricardian equivalence. Journal of Political Economy, 97, 1447–1458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Andreoni, J. (1990). Impure altruism and donations to public goods: A theory of warm-glow giving. Economic Journal, 100, 464–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Becker, G. (1974). A theory of social interactions. Journal of Political Economy, 82, 1063–1093.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Blount, S. (1995). When social outcomes aren’t fair: The effect of causal attributions on preferences. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 63, 131–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, G., & Katok, E. (1998). An experimental test of the crowding out hypothesis: The nature of beneficent behavior. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 37, 315–331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolton, G., & Ockenfels, A. (2000). ERC: A theory of equity, reciprocity and competition. American Economic Review, 90, 166–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridges, K. (2017). The deserving poor, the undeserving poor, and class-based affirmative action. Emory Law Journal, 66, 1049.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cappelen, A., Hole, A., Sørensen, E., & Tungodden, B. (2007). The pluralism of fairness ideals: An experimental approach. American Economic Review, 97, 818–827.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cason, T., & Mui, V.-L. (1998). Social influence in the sequential dictator game. Journal of Mathematical Psychology, 42, 248–265.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness, G. (2000). Responsibility and effort in an experimental labor market. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 42, 375–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness, G. (2004). Attribution and reciprocity in an experimental labor market. Journal of Labor Economics, 22, 665–688.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness, G., & Dufwenberg, M. (2006). Promises and partnership. Econometrica, 74, 1579–1601.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Charness, G., & Rabin, M. (2002). Understanding social preferences with simple tests. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 117, 817–869.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chowdhury, S., & Jeon, J. (2014). Impure altruism or inequality aversion? An experimental investigation based on income effects. Journal of Public Economics, 118, 143–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cox, J. (2004). How to identify trust and reciprocity. Games and Economic Behavior, 46, 260–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dufwenberg, M., & Kirchsteiger, G. (2004). A theory of sequential reciprocity. Games and Economic Behavior, 47, 268–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eckel, C., & Grossman, P. (1996). Altruism in anonymous dictator games. Games and Economic Behavior, 16, 181–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Engel, C. (2011). Dictator games: A meta study. Experimental Economics, 14, 538–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., & Fischbacher, U. (2006). A theory of reciprocity. Games and Economic Behavior, 54, 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Falk, A., Fehr, E., & Fischbacher, U. (2008). Testing theories of fairness—intentions matter. Games and Economic Behavior, 62, 287–303.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fehr, E., & Schmidt, K. (1999). A theory of fairness, competition and cooperation. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 114, 817–868.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forsythe, R., Horowitz, J., Savin, N., & Sefton, M. (1994). Fairness in simple bargaining experiments. Games and Economic Behavior, 6, 347–369.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J., & Thaler, R. (1986). Fairness and the assumptions of economics. Journal of Business, 59, S285-300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kessler, J., & Leider, S. (2012). Norms and contracting. Management Science, 58, 62–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klimecki, O., Mayer, S., Jusyte, A., Scheeff, J., & Schönenberg, M. (2016). Empathy promotes altruistic behavior in economic interactions. Scientific Reports, 6, 31961. https://doi.org/10.1038/srep31961

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konow, J. (2010). Mixed feelings: Theories of and evidence on giving. Journal of Public Economics, 94, 279–297.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Korenok, O., Millner, E., & Razzolini, L. (2012). Are dictators averse to inequality? Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 82, 543–547.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • López-Pérez, R. (2008). Aversion to norm-breaking: A model. Games and Economic Behavior, 64, 237–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Offerman, T. (2002). Hurting hurts more than helping helps. European Economic Review, 46, 1423–1437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potters, J., & Xu, Y. (2018). Social information and selfishness, working paper, University of Heidelberg

  • Rabin, M. (1993). Incorporating fairness into game theory and economics. American Economic Review, 83, 1281–1302.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thunström, L., Cherry, T., McEvoy, D., & Shogren, J. (2016). Endogenous context in a dictator game. Journal of Behavioral and Experimental Economics, 65, 117–120.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trautmann, S. (2009). A tractable model of process fairness under risk. Journal of Economic Psychology, 30, 803–813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warr, P. (1982). Pareto optimal redistribution and private charity. Journal of Public Economics, 19, 131–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sujoy Chakravarty.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

On behalf of all authors, the corresponding author states that there is no conflict of interest.

