Skip to main content
Log in

Experimental, Cross-Cultural, and Classical Indian Epistemology

  • Published:
Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

This paper connects recent findings from experimental epistemology to several major themes in classical Indian epistemology. First, current evidence supports a specific account of the ordinary knowledge concept in contemporary anglophone American culture. According to this account, known as abilism, knowledge is a true representation produced by cognitive ability. I present evidence that abilism closely approximates Nyāya epistemology’s theory of knowledge, especially that found in the Nyāya-sūtra. Second, Americans are more willing to attribute knowledge of positive facts than of negative facts, especially when such facts are inferred and even when the positive and negative “facts” are logically equivalent. Similar suspicions about knowledge of negative facts (absences) seemingly occur in classical Indian epistemology, suggesting that the asymmetry might not be an American quirk but instead reflect a cross-culturally robust tendency in knowledge attributions. Each of these themes—abilism and the positive/negative asymmetry—presents an exciting opportunity for further research in experimental cross-cultural epistemology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Alexander, J. (2012). Experimental philosophy. Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anthony, D. W. (2007). The horse, the wheel, and language: How bronze-age riders from the Eurasian steppes shaped the modern world. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. (1941). Nichomachean ethics (R. McKeon, Ed., W. D. Ross, Trans.).

  • Austin, J. L. (1956). A plea for excuses. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 1–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J. R. (2012). Experimental epistemology. In A. Cullison (Ed.), Continuum companion to epistemology (pp. 248–269). Vancouver: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beebe, J. R., & Monaghan, J. (in press). Epistemic closure in folk epistemology. In J. Knobe, T. Lombrozo, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology (vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Bhatt, G. P. (1989). The basic ways of knowing: An in-depth study of Kumārila’s contribution to Indian epistemology (2nd ed.). Delhi: Motilal Banarsidass.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharya, R. (2002). Cārvāka fragments: A new collection. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 30, 597–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bhattacharya, R. (2011). Studies on the Cārvāka/Lokāyata. London: Anthem Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., Rose, D., & Turri, J. (2015). Belief through thick and thin. Nous, 49(4), 748–775. doi:10.1111/nous.12048.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2016). In the thick of moral motivation. Review of Philosophy and Psychology. doi:10.1007/s13164-016-0306-3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (in press). Modest scientism in philosophy. In J. R. Ridder, R. Peels, & R. van Woudenberg (Eds.), Scientism: Prospects and problems. Oxford University Press.

  • Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Does the chimpanzee have a theory of mind? 30 years later. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 12(5), 187–192.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clément, F., Koenig, M., & Harris, P. (2004). The ontogenesis of trust. Mind and Language, 19(4), 360–379.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corriveau, K., & Harris, P. L. (2009). Preschoolers continue to trust a more accurate informant 1 week after exposure to accuracy information. Developmental Science, 12(1), 188–193. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2008.00763.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corriveau, K. H., Meints, K., & Harris, P. L. (2009). Early tracking of informant accuracy and inaccuracy. British Journal of Developmental Psychology, 27(2), 331–342. doi:10.1348/026151008X310229.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature: An essay in conceptual synthesis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cushman, F., & Greene, J. D. (2012). Finding faults: How moral dilemmas illuminate cognitive structure. Social Neuroscience, 7(3), 269–279. doi:10.1080/17470919.2011.614000.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasti, M. R. (2012). Parasitism and disjunctivism in Nyāya epistemology. Philosophy East and West, 62(1), 1–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dasti, M. R. (2017). Nyaya. Retrieved January 2017, from http://www.iep.utm.edu/nyaya/#SH1e.

  • Flombaum, J. I., & Santos, L. R. (2005). Rhesus monkeys attribute perceptions to others. Current Biology, 15(5), 447–452. doi:10.1016/j.cub.2004.12.076.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ganeri, J. (1990). Dharmakīrti on inference and properties. Journal of Indian Philosophy, 18(3), 237–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gautama. (200/1913). Nyāya Sūtras (B. D. Basu, Ed., various Sanskrit scholars, Trans.). Allahabad: Sudhindranatha Vasu.

  • Gokhale, P. (1978). The philosophical position of Jayarasibhatta. Indian Philosophical Qurterly, 5(3), 489–498.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1993). Epistemic folkways and scientific epistemology. Philosophical Issues, 3, 271–285.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge: A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hall, K., Oram, M. W., Campbell, M. W., Eppley, T. M., Byrne, R. W., & de Waal, F. B. M. (2016). Chimpanzee uses manipulative gaze cues to conceal and reveal information to foraging competitor. American Journal of Primatology, 79(3), e22622. doi:10.1002/ajp.22622.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., Agnetta, B., & Tomasello, M. (2000). Chimpanzees know what conspecifics do and do not see. Animal Behaviour, 59(4), 771–785. doi:10.1006/anbe.1999.1377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hare, B., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2001). Do chimpanzees know what conspecifics know? Animal Behaviour, 61(1), 139–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1993). An enquiry concerning human understanding. In E. Steinberg (Ed.), 2nd edn. Indianapolis: Hackett.

