Skip to main content
Log in

Comparing Comparatives: The Argumentative Force of Comparative Quantifiers

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Corpus Pragmatics Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This study investigates the difference between more than n and at least n + 1. It is observed that these two quantifiers can generate different implicatures in intensional contexts due to their exhaustivity properties. Building on theoretical notions of argumentation in discourse, it is proposed that more than n, but not at least n + 1, is associated with positive argumenatative orientation (an attempt to convince the addressee of something). In a large-scale corpus investigation, more than n is shown to be associated with much larger numerical values than at least n (as well as other comparative quantifiers). Based on a qualitative investigation of the data, I propose that more than n is used more commonly to convey subjective positions that are being made more convincing by larger values of n, while at least n + 1 is used more commonly to convey objectively informative content. The quantifiers’ behavior in intensional contexts is explained as a combined effect of their respective argumentative orientation and the exhaustivity implicatures they generate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. From the technical perspective, when a sample standard deviation renders most observations negligibly small, no statistical generalizations are usually possible. p values grow monotonically alongside variance, and therefore gargantuan variance leads to high \( p \) values even when sample means are truly different. Arguably, the abnormally high variance does not reflect the true variance of numerical expressions but rather the diversity of discourse domains. From the conceptual perspective, the argumentative impact of numerical values does not grow to scale with their numerical magnitude. Mentioning 5 million billion is not a million billion times more impressing than mentioning 5—it simply means you are probably talking about some scientific domain, like biology or physics. This problem is ameliorated by reducing numerical values to log space, since it bins all numbers into their respective orders of magnitude without losing the linear ordering. This makes comparison possible between numbers without creating unrealistic variance.

  2. A shortcoming of the above model is that it treats all numerical expressions as being on the same scale. But arguably, comparison is usually made between numbers no more than one order of magnitude (oom) above or below each other. For example, in (35), in my judgment, the set of salient alternatives to the expression 35,000 is probably somewhere in the broad range of 1000–1,000,000, but probably not below or above this range. Therefore, an interesting question is whether comparatives differ in the magnitude of their arguments even after oom is taken into account. Presumably, the numbers within each 3-oom window correspond to the approximate range of alternatives perceived by speakers in discourse. So after accounting for the oom of a numerical expression, do comparative quantifiers still contain any information about its magnitude?

    To answer this question, the model was rebuilt, but now the oom of each numerical value was subtracted from it. So for example, 3.16 was replaced with .16, and .16 remained .16. This new target variable represents the variation within each oom—the higher this variable is, the larger the number is within its respective oom. This setup thus controls for the variation in oom described above. The Aikaike Information Criterion (AIC) was then applied to the resulting model. The AIC uses the statistical equivalent of Occam’s Razor to test whether some variable in a model accounts for more variation than it inherently introduces by strengthening the model. The null hypothesis is that there is no interaction between comparatives and numerical values within an oom window. That is, all variation is explained by the oom of the number and none is due to the comparative following it (or lack thereof). The alternative hypothesis is that a comparative does correlate with higher/lower numerical values within the same oom. If the alternative hypothesis is true, then the coefficient for that comparative is very unlikely to be removed by the AIC.

    In the new model, all coefficients remained significant and none was removed by the AIC, with the exception of the coefficient for AM.

  3. Defined as: \( p \cdot \surd p\left( {1 - p} \right) \), where \( p \) is the proportion of numbers satisfying a rounding expression. The observed proportion \( p \) is multiplied by its binomial standard deviation \( \surd p\left( {1 - p} \right) \) to account for sampling variance, as when computing \( t \) -values.

  4. For the same reason, for \( (m/2) \cdot 10^{n} \), 9 was replaced by 18, and for \( 10^{n} \), 9 was replaced by 1.

  5. However, recall that the coefficient for AM did not survive the AIC in the model described in footnote 2, and the difference of the means for AM and LT was not significant. This is likely due to the relatively small number of observations for AM, and so these results warrant further research. The fact that AM is so infrequent in COCA relative to its alternative LT suggests that AM is dispreferred due to markedness considerations. Therefore, some of the semantic effects observed involving AM might be a result of its markedness rather than AO or lack thereof.

