Skip to main content
Log in

Humboldt, Darwin, and theory of evolution

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Numerous authors have examined the influence of other thinkers on Darwin’s formulation of some of the key concepts of the theory of evolution. Amongst those, Alexander von Humboldt often stands out – a scholar who, following his intention to explain the interconnection of various parts of the natural system, seems to tackle the question of evolution but does not offer an explicit answer. In this article, I examine Humboldt’s thoughts on evolution and the origin of species and evaluate his contribution to Darwin’s theory of evolution. First, I analyse and explicate the fundamental assumptions and goals of Humboldt theory, and compare them to Darwin. Moving forward, I highlight the similarity of their methods, and argue that Humboldt and Darwin conduct similar investigation of fossil record and geographical distribution of species. Finally, I show that Humboldt acknowledges essential elements of Darwin’s theory of evolution: evidence given by fossil records, struggle for survival and relation between natural environment and living organisms. Humboldt, however, concludes we cannot know the evolution of species. I explain this stance, and contend that theories of Humboldt and Darwin turn out to be more similar than they seem, yet their different conclusions regarding the evolution of species stem from different initial assumptions underlying their respective frameworks.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For example, Glaubrecht (2022) and Helmreich (2009) offer arguments that Humboldt’s is anti-evolutionist, whilst Schmuck (2014) declares Humboldt is an evolutionist, even though he is not a Darwinian due to the methodological limitations of his theory.

  2. Citing the letter of Caroline Darwin to Charles Darwin, Baron (2010, p. 03) points out that Humboldt’s influence on Darwin can be detected even in the poetic descriptions of landmarks and life presented in Darwin’s correspondence letters. Humboldt’s vivid descriptions of South America left a notable impression on Darwin. Because of that, some authors also discuss Humboldt’s Romantic influence on Darwin’s work, e.g., Richards (2002); Sloan (2009); Greif (2015); White (2012).

  3. Puig-Samper & Rebok (2010) offer a detailed overview of correspondence and mutual reference between Humboldt and Darwin.

  4. More examples of similar evidence can be found in Voyage of Beagle where one can find many references to Humboldt, as well as numerous Darwin’s letters.

  5. For example, Humboldt states there are many relations between atmospheric electricity and other natural phenomena. In the case of the organic world, atmospheric electricity has an impact not only as a meteorological process, but as an electrical force that directly affects the nerves and promotes the circulation of “organic juices” (Humboldt, 1893, pp. 342–343).

  6. Due to limited space, the fact one can write another paper dedicated just to the Humboldtian science, and possible long digression on this topic, I refrain to futher discussion of this notion.

  7. The origin of life refers to the moment of actual creation, the beginning of existence from the non-existence (Humboldt, 1893, p. 68).

  8. For example, Darwin designed an experiment to determine how plants and animals migrate to distant island (Darwin, 1997).

  9. However, one should note that Humboldt was not the first to study biogeography. For example, August Wilhelm von Zimmermann also developed a historical biogeography and his influence on Humboldt, as Glaubrecht notices, should not be underestimated (Glaubrecht, 2022, p. 33).

  10. Reasons for such methodological decision can be found, on the one hand, in creationist interpretation of fossils and, on the other hand, in numerous criticisms that emphasized the shortcomings of this form of evidence as evidence for the theory of evolution. For details on these aspects, please see (Archibald, 2017).

  11. Besides Jackson, Helmreich states that Humboldt completely adopts Cuvier’s anti-evolutionist argumentation (2009, p. 60).

  12. Humboldt takes this example from Vol. V of his Personal Narrative (Humboldt, 1819, pp. 437–438).

  13. As noted, Cosmos is divided into several thematic units dealing with the phenomena of five different spheres: atmosphere, hydrosphere, lithosphere, biosphere (the domain of living beings), and the celestial sphere. Making an exception with these terms, Humboldt does not use the term “sphere” in the sense I opt to use it. Nonetheless, I believe the notion of five natural spheres can introduce us to a better understanding of Humboldt’s holism: life equally affects the natural processes in each of these spheres and contributes to the creation and maintenance of harmony in nature. I offer a detailed explanation in due course. On this place, I feel the need to shortly explain my usage of this term.

  14. To my knowledge, Humboldt does not use the term “struggle for survival.” He does, however, speak of the “struggle with the elements”, where the term “elements” betoken different phenomena that challenge the survival of organic beings, e.g., limited food resources, potential predators, natural disasters etc. It seems to me that the notion of struggle with the elements captures Darwinian sense of the struggle for survival.

  15. I should not that Humboldt does not separately define and discuss these phenomena. Nonetheless, they represent an important part of his general research of nature. Uncovering the relations between his distinct discussions in various writings reveals a coherent picture of his position on the problem of the evolution of species.