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

We are grateful to the University Grants Commission for providing financial support under the UPE II (2014–19) scheme and indebted to Ritwik Banerjee, Timothy Cason, Subhashis Modak Chowdhury, Sugato Dasgupta, Sanmitra Ghosh, Joo Young Jeon, Oleg Korenok, James Konow, Edward Millner, Jaideep Roy, and Parvathy for their comments and feedback. We retain responsibility for all errors and omissions.

Appendices

Appendix A: Theoretical background

1.1 A1: Deriving the hypotheses

Focusing on the second game, suppose we interpret any endowment e present with a recipient as arising from the amount received in a prior dictator game. Theoretical models of dictator giving posit utility functions which are defined effectively over ex post wealth of the recipient, or beliefs over it. Since these theories are familiar, we relegate a detailed discussion (including the derivation of relationships we refer to in this section) to Appendix A3, and consider here for example the reference point-based dictator utility function below, based on Bolton and Ockenfels (2000), where y is the amount the dictator keeps for herself out of an endowment normalized to 1, \(\sigma\) is the norm or social reference point for giving (the reference point of ex post-equality is typically assumed to be the social norm, with \(\sigma =\frac{1+e}{2}\)), u is an increasing and concave function, and v is a concave function reaching a maximum at y = \(\sigma\)

$$U\left(y;\sigma \right)=u\left(y\right)+v(y-\sigma )=u\left(y\right)+v\left(y-\frac{1+e}{2}\right)$$

As can be seen, the dictator’s utility is independent of the source of the recipient’s endowment. Hence, attributional concerns cannot affect the amount given by C, which we denote as x*. In our experiment, since the distribution of allocations in the first game are the same across Human, Human3U, Human3R, and CompU by design, these models predict for the first question that average second game choices are identical across these four conditions. Similarly, for the second question, these predict that as long as there are sufficiently many C subjects choosing to give positive amounts and sufficiently many B subjects with positive endowment, there should be a negative relationship between e and x* in any of Human, Human3U, Human3R, and CompU. Also similarly, for the comparison of average giving across the first and second games for conditions Human, Human3U, Human3R, and CompU (part of the third question), these predict that as long as there are sufficiently many C subjects choosing to give positive amounts and sufficiently many B subjects with positive endowment, average giving should be higher by A subjects compared to C subjects.

For the rest of the answer to the third question, and for the answer to the fourth question, we need to specify the belief of a C subject in HumanN, who does not know what endowment her matched B subject has, but knows it may be positive. Suppose she conjectures that the endowment is \(\hat{e}\) ≥ 0. For the comparison across average giving in the first and second games for HumanN (third question), the models then predict that as long as sufficiently many C subjects conjecture \(\hat{e}\) > 0, giving should be less in the second game. Hence, for the third question as a whole, allocation by the second dictator is lower than that by the first, because the former anticipates that the recipient’s endowment may be positive.

The answer to the fourth question depends on the comparison between the distribution of \(\hat{e}\) among C subjects in HumanN and the actual distribution of giving by A subjects in Human. If these are the same, then all the models predict that information on the amount received by the matched recipient should not impact average dictator giving in the second game, leading to indistinguishable second game choices on average across HumanN and Human. For the first and fourth questions together, the prediction is therefore that the distribution of allocations by second dictators when they know the allocations by the first dictators equals the distribution when they do not know yet correctly anticipate the aggregate distribution. Overall, the prediction for any of the four questions is invariant across these models.

