Skip to main content
Log in

A Plea for Ecological Argument Technologies

  • Research Article
  • Published:
Philosophy & Technology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

    We’re sorry, something doesn't seem to be working properly.

    Please try refreshing the page. If that doesn't work, please contact support so we can address the problem.

Abstract

In spite of significant research efforts, argument technologies do not seem poised to scale up as much as most commentators would hope or even predict. In this paper, I discuss what obstacles bar the way to more widespread success of argument technologies and venture some suggestions on how to circumvent such difficulties: doing so will require a significant shift in how this research area is typically understood and practiced. I begin by exploring a much broader yet closely related question: To what extent are people natively good at arguing? This issue has always been central to philosophical reflection and it has become even more urgent nowadays, with the explosion of persuasive technologies and unprecedented opportunities for large-scale social influence. The answer hinges on what aspect of argumentation is taken under consideration: evidence suggests that people are relatively bad at analyzing the structure of arguments, especially when these are presented out of context and in abstract terms; in contrast, data show that even laymen tend to excel in the interactive practice of argumentation, in particular when motivation is high and something significant is at stake. Unfortunately, current argument technologies are more closely tailored to the former type of activity than to the latter, which is the main reason behind their relative lack of success with the general public. Changing this state of affair will require a commitment to ecological argument technologies: that is, technologies designed to support real-time, engaging and meaningful argumentative interactions performed by laypeople in their ordinary life, instead of catering to the highly specific needs of a minority of niche users (typically, argumentation scholars).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. “Argument”, retrieved December 28, 2015, from http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/argument

  2. CMNA, Computational Models of Natural Arguments, since 2001 (http://www.cmna.info/); ArgMAS, Argumentation in Multi-Agent Systems, since 2004 (http://www.mit.edu/~irahwan/argmas/); UM4Motivation, User Models for Motivational Systems, in 2011 and 2012 (http://cgi.csc.liv.ac.uk/~floriana/UM4Motivation2/Home.html)

  3. COMMA, Computational Model of Arguments, since 2006 (http://www.comma-conf.org/)

  4. Just to mention a few: ASPIC, Argumentation Service Platform with Integrated Components (http://cordis.europa.eu/ist/kct/aspic_synopsis.htm); DAM, Dialectical Argumentation Machines (http://www.arg-tech.org/index.php/projects/dialectical-argumentation-machines/); DYNARG, The Dynamics of Argumentation (http://icr.uni.lu/dynarg/DYNARG/Home.html); and the recent EPSRC large grant on Argument Mining (http://gow.epsrc.ac.uk/NGBOViewGrant.aspx?GrantRef=EP/N014871/1)

  5. The EU COST action Agreement Technologies (http://www.agreement-technologies.eu/)

  6. AT, International Conference on Agreement Technologies, since 2012 (http://www.agreement-technologies.eu/resources/at-conference-series)

  7. The notion of ecological argument technologies detailed in this paper refers to the broader concept of ecological rationality, as developed by Gigerenzer and Selten (2001) and Gigerenzer et al. (2011). The ties between the present proposal and this line of work will be further discussed later on: for now, let us just say that an argumentative technology, in order to be ecological in the required sense, ought to be designed to match the argumentative skills human users developed in response to the ecological pressures they face in everyday life.

  8. Non-ecological argument technologies may still be very valuable for dedicated purposes, e.g., education, and may even provide guidance on how to design more productive and sustainable platforms and tools. What they cannot do, however, is to scale up, as long as they fail to meet the ecological challenge. This is the claim articulated in this paper, which of course does not deny the potential usefulness of argument technologies also in more restricted domains.

  9. Both the universality and the incorrigibility claims are tied to the tradition of classifying fallacies at a high level of abstraction, as idealized inference patterns—a tradition criticized by van Eemeren and Grootendorst (1995), among others. In contrast, situated learning theory (Lave and Wenger 1991) has provided evidence that otherwise common errors occur less frequently (and are more varied) in concrete problem-solving situations, as opposed to abstractly defined problems. An echo of this line of work can be found in recent attempts to articulate more nuanced versions of fallacy theory, which will be discussed in Section 2.2 (see also Boudry et al. 2015; Paglieri 2016).