  16. A significant observation given the fact that the difference among the birds on islands is greater compared to the South American species.

  17. For example, in Cosmos, Humboldt refers many times to Kant’s Universal Natural History and theory of the heavens ([1755] 2012), and Kant argues in his Physical Geography that “it is to be hoped that we shall get to know a significant part of South America better through von Humboldt” (Kant, 2012 p. 508).

  18. Lofti explains the functionality of living organisms must be regarded as operating in accordance with the mechanical laws but says Kant was skeptical that we would be able to explain it from such a point of view (Lofti, 2010, p. 124); Kolb contrasts Kant’s view of organic teleology with his account of mechanical processes and concludes that explanations of purposiveness of organisms requires “both a systematic conception of a whole not found in mechanical explanations and a reversal of the mechanical order of cause and effect” (Kolb, 1992, pp.12–13).

  19. As noted before, Glaubrecht (2022) and Helmreich (2009) retain their conclusions that Humboldt is not evolutionist. Werner states we cannot find any evolutionist thesis in Humboldt’s Cosmos (Werner, 2010). Wulf states that Humboldt is evolutionist, and indicates he indeed is a pre-Darwinian Darwinist (Wulf, 2015,p. 272). Schmuck (2014), however, argues Humboldt is an evolutionist, even though he is not a Darwinian due to the methodological limitations of his theory.

  20. In fact, Humboldt’s general theory represents the fusion of natural, social and political observations, which probably represents the greatest difference between him and Darwin.

References

  • Archibald, J. D. (2017). Origins of Darwin’s evolution: Solving the species puzzle through time and place. Columbia University Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Barrett, P. H., & Corcos, Alain F. (1972). A letter from Alexander von Humboldt to Charles Darwin. Journal of the History of Medicine and Allied Sciences, 27(2), 159–172

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. J. (1976). Malthus, Darwin, and the concept of struggle. Journal of the History of Ideas, 37(4), 631–650

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baron, F. (2010). From Alexander von Humboldt to Charles Darwin: Evolution in observation and interpretation. Internet Zeitschrift für Kulturwissensdhaften, 17, 1–5. http://www.inst.at/trans/17Nr/7-8/7-8_baron17.htm

    Google Scholar 

  • Casas, V. D. (2018). Immanuel Kant, Alexander von Humboldt and the tequendama fall: Two Prussians linked by geography. Humboldt im Netz, 36, 35–46

    Google Scholar 

  • De Beer, G. (Ed.). (1960). Darwin’s notebooks on transmutation of species: Part 3: Third notebook [D]. Bulletin of the British Museum (Natural History): Historical Series 4 (2): 119–150

  • Darwin, C. (1997). The voyage of Beagle. Wordsworth Classics of World Literature

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (2009). The origin of species: By means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured races in the struggle for life (6th ed.). Cambridge University Press: Cambridge Library Collection – Darwin, Evolution and Genetics

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. (1892). Charles Darvin: His life told in an autobiographical chapter, and in a selected series of his published letters. John Murray

    Google Scholar 

  • Egerton, F. N. (1970). Humboldt, Darwin, and the concept of struggle. Journal of the History of Biology, 3(2), 325–360

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gale, B. G. (1972). Darwin and the concept of a struggle for existence: A study in the extrascientific origins in scientific ideas. Isis, 63(3), 321–344

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginsborg, H. (2001). Kant on understanding organisms as natural purposes. In E. Watkins (Ed.), Kant and the sciences (pp. 231–258). Oxford University Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Greif, H. (2015). The Darwinian tension: Romantic science and the causal laws of nature. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Science, 53, 53–61

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glaubrecht, M. (2022). “Through a country We never intended to see”: Revisiting the Humboldt renaissance. In C. Falk, Manfred R. Strecker & Simon Schneider (Eds.), Alexander von Humboldt: Multiperspective approaches. (pp. 3–36). Springer https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-94008-9

  • Humboldt, A. V., & Bonplad, A. (1822). Personal narrative of travels to the equinoctial regions of the new continent during the years 1799–1804 Vol 1 and 2. Longman, Hurst, Reese, Orme, and Brown

    Google Scholar 

  • Humboldt, A. V., & Bonplad, A. (1818). Personal narrative of travels to the equinoctial regions of the new continent during the years 1799–1804 Vol 3. Longman, Hurst, Reese, Orme, and Brown

    Google Scholar 

  • Humboldt, A. V., & Bonplad, A. (1819). Personal narrative of travels to the equinoctial regions of the new continent during the years 1799–1804 Vol 4. Longman, Hurst, Reese, Orme, and Brown