1.2 A2: A model allowing for attributional effects

On the other hand, if attributional concerns can affect choice in the dictator game, as Blount (1995) and others found for ultimatum and other games, then average second game choices may differ across Human, Human3U, Human3R and CompU (first question), and the relationship between e and x* (second question) may not be negative in any of these four conditions, and may be different across them. Here, we sketch a simple extension of the reference point-based model above, based on Cappelen et al. (2007), López-Pérez (2008) and Kessler and Leider (2012), which permits attributional concerns to affect choice. Specifically, we allow the reference point for C to depend not only on what B received from her earlier interaction, but also on how it was obtained, i.e., the nature or intention of the prior decision-maker.

Consider the first game in conditions HumanN and Human, where the recipient B has no endowment or history of prior interaction. This corresponds to the version of the dictator game commonly studied in the literature. We assume the ex post-equality norm continues to apply in this benchmark case unaltered. Letting \({\sigma }_{1}\) and \({\sigma }_{2}\), respectively, denote reference points in games 1 and 2, we have \({\sigma }_{1}=\frac{1}{2}\).

Now, consider dictator C in the second game in condition HumanN, who knows B has interacted with an earlier dictator. Although he does not know how much B received in that interaction, he may consider the possibility that she received a positive amount. It seems reasonable to posit that C’s desire to divide his own endowment equally may then be impaired relative to a dictator in game 1, since he takes into account that B may already be in possession of some wealth.Footnote 8 We suppose therefore for this case that the norm of how much to keep is adjusted relative to \({\sigma }_{1}\): \({\sigma }_{2}^{HumanN}=\frac{1}{2}+{\varphi }^{HumanN}\), where \({\varphi }^{HumanN}\) is the adjustment factor. Let ê be his conjecture regarding how much A gave to B and \(\stackrel{\sim }{{e}}\) be his belief or position, which could be socially determined or influenced, with respect to how much B should have received from A. We assume \(\varphi^{HumanN} \left( {\hat{e},\tilde{e}} \right) = \alpha^{HumanN} \left( {\hat{e} - \tilde{e}} \right) + \beta^{HumanN} \left( {\tilde{e}} \right)\), \(\alpha^{HumanN} \left( 0 \right) = 0\), \(\alpha^{{HumanN^{\prime}}} > 0\), \(\beta^{HumanN} \left( 0 \right) = 0\), and \(\beta^{{HumanN^{\prime}}} > 0\). The factor thus is the sum of an absolute component, dependent on position alone, and a relative component, an adjustment depending on whether A’s conjectured giving exceeds or falls short of that position. For the determination of \(\hat{e}\), we assume that the dictator considers himself representative. We take this to imply in this context a belief that B has received what C would have given her had he been in the role of A, so that \(\hat{e} ={x}_{1}^{*}=1-{y}_{1}^{*}\), where \({y}_{1}^{*}\) and \({x}_{1}^{*}\) are, respectively, the amounts individual C would have optimally kept for himself and given to the recipient in the benchmark environment. For the determination of \(\tilde{e }\), we appeal again to representativeness and take it to imply in this context that C holds that A should have given what C would have given had he been in the role of A, so that \(\tilde{e }={x}_{1}^{*}\). We therefore have \({\sigma }_{2}^{HumanN}=\frac{1}{2}+{\beta }^{HumanN}\left({x}_{1}^{*}\right)\). The benchmark norm is thus restored if C believes A gave nothing. As long as solutions are interior, giving by C should be lower compared to giving by A under these assumptions.

We now consider the second game in conditions Human, Human3U, Human3R, and CompU, and assume an adjustment factor similar to the one in IB, with the difference that C knows e, the amount B received from the earlier interaction. Let therefore \({\sigma }_{2}^{j}=\frac{1}{2}+{\varphi }^{j}\), and \({\varphi }^{j}\left(e,\tilde{e }\right)={\alpha }^{j}\left(e-\tilde{e }\right)+{\beta }^{j}\left(\tilde{e }\right)\), \({\alpha }^{j}\left(0\right)=0\),\({\alpha }^{j{^{\prime}}}>0\), \({\beta }^{j}\left(0\right)=0\) and \({\beta }^{j{^{\prime}}}>0\),\(j\in \{Human, Human3U, Human3R,CompU\}\).Footnote 9 Appealing to representativeness again yields \(\tilde{e }={x}_{1}^{*}\), so that \({\varphi }^{j}={\alpha }^{j}\left(e-{x}_{1}^{*}\right)+{\beta }^{j}\left({x}_{1}^{*}\right)\) and \({\sigma }_{2}^{j}=\frac{1}{2}+{\alpha }^{j}\left(e-{x}_{1}^{*}\right)+{\beta }^{j}\left({x}_{1}^{*}\right)\).

