Skip to main content
Log in

Does Determinism imply Inevitability? A Dennettian Counter analysis

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This research study postulates an argument aimed at disputing the conception that determinism intrinsically entails the inevitability or unchangability of events. It claims that within our world, there exist events that are, in fact, avoidable. To defend this claim, the paper draws upon the evolutionary foundation established by cognitive philosopher Daniel C. Dennett. According to Dennett, the phenomenon of natural selection has bestowed human beings with the capability to avoid specific events by reducing the pervasiveness of inevitable events over time. Nevertheless, a crucial query arises while recognizing the existence of avoidance-capable entities within a Toy deterministic world, such as John Conway’s “Game of Life.” The existence of such entities puts forward the presence of a practical expression of free will, despite the allegedly deterministic nature of the world. Dennett, a staunch proponent of naturalism, endeavors to demonstrate that determinism is not inherently problematic and does not pose a significant threat to our free existence. Anchored in compatibilism, Dennett argues that determinism and freedom can coexist, with the emergence of evolution enabling human beings to possess the capacity for avoidance within a so-called deterministic world. Thus, the prime intention of this paper is to exhibit an extensive analysis exemplifying that determinism does not diminish our notion of free will. To achieve this objective, the paper seeks to debunk prevailing misconceptions about determinism by employing a toy model wherein simplistic entities can evolve and acquire the ability to avoid harm, which can also be reflected in human life. Moreover, the paper endeavors to establish that the conventional association between determinism and inevitability is flawed, as the notion of inevitability should be attributed to the design level rather than the physical level of any system.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Free will and determinism are thought to be mutually compatible, and it is possible to have both beliefs without being illogically contradictory, according to compatibilism. For compatibilists, freedom can exist or not in certain circumstances for reasons unrelated to metaphysics.

  2. Dennett defined “toy model” to show that in the huge expanse of possible arrangements of matter, there exist some substances that preserve better than others, as they have been designed to escape harm, in spite of determinism being true.

  3. Dennett emphasizes that chess-playing computers and the Game of Life are analogous to agents in this context. Additionally, he shifts the perspective and claims that the entities that resemble the Game of Life and chess-playing computers are agents. In other words, rather than the other way around, he sees agents as being similar to these simulations.

  4. Natural selection is Charles Darwin’s theory of how particular favorable features in a population become more habitual over time because of their survival and reproductive benefits. It is a rudimentary conception in evolutionary biology, driving species adaptation and diversity.

  5. Dennett claims that the “epistemic” level denotes the perspective from which we comprehend and account for the behavior of the agent, stressing their intents, beliefs, desires, and mental states. It entails taking a deliberate position to explain and forecast performance in light of the agent’s internal mental state and motivation. This perspective aids in our understanding of complex behaviors and decision-making processes, especially when addressing higher-order phenomena like human consciousness and free will.

  6. John Horton Conway created the mathematical simulation and model known as John Conway’s Game of Life in 1970. The system’s infinite two-dimensional grid contains square cells that can either be alive or dead. Dennett focuses on how complex actions can develop from simple regulation by using “The Game of Life” as a concrete example. It also demonstrates how interactions between fundamental physical components can lead to higher-level phenomena like human consciousness and decision-making.

  7. In this context, the notion of “evitability” indicates the ability to prevent undesirable events in the determined world. It is referring to the belief that the bounded rationality of the organism (limited rational thinking) has led to the notion that particular outcomes can be avoided or prevented.

  8. Dennett understood “epistemic openness” to mean that even in a deterministic universe, people can engage in rational inquiry, critically assess claims and evidence, and adjust their beliefs in light of new information.

  9. The term “agential state,” also known as an intentional state, refers to a mental state or psychological phenomenon of an agent, such as a human being, that contains desires, beliefs, intentions, or other mental states that affect their behavior and decision-making processes. It is a mental state that controls how the actor behaves and is crucial to understanding and explaining human behavior within the context of intentional psychology.

References

  • Austin, J. (1961). Ifs and cans. In J. O. Urmson & G. Warnock (Eds.), Philosophical papers (p. 166). Claredon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. (2001). Social cognitive theory: An agentic perspective. Annual Review of Psychology, 52, 1–26. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev.psych.52.1.1

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bandura, A. (2006). Toward a psychology of human agency. Perspective on Psychological Science, 1(2), 164–180. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1745-6916.2006.00011.x

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, R. C. (2002). Chaos, indeterminism and free will. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (pp. 111–124). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bishop, R. C., & Kronz, F. M. (1999). Is chaos indeterministic. In M. L. Dalla Chiara, G. Roberto, & F. Laudisa (Eds.), Language, quantum, music (pp. 129–141). Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1978). Brainstorms: Philosophical essay on mind and psychology. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1991). Consciousness explained. Little, Brown and Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1995). Darwin’s dangerous idea: Evolution and the meanings of life. Simon & Schuster Publisher.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1984). Elbow room: The varieties of free will worth wanting. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2003). Freedom evolves. Viking Penguin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (2013). Intuition pumps and other tools for thinking. WW Norton Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1996). Kinds of minds: toward an understanding of consciousness. Weidenfeld & Nicolson Publisher.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, D. C. (1987). The intentional stance. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hard determinism. (2023, September 7). In Wikipedia. https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Hard_determinism

  • Hoefer, C. (2023). Causal determinism. In E. N. Zalta & U. Nodelman (Eds.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2023 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2023/entries/determinism-causal/>

  • Kane, R. (2002). The contours of contemporary free will debates. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (pp. 7–27). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2012). Groundwork of the metaphysics of morals (M. Gregor, Trans.) Cambridge University Press.

  • Laplace, P.-S. (1814). A philosophical essay on probabilities. Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1996). The sciences of the artificial. The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talbert, M. (2022). Moral responsibility. In E. N. Zalta & U. Nodelman (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Fall 2022 ed.). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2022/entries/moral-responsibility/>

  • Taylor, Christopher., & Daniel, Dennett. (2001). Who’s afraid of determinism? Rethinking causes and possibilities. In R. Kane (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of free will (pp. 257–277). Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1983). An essay on free will. Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werndl, C. (2017). Determinism. In M. Griffith, T. Neil, & K. Timpe (Eds.), The Routledge companion to free will (pp. 669–679). Routledge Taylor & Francis Group.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dipu Basumatary.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

I wish to assert that there is no conflict of interest with respect to my paper, “Does Determinism imply inevitability? A Dennettian Counter analysis.”

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Basumatary, D. Does Determinism imply Inevitability? A Dennettian Counter analysis. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 40, 259–286 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00308-x

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-023-00308-x

Keywords

Navigation