  • James, W. (1889). The psychology of belief. Mind, 14(55), 321–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaswal, V. K., & Neely, L. A. (2006). Adults don’t always know best: Preschoolers use past reliability over age when learning new words. Psychological Science, 17(9), 757–758. doi:10.1111/j.1467-9280.2006.01778.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaminski, J., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2008). Chimpanzees know what others know, but not what they believe. Cognition, 109, 224–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, M., & Yuan, Y. (ms). Cross-cultural universality of knowledge attributions. New Haven: Yale University.

  • Kim, S., Paulus, M., & Kalish, C. (2016). Young children’s reliance on information from inaccurate informants. Cognitive Science. doi:10.1111/cogs.12471.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J., Buckwalter, W., Nichols, S., Robbins, P., Sarkissian, H., & Sommers, T. (2012). Experimental philosophy. Annual Review of Psychology, 63(1), 81–99. doi:10.1146/annurev-psych-120710-100350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenig, M. A., Clément, F., & Harris, P. L. (2004). Trust in testimony: Children’s use of true and false statements. Psychological Science, 15(10), 694–698.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koenig, M. A., & Harris, P. L. (2005). Preschoolers mistrust ignorant and inaccurate speakers. Child Development, 76(6), 1261–1277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lillard, A. (1998). Ethnopsychologies: Cultural variations in theories of mind. Psychological Bulletin, 123(1), 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., & Struchiner, N., et al. (in press). Gettier across cultures. Noûs.

  • Mallory, J. P., & Adams, D. Q. (2006). The Oxford introduction to Proto-Indo-European and the Proto-Indo-European world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marticorena, D. C. W., Ruiz, A. M., Mukerji, C., Goddu, A., & Santos, L. R. (2011). Monkeys represent others’ knowledge but not their beliefs. Developmental Science, 14(6), 1406–1416. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2011.01085.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, A., & Santos, L. R. (2016). What cognitive representations support primate theory of mind? Trends in Cognitive Sciences. doi:10.1016/j.tics.2016.03.005.

    Google Scholar 

  • Melis, A. P., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2006). Chimpanzees conceal visual and auditory information from others. Journal of Comparative Psychology, 120(2), 154. doi:10.1037/0735-7036.120.2.154.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Monier-Williams, M. (1964). A Sanskrit-English dictionary. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murray, D., Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2013). God knows (but does God believe?). Philosophical Studies, 166(1), 83–107. doi:10.1007/s11098-012-0022-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Myers-Schulz, B., & Schwitzgebel, E. (2013). Knowing that P without believing that P. Nous, 47(2), 371–384.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S., Stich, S., & Weinberg, J. M. (2003). Meta-skepticism: meditations on ethno-epistemology. In Collected papers, volume 2: Knowledge, rationality, and morality, 1978–2010. Oxford University Press. http://doi.org/10.1093/acprof:oso/9780199733477.001.0001.

  • O’Neill, D. K., Astington, J. W., & Flavell, J. H. (1992). Young children’s understanding of the role that sensory experiences play in knowledge acquisition. Child Development, 63(2), 474–490. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8624.1992.tb01641.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patil, P. G. (2009). Against a Hindu god: Buddhist philosophy of religion in India. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, S. (2015). Epistemology in classical indian philosophy. Retrieved January 2017, from https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-india/.

  • Phillips, J., Knobe, J., & Cushman, F. (2015). Knowledge before belief: response-times indicate evaluations of knowledge prior to belief. Presented at the 41st annual meeting of the Society for Philosophy and Psychology, Durham, NC.

  • Pillow, B. H. (1989). Early understanding of perception as a source of knowledge. Journal of Experimental Child Psychology, 47(1), 116–129. doi:10.1016/0022-0965(89)90066-0.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Puligandla, R. (1996). Fundamentals of Indian philosophy. New Delhi: D.K. Printworld.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rakoczy, H. (2009). Executive function and the development of belief-desire psychology. Developmental Science, 13(4), 648–661. doi:10.1111/j.1467-7687.2009.00922.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reid, T. (1997). An inquiry into the human mind on the principles of common sense. In D. R. Brookes (Ed.). University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University Press.

  • Rose, D., Machery, E., Stich, S., et al. (in press). Nothing at stake in knowledge. Noûs.