The formulation above allows for parsimonious description. Knowledge of a second dictator’s decision, her belief with regard to how much a first dictator should have given, i.e., how much she would have given had she been the first dictator, and her functional forms \(u\), \(v\), \(\alpha\), and \(\beta\), permit the use of the decision as second dictator as a proxy for decision as the first.

In terms of this model, findings presented in Sects. 4.1 and 4.2, and Appendix B1 indicate that for \(j,j{^{\prime}}\in \{Human3U,Human3R,CompU\}\), \({\alpha }^{j{^{\prime}}}={\alpha }^{j}=0\) and \({\beta }^{j}={\beta }^{IB}\), whereas \({\alpha }^{SI{^{\prime}}}>0\).Footnote 10 An interesting finding (Sect. 4.1 and Appendix B2) is that average second game giving in condition Human is the same as that in any other condition. It is implied if the adjustment (\(\alpha\)) in giving by C in Human is on average zero and \({\beta }^{Human}={\beta }^{HumanN}\). The extended model thus allows a unified explanation for all our findings under the maintained assumptions.

1.3 A3: Theories of giving by dictators

Several theoretical frameworks have been advanced to explain why dictators may give positive amounts. We briefly describe examples of some prominent such theories below. Specifically, we discuss altruism theory, models where preferences are influenced by reference points regarding posterior wealth distributions, and hybrid models combining distributional preferences with reactivity to attributions of intent.

As a note, models based on preferences for aggregate efficiency or maximin preferences (e.g., Charness & Rabin, 2002) have also been fruitfully applied to explain data from one-shot distribution experiments. Korenok et al (2012) report poor performance of such models in an experimental setting close to ours; we hence do not focus on these. Similarly, models based on guilt aversion (Charness & Dufwenberg, 2006) can explain positive giving in the dictator game. Under the usual interpretation of guilt aversion, however, the recipient's belief is over how much he will get from the dictator, resulting in no direct link between the dictator's giving and the recipient's prior receipt, a key consideration of this paper. We thus do not focus on such models either.

In the impure altruism theory of Andreoni (1989, 1990), a dictator choosing how much of a surplus to share with the recipient obtains utility from (a) the amount she keeps for herself, as in classical models, (b) the well-being or ex-post payoff of the recipient (pure altruism, Becker, 1974), and (c) the amount she gives to the recipient (warm glow, the source of impurity in altruism). As Konow (2010) points out, the warm glow element, originally introduced to address empirical findings related to public good games, has little marginal importance in the dictator game. We represent the overall utility function of an altruistic dictator using the classical and purely altruistic parts, with the warm glow element eliminated. It is easy to show in the current environment that qualitative results are invariant to the presence of this element (see Konow, 2010, Sect. 3.1), leading to essential equivalence between models of pure and impure altruism. This is not true in all environments, though: for an example, see Chowdhury and Jeon (2014).

Suppose a dictator is deciding how much to give to a recipient out of a surplus, normalized to 1. Let x be amount she gives to the recipient, and y be the amount she keeps for herself, with x + y = 1. We assume that i) the dictator has no endowment other than the surplus to be divided, and ii) the recipient has an endowment \(e\in \left[\mathrm{0,1}\right]\), which cannot be shared. The overall utility function UA (assuming separability for simplicity) is as followsFootnote 11:

$$U_{A} \left( {y;e} \right) = u\left( y \right) + f\left( {e + x} \right) \ldots$$
(1)

u(.) represents material utility, while f(.) represents altruistic utility in (1).Footnote 12 Both functions are assumed to be differentiable, monotone increasing and strictly concave: u′ > 0, u″ < 0, f′ > 0, f″ < 0.