    Google Scholar 

  • Humboldt, A. V., & Bonplad, A. (1827). Personal narrative of travels to the equinoctial regions of the new continent during the years 1799–1804 Vol 5. Longman, Reese, Orme, Brown, and Green

    Google Scholar 

  • Humboldt, A. V. (1893). Cosmos: A sketch of a physical description of the universe Vol 1. George Bell and Sons

  • Humboldt, A. V. (1851). Cosmos: A sketch of a physical description of the universe Vol 3Part 1. Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans

  • Humboldt, A. V. (1860). Cosmos: A sketch of a physical description of the universe Vol 5. Harper and Brothers

  • Humboldt, A. V. (1878). Views of nature: Or contemplations on the sublime phenomena of creation. George Bell and Sons

    Google Scholar 

  • Humboldt, A. V., & Bonpland, A. (2009). Essay on the geography of plants. The University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmreich, C. (2009). Geschichte der Natur bei Alexander von Humboldt. Humboldt im Netz, 10(18), 53–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Jackson, S. T. (2009). Introduction: Humboldt, ecology, and the cosmos. In S. T. Jackson, & S. Romanowski (Eds.), Essay of the geography of plants (pp. 1–46). The University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2007). Critique of judgement. Oxford University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2012). Universal natural history and theory of the heavens or essay on the constitution and the mechanical origin of the whole universe accordion to Newtonian principles. In P. Guyer, & A. W. Wood (Eds.), Physical geography. Natural science (pp. 434–679). Cambridge University Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kolb, D. (1992). Kant, theology, and evolution. Synthese, 91, 9–28

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobloch, E. (2004). Naturgenuss und Weltgemälde. Gedanken zu Humboldts Kosmos. Humboldt im Netz, 5(9), 33–47

    Google Scholar 

  • Lofti, S. (2010). The ‘purposiveness’ of life: Kant’s critique of natural teleology. The Monist, 93, 123–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lyell, C. [1830] 1832. Principles of geology, being an attempt to explain former changes of earth’s surface, by reference to causes now in operation Vol. 2. John Murray

  • Malthus, T. R., [1798] (1878). An essay on the principle of population or a view of its past and present effects on human happiness. Reeves and Turner

    Google Scholar 

  • Puig-Samper, M. A., & Rebok, S. (2010). Charles Darwin and Alexander von Humboldt: An exchange of looks between two famous naturalists. Humboldt im Netz, 11(21), 56–65

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, W. V. (1951). Main trends in recent philosophy: Two dogmas of empiricism. The Philosophical Review, 60(1), 20–43

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, Robert J. (2002). The romantic conception of life: Science and philosophy in the age of goethe. The University of Chicago Press

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, Robert J. (2009). Darwin’s place in the history of thought: A re-evaluation. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 106(1), 10056–10060

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Romanowski, S. (2009). Humboldt’s pictorial science: An analysis of the tableau physique des andes et pays voisins. In S. T. Jackson, & S. Romanowski (Eds.), Essay on the geography of plants (pp. 157–197). University of Chicago Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Sloan, P. R. 2001.‘The sense of sublimity’: Darwin on nature and divinity. Osiris, 16, 251–269

  • Sloan, P. R. (2009). The making of a philosophical naturalist. In J. Hodge, & G. Radick (Eds.), The Cambridge companion to Darwin (pp. 21–43). Cambridge University Press

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Schmuck, T. (2014). Humboldt, Baer und die evolution. Humboldt im Netz, 15(29), 80–86

    Google Scholar 

  • Werner, P. (2009). Zum verhältnis Charles Darwins zu Humboldt und Ehrenberg. Humboldt im Netz, 10(18), 68–95

    Google Scholar 

  • Werner, P. (2010). Charles Darwin and Alexander von Humboldt. Sitzungsberichte der Leibniz-Soziet?t der wissenschaften zu Berlin. 105, 107?121

  • White, P. (2012). Darwin, Concepción, and the geological sublime. Science in Context, 25, 49–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wulf, A. (2015). The invention of nature: Alexander von Humboldt’s new world. Alfred A. Knopf

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Slobodan Perovi? for carefully reading and commenting on previous versions of the manuscript. His suggestions helped to greatly improve it. I also thank two anonymous referees for their insightful suggestions.

Funding

This research was supported by the Ministry of education, science and technological development of the Republic of Serbia under the project ?Dynamical systems in nature and society: philosophical and empirical aspects? (179041).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Bogdana Stamenković.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Stamenković, B. Humboldt, Darwin, and theory of evolution. HPLS 44, 57 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-022-00546-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s40656-022-00546-3

Keywords

Navigation