  • Santos, L. R., Nissen, A. G., & Ferrugia, J. A. (2006). Rhesus monkeys, Macaca mulatta, know what others can and cannot hear. Animal Behaviour, 71(5), 1175–1181. doi:10.1016/j.anbehav.2005.10.007.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmelz, M., Call, J., & Tomasello, M. (2011). Chimpanzees know that others make inferences. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 108(7), 3077–3079. doi:10.1073/pnas.1000469108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seed, A., & Tomasello, M. (2010). Primate cognition. Topics in Cognitive Science, 2(3), 407–419. doi:10.1111/j.1756-8765.2010.01099.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, W. (1963). Science, perception and reality. Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shahaeian, A., Peterson, C. C., Slaughter, V., & Wellman, H. M. (2011). Culture and the sequence of steps in theory of mind development. Developmental Psychology, 47(5), 1239–1247. doi:10.1037/a0023899.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sharma, D. (1966). Epistemological negative dialectics of indian logic — “abhāva” versus “anupalabdh”. Indo-Iranian Journal, 9(3), 291–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Southgate, V., & Vernetti, A. (2014). Belief-based action prediction in preverbal infants. Cognition, 130(1), 1–10. doi:10.1016/j.cognition.2013.08.008.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Buckwalter, W. (Eds.). (2016). A companion to experimental philosophy. Wiley: Malden.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2015). The theory and practice of experimental philosophy. Peterborough: Broadview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2011). Believing for a reason. Erkenntnis, 74(3), 383–397. doi:10.1007/s10670-011-9271-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2012). Review of: Achieving knowledge—A virtue-theoretic account of epistemic normativity, by John Greco. Mind, 121(481), 183–187. doi:10.1093/mind/fzs032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2013). A conspicuous art: Putting Gettier to the test. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13(10), 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2015a). An open and shut case: Epistemic closure in the manifest image. Philosophers’ Imprint, 15(2), 1–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2015b). From virtue epistemology to abilism: Theoretical and empirical developments. In C. B. Miller, M. R. Furr, A. Knobel, & W. Fleeson (Eds.), Character: New directions from philosophy, psychology, and theology (pp. 315–330). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2015c). Skeptical appeal: The source-content bias. Cognitive Science, 39(2), 307–324. doi:10.1111/cogs.12153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2015d). Unreliable knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 90(3), 529–545. doi:10.1111/phpr.12064.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016a). A new paradigm for epistemology: From reliabilism to abilism. Ergo, 3(8), 189–231.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016b). Epistemic situationism and cognitive ability. In M. Alfano & A. Fairweather (Eds.), Epistemic situationism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016c). How to do better: Toward normalizing experimentation in epistemology. In J. Nado (Ed.), Advances in experimental philosophy and philosophical methodology (pp. 35–51). London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016d). Knowledge attributions and behavioral predictions. Cognitive Science. doi:10.1111/cogs.12469.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (2016e). Knowledge judgments in “Gettier” cases. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 337–348). London: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J. (in press a). Virtue epistemology and abilism on knowledge. In H. Battaly (Ed.), Routledge handbook of virtue epistemology. New York: Routledge.

  • Turri, J. (in press b). Primate social cognition and the core human knowledge concept. In M. Mizumoto, E. McCready, S. Stich (Eds.) Epistemology for the rest of the world: Linguistic and cultural diversity and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Turri, J. (under review). A peculiar and perpetual tendency: An asymmetry in knowledge attribution for affirmations and negations. Waterloo: University of Waterloo.

  • Turri, J., & Buckwalter, W. (2017). Descartes’s schism, Locke’s reunion: Completing the pragmatic turn in epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly, 54(1), 25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turri, J., Buckwalter, W., & Rose, D. (2016). Actionability judgments cause knowledge judgments. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 5(3), 212–222. doi:10.1002/tht3.213.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, J. J., Miletich, D. D., Ramsey, R., & Samson, D. (2014). Adults see vision to be more informative than it is. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 67(12), 2279–2292. doi:10.1080/17470218.2014.915331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watkins, C. (2000). The American Heritage dictionary of Indo-European roots. Boston: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wellman, H. M., Fang, F., Liu, D., Zhu, L., & Liu, G. (2006). Scaling of theory-of-mind understandings in Chinese children. Psychological Science, 17(12), 1075–1081.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

For helpful feedback and discussion, I thank Wesley Buckwalter, Ashley Keefner, Vanessa Lam, YeounJun Park, Stephen Stich, Angelo Turri, and Sarah Turri. This research was supported by the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada, the Ontario Ministry of Economic Development and Innovation, and the Canada Chairs Research program.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John Turri.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Turri, J. Experimental, Cross-Cultural, and Classical Indian Epistemology. J. Indian Counc. Philos. Res. 34, 501–516 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0117-7

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40961-017-0117-7

Keywords

Navigation