The dictator maximizes (1) subject to \(y\in \left[\mathrm{0,1}\right]\) and x + y = 1. The solution for x is unique and the first-order condition is \(u{^{\prime}}\left(1-x\right)=f{^{\prime}}\left(e+x\right)\). For interior solution with x* > 0, Konow (2010, Proposition 1) shows that \(\frac{\mathrm{d}{x}^{*}}{\mathrm{d}e}=\frac{-{f}^{{^{\prime}}{^{\prime}}}}{{u}^{{^{\prime}}{^{\prime}}}+{f}^{{^{\prime}}{^{\prime}}}}<0\).

In models based on reference points, a dictator’s utility from giving an amount is dependent on a reference point for giving or posterior inequality. Here, we present a typical model, with a reference point defined purely in terms of payoff-linked variables such as giving or posterior wealth positions. An example would be the inequality aversion model of Bolton and Ockenfels (2000) or the conditional altruism model of Konow (2010), the latter with any warm glow element suppressed (an extension with a non-consequentialist reference point is presented in Appendix A1). Two factors affect the utility a dictator gets from giving a part of the surplus to her matched recipient: (a) the amount she keeps for herself (y), as in altruism theory, and (b) the difference between the amount she keeps for herself and the amount to be kept (\(\sigma\)), as specified by a norm or social reference point for a dictator in her situation. The reference point of ex post-equality is typically assumed to be the social norm: \(\sigma =\frac{1+e}{2}\). Using the same notation and assumptions as for altruism theory, we represent the overall utility function (again assuming separability) of a dictator as follows:

$$U_{I} \left( {y;\sigma } \right) = u\left( y \right) + v\left( {y - \sigma } \right) \to U_{I} \left( {y;e} \right) = u\left( y \right) + v\left( {y - \frac{1 + e}{2}} \right) \ldots$$
(2)

e is recipient endowment, and x + y = 1 (v is assumed to be defined over the difference between y and \(\sigma\) for simplicity). u(.) has the same interpretation and properties as in (1). For v, we assume that \({{v}^{{\prime}}\left(y\right)}_{y=\sigma }=0\) and \({v}^{{{\prime\prime}}}\left(y\right)<0\). The dictator maximizes (2) subject to \(y\in \left[\mathrm{0,1}\right]\). The solution for y is unique, y* ≥ \(\frac{1+e}{2}\), and the first-order condition is \({u}^{{\prime}}\left(y\right)+{v}^{{\prime}}\left(y-\frac{1+e}{2}\right)=0\). For interior solution with y* < 1, it follows that \(\frac{\mathrm{d}{y}^{*}}{\mathrm{d}e}=\frac{{v}^{{^{\prime}}{^{\prime}}}}{2\left({u}^{{^{\prime}}{^{\prime}}}+{v}^{{^{\prime}}{^{\prime}}}\right)}\). Since y* > \(\frac{1+e}{2}=\sigma\), the properties assumed for u and v imply \(\frac{\mathrm{d}{y}^{*}}{\mathrm{d}e}>0\), and so \(\frac{\mathrm{d}{x}^{*}}{\mathrm{d}e}<0\).

Findings from various distribution experiments have led to models (e.g., Falk & Fischbacher, 2006; Trautmann, 2009) which combine distributional preferences with a role for perceived intentions or procedural considerations (Dufwenberg & Kirchsteiger, 2004; Rabin, 1993). We focus on Falk and Fischbacher (2006) as they provide an explicit analysis of the dictator game. In their model, developed to analyze sequential move games, a player’s utility depends on (a) her own ex post payoff, as in other theories, (b) her perception of the ‘kindness’ of the other player, as measured by expected ex post payoff difference, and (c) her ‘reciprocal response’, as measured by how her action affects the ex post-expected payoff of the other player.Footnote 13 They impose some linearity assumptions for their applications. For the dictator game, the utility function for a dictator reduces to (the notation is as above).Footnote 14

$$U_{F} \left( {y; \, \tilde{x},e} \right) = y + \frac{1}{b}\left( {1 - 2\tilde{x} - e} \right)\left( {x - \tilde{x}} \right) \ldots$$
(3)

