Skip to main content
Log in

On the Place of Behavior in the Analysis of Psychological Categories

  • Theoretical Article
  • Published:
The Psychological Record Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The traditional, and still quite accepted, view of psychological phenomena (e.g., emotions, moods, “propositional attitudes”) holds that they are inner entities of some non-behavioral sort (reducible or not to brain phenomena) that bring about behaviors. Behavioral and related externalist perspectives, on the other hand, oppose (in different ways) this view. There is controversy, however, over how to understand psychological phenomena giving prominence to behaviors. Most versions of the so-called extended mind view, for instance, are very different from behavioral perspectives. This paper aims at contributing to this discussion by outlining a behavioral approach that draws upon Ryle and Skinner, among others. According to this approach, psychological phenomena of different categories are by and large made up of overt and/or covert behaviors and their relations to the environment. This paper starts off by briefly surveying the range of psychological categories and identifying a desideratum for an account thereof, according to which the account should, in general, be consistent with the basic nuances of these categories. It is suggested that the outlined approach fares well in this respect and is virtuously (as opposed to viciously) parsimonious. Also, Rachlin's teleological behaviorism and Clark and Chalmers' extended mind view are very briefly discussed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. The terminology of 'cognitive processes' used here is simply a convenient label. As will become clear later on, I am not relying upon any assumptions distinctive of the cognitivist tradition.

  2. I do not understand covert behavior as behavior observable uniquely from (or accessible to) the organism's own vantage point. Rather, I understand it as behavior largely unobservable by simple consideration of what is going on outside the organism's skin, exoskeleton or the like.

  3. I say 'at least partially' not to rule out the participation of non-selective (or neutral) processes in their etiology (e.g., genetic drift in phylogeny and its analogous in the ontogeny of behavior). On this, see Cleaveland (2002).

  4. The view here outlined is nevertheless different from those of Ryle and Rachlin. For example, I consider that covert behaviors make up some instances of psychological phenomena, whereas Rachlin does not. My view is perhaps largely in continuity with Ryle's, but I work with a more detailed characterization of behaviors.

  5. Some authors believe that, like propositional attitudes, these affections have an episodic character in some cases. My previous remark upon supposed episodic propositional attitudes applies analogously here.

  6. The well-known holistic objection to behavioral accounts is no threat to the account here outlined. For one reason, this objection is question-begging, since it assumes that psychological phenomena are non-behavioral inner things that cause behavior. Also, it assumes that such accounts intend to reduce ascriptions of psychological phenomena to ascriptions of behavior without introducing mention to psychological phenomena (Lazzeri & Oliveira-Castro 2010).

References

  • Bedford, E. (1957). Emotions. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 57, 281–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, M. R., & Hacker, P. M. (2003). Philosophical foundations of neuroscience. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braddon-Mitchell, D., & Jackson, F. (2007). Philosophy of mind and cognition (2nd ed.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. (1979). Individualism and the mental. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 4, 73–121. doi:10.1111/j.1475-4975.1979.tb00374.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Catania, A. C. (2012). Learning (5th ed.). Cornwall-on-Hudson, NY: Sloan.

  • Catania, A. C. (2013). A natural science of behavior. Review of General Psychology, 17, 133–139. doi:10.1037/a0033026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. J. (1995). Facing up to the problem of consciousness. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 2, 200–219.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charles, E. P., Bybee, M. D., & Thompson, N. S. (2011). A behaviorist account of emotions and feelings: Making sense of James D. Laird's Feelings: The perception of self. Behavior and Philosophy, 39, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, A., & Chalmers, D. J. (1998). The extended mind. Analysis, 58, 7–19. doi:10.1093/analys/58.1.7.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cleaveland, J. M. (2002). Beyond trial-and-error in a selectionist psychology. Behavior and Philosophy, 30, 73–99.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1987). Knowing one’s own mind. Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, 60, 441–458.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donahoe, J., & Palmer, D. C. (1994). Learning and complex behavior. Boston: Allyn and Bacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epstein, R., Kirshnit, C. E., Lanza, R. P., & Rubin, L. C. (1984). 'Insight' in the pigeon: Antecedents and determinants of intelligent performance. Nature, 308, 61–62. doi:10.1038/308061a0.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1968). Psychological explanation. New York: Random House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor, J. A. (1980). Methodological solipsism considered as a research strategy in cognitive psychology. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3, 63–109. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00001771.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Genone, J. R. (2011). Appearance as reality: Direct perception and perceptual error. Ann Arbor: ProQuest.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gibson, J. J. (1979). The ecological approach to visual perception. Boston: Houghton-Mifflin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harzem, P., & Miles, T. R. (1978). Conceptual issues in operant psychology. New York: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Holt, E. B. (1915). The Freudian wish and its place in ethics. New York: Henry Holt.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, R., & Burgess, H. (1997). Mythmaking: How introductory psychology texts present B. F. Skinner's analysis of cognition. The Psychological Record, 47, 221–232.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kantor, J. R. (1933). A survey of the science of psychology. Bloomington: Principia Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kantor, J. R. (1978). Cognition as events and as psychic constructs. The Psychological Record, 38, 329–342.