References

  • Anscombre, J. C., & Ducrot, O. (1976). L’argumentation dans la langue. Langages, 42, 5–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombre, J. C., & Ducrot, O. (1977). Deux mais en français? Lingua, 43, 23–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombre, J. C., & Ducrot, O. (1983). L’argumentation dans la langue. Brussels: Pierre Mardaga.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombre, J. C., & Ducrot, O. (1986). Argumentativité et informativité. In M. Meyer (Ed.), De la métaphysique á la rhétorique. Brussels: Mardaga.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombre, J. C., & Oswald, D. (1989). Argumentativity and informativity. In M. Meyer (Ed.), From metaphysics to argumentation (pp. 71–87). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers. English translation of Anscombre and Durcrot (1986).

  • Ariel, M. (2004). Most. Language, 80(4), 658–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ariel, M. (2014). What discourse can(not) teach us. International Review of Pragmatics, 6(2), 181–210.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barwise, J., & Cooper, R. (1981). Generalized quantifiers and natural language. Linguistics and Philosophy, 4, 159–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cummins, C., & Katsos, N. (2010). Comparative and superlative quantifiers: Pragmatic effects of comparison type. Journal of Semantics, 27, 271–305.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davies, M. (2008). Corpus of contemporary American English. Brigham Young University.

  • Ducrot, O. (1993). Pour une description non-véritative du langage. Actes du congrès de linguistique de Séoul, 86–98.

  • Fox, D. (2007). Free choice and the theory of scalar implicatures. In P. Stateva & U. Sauerland (Eds.), Presupposition and implicature in compositional semantics (pp. 71–120). London: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Geurts, B., & Nouwen, R. (2007). ‘At least’ et al.: The semantics of scalar modifiers. Language, 83(3), 553–559.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goodman, N. D., & Daniel, L. (2014). Probabilistic semantics and pragmatics: Uncertainty in language and thought. In Handbook of contemporary semantic theory. Wiley-Blackwell.

  • Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. Berkeley: University of California.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hackl, M. (2001). Comparative quantifiers. Ph.D. dissertation, MIT.

  • Hackl, M. (2009). On the grammar and processing of proportional quantifiers: Most versus more than half. Natural Language Semantics, 17, 63–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heim, I. (1983). On the projection problem for presuppositions. In M. Barlow, D. P. Flickinger, & M. T. Wescoat (Eds.), Proceedings of the 2nd West Coast conference on formal linguistics (pp. 114–125). Stanford, MA: Stanford Linguistics Association.

  • Iten, C. (1999). The relevance of argumentation theory. In UCL working papers in linguistics (pp. 41–81).

  • Kamp, H. (1981). A theory of truth and semantic representation. In J. A. G. Groenendijk, T. M. V. Janssen, & M. B. J. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (pp. 277–322). Mathematical Centre Tracts 135, Amsterdam.

  • Kratzer, A., & Heim, I. (1998). Semantics in generative grammar. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krifka, M. (1999). At least some determiners aren’t determiners. In K. Turner (Ed.), The semantics/pragmatics interface from different points of view (=Current Research in the Semantics/Pragmatics Interface, Vol. 1) (pp. 257–291). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

  • Link, G. (1987). Generalized quantifiers and plurals. In P. Gärdenfors (Ed.), Generalized quantifiers. Linguistic and logical approaches (pp. 151–180). Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nyan, T. (1998). Metalinguistic operators with reference to French. Bern: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shetreet, E., Chierchia, G., & Gaab, N. (2014). When some is not every: Dissociating scalar implicature generation and mismatch. Human Brain Mapping, 35(4), 1503–1514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spector, B. (2003). Scalar implicatures: Exhaustivity and Gricean reasoning. European summer school in logic, language and information (ESSLLI)—student session 8 (pp. 277–288).

  • Spector, B. (2006). Aspects de la pragmatique des opérateurs logiques. Université Paris.

  • Verkuyl, H. J. (1981). Numerals and quantifiers in X-bar-syntax and their semantic interpretation. In J. A. G. Groenendijk, T. M. V. Janssen, & M. J. B. Stokhof (Eds.), Formal methods in the study of language (Vol. 136, pp. 567–599). Amsterdam: Mathematical Centre Tracts.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Omer Korat.

Additional information

The code and data for this paper are available in the following repository: https://github.com/Omerkorat/comparatives.

Electronic supplementary material

Below is the link to the electronic supplementary material.

Supplementary material 1 (DOCX 31 kb)

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Korat, O. Comparing Comparatives: The Argumentative Force of Comparative Quantifiers. Corpus Pragmatics 2, 399–423 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s41701-018-0042-2

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s41701-018-0042-2

Keywords

Navigation