x, y, and e are as defined before, so x + y = 1, and \(b\) is a positive parameter. \(\tilde{x }\) is the dictator’s belief regarding the recipient’s belief about the amount the dictator will give. Their solution concept (reciprocity equilibrium; see Falk & Fischbacher, 2006, Sect. 3.4) derives \(\tilde{x }\) from the first-order condition when the right-hand side of (3) is differentiated with respect to x: \(\tilde{x }=\frac{1-b-e}{2}\). Replacing in (3), it follows (see Proposition 8 in Falk & Fischbacher, 2006) that the solution for x is unique and given by \({x}^{*}=\mathrm{max}\left[0,\frac{1}{2}\left(1-b-e\right)\right]\). For \({x}^{*}>0\), this implies that \(\frac{\mathrm{d}{x}^{*}}{\mathrm{d}e}=\frac{-1}{2}<0\).

Appendix B: Results with respect to hypotheses 3 and 4

2.1 B1: Comparing average giving across first and second dictators

Here, we explore the third question, and compare average giving across A and C subjects.Footnote 15 Giving should be higher by A subjects to be in accordance with Hypothesis 3. Table 3 presents mean amount given by A and C subjects in various conditions. Average giving in the first game is the same across conditions Human, Human3U, Human3R, and CompU as observations generated in Human were implemented in Human3U, Human3R, and CompU. The overall mean for game 1 giving is 37.65 (using 90 unique observations), while it is 30.80 for game 2 giving (with 225 unique observations). These are different at the 1% level using either a t test or an MW test (two-sided p values: t test = 0.0024, MW = 0.0012).

Table 3 Mean amounts given by A and C subjects

We also compare A and C dictator giving independently by condition and find that the overall effect of A giving being greater than C giving is driven by Human3R (t test p value = 0.0471) with the difference statistically insignificant at the 5% level for other conditions. As further robustness checks, we run two partially pooled OLS regressions, one with data from only HumanN and Human (which have human agents with intent as dictators in both games), and the other using data only from Human, Human3U, Human3R, and CompU (which have identical distributions of giving for game 1, and in which game 2 dictators know recipient endowment). Finally, we run a regression with data pooled over all five conditions. The dependent variable in these regressions is dictator giving. Regressors consist of condition dummies and their interactions with the game 2 dummy. In the pooled regression of Human and HumanN, we find no significant regressors. In the latter two regressions, we find that only the interaction of the period 2 dummy with condition Human3R to be significant (p value = 0.043). This is unsurprising as we found the difference between game 1 and game 2 giving to be significant at the 5% level only for condition Human3R. These regressions are not reported for the sake of brevity.Footnote 16 We thus conclude that second dictators give less than first dictators, with this effect disappearing once we put in condition specific controls and interactions. Overall, we find qualified support for Hypothesis 3.

2.2 B2: The effect of providing information on amount received earlier on average giving

HumanN and Human are identical except that C subjects in Human are told the exact amount their matched B subjects received from the earlier game. For the fourth question, comparing giving by C subjects across these two conditions thus yields the impact of information regarding the amount received.

Tests comparing giving by C subjects across HumanN and Human yield insignificant difference (two-sided p values: t test = 0.523, MW = 0.638). In addition to these two-group tests, we also compare C giving from HumanN and Human using Wald test contrasts that report an F statistic. We find that \({\overline{c}}_{Human}\) and \({\overline{c}}_{HUmanN}\) are not statistically different (Wald F test p value = 0.4284).

Specific information on amount received earlier thus does not leave an impact on giving on average. This suggests, in accordance with Hypothesis 4, that the actual distribution of giving by A subjects in Human is comparable to the distribution of giving by A subjects as expected by C subjects in HumanN, i.e., C dictators, on average, correctly anticipate the decisions made by the A dictators. Together with the finding from Appendix B1 above, this indicates that the effect of sequential dictatorship is independent of whether or not a later dictator knows the exact prior receipts of her matched recipient.

Appendix C: Instructions

The subjects were given roles Red, Green, and Blue, corresponding, respectively, to A, B, and C.