    Google Scholar 

  • Krueger, J. (2012). Seeing mind in action. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences, 11, 149–173.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazzeri, F. (2012). Acerca da taxonomia do mental para contextos que requerem neutralidade [On the taxonomy of the psychological for contexts requiring neutrality]. Principia, 16, 365–392. doi:10.5007/1808-1711.2012v16n3p365.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazzeri, F. (2013). Um estudo sobre definições de comportamento [A study upon definitions of behavior]. Brazilian Journal of Behavior Analysis, 9, 47–65.

  • Lazzeri, F. (2015a). Dynamic interactions with the environment make up our psychological phenomena: A review of Noë's Out of our heads. The Psychological Record, 65, 215–222. doi:10.1007/s40732-014-0090-3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lazzeri, F. (2015b). On defining behavior: Some notes. Behavior and Philosophy.

  • Lazzeri, F., & Oliveira-Castro, J. M. (2010). Um exame de objeções a Ryle sobre o funcionamento dos termos psicológicos intencionais [An assessment of objections to Ryle as regards intentional psychological terms]. Abstracta, 6, 42–64.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leigland, S. (2014). Contingency-horizon: On private events and the analysis of behavior. The Behavior Analyst, 37, 13–24. doi:10.1007/s40614-014-0002-5.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. K. (1972). Psychophysical and theoretical identifications. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 50, 249–258. doi:10.1080/00048407212341301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1984). Language, thought, and other biological categories. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Millikan, R. G. (1993). White queen psychology and other essays for Alice. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2008). Conceptual foundations of radical behaviorism. Sloan: Cornwall-on-Hudson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, J. (2010). What do mental terms mean? The Psychological Record, 60, 699–714.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2004). Action in perception. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Noë, A. (2009). Out of our heads. New York: Hill and Wang.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oliveira-Castro, J., & Oliveira-Castro, K. (2003). The relativity of 'intelligence' in psychology and its adverbial function in ordinary language. Behavior and Philosophy, 31, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • O'Regan, K., & Noë, A. (2001). A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 24, 939–1031. doi:10.1017/S0140525X01000115.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, D. C. (2003). Cognition. In K. A. Lattal & P. N. Chase (Eds.), Behavior theory and philosophy (pp. 167–185). New York: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1975). The meaning of 'meaning'. Mind, language, and reality (pp. 215–271). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rachlin, H. (1994). Behavior and mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rey, G. (1997). Contemporary philosophy of mind. Malden: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ribes-Iñesta, E. (2004). Behavior is abstraction, not ostension: Conceptual and historical remarks on the nature of psychology. Behavior and Philosophy, 32, 55–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ribes-Iñesta, E. (2008). Brain and behavior: Misunderstandings and misconceptions regarding an asymmetric relationship. In J. E. Burgos & E. Ribes-Iñesta (Eds.), The brain-behavior nexus: Conceptual issues (pp. 101–122). Guadalajara, JA: University of Guadalajara.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rockwell, W. T. (2005). Neither brain nor ghost: A nondualist alternative to the mind-brain identity theory. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (1999). The body in mind. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2003). Externalism. Montreal: McGill Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rowlands, M. (2010). The new science of the mind. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1951). Feelings. Philosophical Quarterly, 1(3), 193–205. doi:10.2307/2217246.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1953). Science and human behavior. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1969). Contingencies of reinforcement. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1971). Beyond freedom and dignity. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skinner, B. F. (1976/1974). About behaviorism. New York: Vintage Books.

  • Skinner, B. F. (1981). Selection by consequences. Science, 213, 501–504. doi:10.1126/science.724464.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. W. (1984). Fundamentals of interbehavioral psychology. The Psychological Record, 34, 479–494.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, N. W. (2007). Events and constructs. The Psychological Record, 57, 169–186.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stout, R. (2010). Seeing the anger in someone's face. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, 84, 29–43. doi:10.1111/j.1467-8349.2010.00184.x.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1953). Philosophical investigations. (G. E. Anscombe, Trans.). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. (1967). Zettel (G. E. Anscombe, Trans). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Work supported by São Paulo Research Foundation (FAPESP), Brazil, grant #2012/00059-2. The author would especially like to thank Jorge M. Oliveira-Castro, Maria Helena L. Hunziker, Mark Rowlands and Osvaldo Pessoa Jr. for helpful conversations on the subject of this paper in the course of its development. Thanks are also due to two anonymous reviewers and Bryan Roche, associate editor, for helpful suggestions. The content, however, is solely the responsibility of the author.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Filipe Lazzeri.

Additional information

A version of this work was written in partial fulfillment of the author's PhD in Philosophy at the University of São Paulo, Brazil.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Lazzeri, F. On the Place of Behavior in the Analysis of Psychological Categories. Psychol Rec 65, 567–577 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40732-015-0121-8

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40732-015-0121-8

Keywords

Navigation