1. General instructions—given at the beginning of any session to all subjects.

Hello and welcome. Today, you will participate in a study on decision-making. Depending on chance, some of you will have to make a decision in today’s session based on which you will get a payment in rupees to take home after the session. You will receive Rs 50 for showing up and completing the session. Depending on your decision or those of others, you may receive another payment which will be added to this show-up fee of Rs. 50.

Your decisions are strictly confidential and your identity will never be disclosed to anyone. You will be identified by a unique ID which cannot be traced to you, so there is no chance that others will know how you decided. In making decisions, please think carefully and perform the action of your choice, not what you think others may want to see.

Today, you will be participating in either Red, Green or Blue roles. A box containing some colored slips of paper will be brought to you shortly. Please choose a slip from the box. The color of the paper you draw will determine your role (red, green, or blue). Please follow instructions thereafter.

Thank you for your interest in this project, and please wait for further instructions.

2. Instructions to Green subjects (B) given in all conditions (Red subjects (A) given in conditions Human3U, Human3R and CompU).

You have been paired with two other participants, one red (green) and one blue. Their identities will not be revealed to you now or later. Furthermore, these other participants will also never learn your identity. You will merely be conveyed their decisions at the end of the session.

You do not have to make a decision in today’s session. Please wait quietly, do not communicate with anyone and await further instructions.

3. Instructions to Red subjects (A) given in conditions HumanN and Human.

You have been paired with a green participant. His/her identity, however, will not be revealed to you now or later. Furthermore, the other person will also never learn your identity. The individual will merely be conveyed your decision at the end of the session.

Now the game. Suppose you have been allocated Rs. 100. Your task is to divide Rs. 100 between yourself and this other person (integer division only please). In the designated space below, please put down the amount out of this you wish to share with this other individual. Whatever you do not share is yours to take home. Thus, if you give nothing, you get 100, and if you give everything, you get 0. The entire range in between and including 0 and 100 is open to you.

I give to the other person _________________

Before submitting this sheet, please check that the number above is (a) an integer, (b) not negative, and (c) not greater than 100.

4. Instructions to Blue subjects (C).

Instructions given to Blue subjects were the same as those given to Red subjects in condition HumanN and Human, except that a third paragraph was added after the second (beginning with ‘Now the game’). This paragraph differed across the five conditions. These paragraphs are reproduced below.

I. Condition HumanN—Additionally, in another identical earlier interaction, this same person was paired with a red participant, i.e., the red participant had an opportunity to give out of 100 to this green participant, who is now paired with you. The red participant was not aware at the time of this earlier interaction that the green participant would later be paired again.

II. Condition Human—Additionally, in another identical earlier interaction, this same person was paired with a red participant and received ______ out of 100, i.e., the red participant had an opportunity to give out of 100 to this green participant, who is now paired with you, and gave the specified amount. The red participant was not aware at the time of this earlier interaction that the green participant would later be paired again.

III. Condition Human3U—Additionally, just before this session, this same person was paired with a red participant. A neutral third party, who is a doctoral student and present among us, then divided 100 among the two, selecting from among a set of possible divisions. The green participant received ____. This neutral third party was not aware at the time of this earlier interaction that the green participant would later be paired again, and did not receive any compensation for performing the division.

IV. Condition Human3R—Additionally, just before this session, this same person was paired with a red participant. A neutral third party, who is a doctoral student and present among us, then divided 100 among the two, using a random process to select from among a set of possible divisions. The green participant received ____. This neutral third party was not aware at the time of this earlier interaction that the green participant would later be paired again, and did not receive any compensation for performing the division.

V. Condition CompU—Additionally, just before this session, this same person was paired with a red participant. A computer then divided 100 among the two, selecting from among a set of possible divisions. The green participant received ____.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Banerjee, P., Chakravarty, S. Dictator choice and causal attribution of recipient endowment. Ind. Econ. Rev. 56, 351–373 (2021). https://doi.org/10.1007/s41775-021-00118-5

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s41775-021-00118-5

Keywords

JEL Classification

Navigation