  10. The key documents to consult, in order to get a sense of the dominant institutional view on critical thinking education in Italy, are the current guidelines on the curriculum of Italian kindergartens and primary and secondary schools (“Indicazioni nazionali per il curricolo della scuola dell’infanzia e del primo ciclo di istruzione,” http://www.indicazioninazionali.it/documenti_Indicazioni_nazionali/indicazioni_nazionali_infanzia_primo_ciclo.pdf), issued by the Italian Ministry of Education and Research (MIUR) in September 2012. In that document, critical thinking is identified as a priority across all disciplines, in spite of the utter lack of (i) dedicated critical thinking training for teachers and (ii) resources to support the proclaimed shift towards more rigorous critical thinking education in Italian schools.

  11. See http://www.admissionstestingservice.org/for-test-takers/thinking-skills-assessment/.

  12. Source: http://www.admissionstestingservice.org/images/47832-tsa-test-specification.pdf (last consulted on December 27, 2015)

  13. Source: http://www.admissionstestingservice.org/for-test-takers/thinking-skills-assessment/tsa-cambridge/about-tsa-cambridge/ (last consulted on December 27, 2015)

  14. Source: http://www.merton.ox.ac.uk/admissions-feedback-economics-and-management (last consulted on December 27, 2015)

  15. Given all these differences across groups, in terms of test materials, sample size, methodology, context, etc., running statistical analyses on these data would be rather uninformative. Thus, statistical details will be kept to a minimum and provided only for those comparisons that are methodologically appropriate. For the same reason, these findings are meant here only to illustrate the difficulties that various sorts of people encounter in dealing with abstract argument analysis.

  16. Of course, the fact that we are forced to admit the existence of non-fallacious fallacies is just another indication of the theoretical inadequacy of the standard notion of a fallacy: a category designed to capture erroneous reasoning ends up including in its extension also acceptable forms of inference. But what to do about the problematic status of fallacy theory is a topic for another day (for discussion, see Woods 2013; Paglieri 2016).

  17. These results should not be confused with the claim that people are “good with probabilities,” since there is ample evidence they are not—witness the garden variety of well-known biases of probabilistic reasoning, e.g., gambler’s fallacy (Tversky and Kahneman 1971), conjunction fallacy (Tversky and Kahneman 1983), and base rate neglect (Tversky and Kahneman 1982). What these findings show, instead, is that people track the quality of argument based on the same factors that would be relevant if Bayesian update was used: the observed similarity is at the level of the outcome, with no claim being made on a corresponding similarity of mechanisms—indeed, people are certainly not doing Bayesian computation as part of their explicit reasoning. The fact that we get the outcome right when evaluating each other’s arguments, while we do not in solitary reasoning tasks of the sort used by Tversky and Kahneman, provides further support to the argumentative theory of reasoning.

  18. Similar considerations apply also to (and have received much more attention in) instructional design in computer-supported collaborative learning, as documented by scripting studies; for a discussion of several applications to argument education, see Weinberger et al. (2007).

  19. While this may seem reminiscent of Facebook likes, it is actually not—or, more precisely, it aims to achieve the same level of intuitive appeal but for entirely different purposes. What prevents Facebook likes from being used as argumentative indicators is their ambiguity of meaning: by liking a post, a comment, a photo, or anything else, a Facebook user may express a variety of communicative intentions—approval of the contents, support, or solidarity for the author of the contents, approval for the fact that the author of the post decided to make it public, hilarity prompted by the contents or their posting, and more. Argument technologies should strive to provide users with tagging options that are as appealing as Facebook likes but with a much better defined semantics.

  20. See http://staff.computing.dundee.ac.uk/creed/araucaria/.

  21. See http://www.arg.dundee.ac.uk/index.php/ova/.

  22. See https://carneades.github.io/Carneades/.

  23. See http://www.arg.dundee.ac.uk/?p=492.

  24. See http://www.arg-tech.org/index.php/projects/argument-analysis-wall/.

  25. See http://compendium.open.ac.uk/.

  26. See http://cci.mit.edu/klein/deliberatorium.html.

  27. Interestingly, expecting users to dwell too much on argument structure may be not only unrealistic but even undesirable. A recent study on using Facebook for learning purposes (Tsovaltzi et al. 2015b) showed that participants who had carefully prepared their own arguments on a given topic were less likely to interact productively with other SNS users on that topic, compared to people without that sort of individual preparation—yet another finding fully compatible with the argumentative theory of reasoning. That led the authors to conclude that “directly interacting with the support of argumentation scripts and without long individual preparation and reflection may be preferable to carefully preparing arguments before joining discussion in a SNS” (Tsovaltzi et al. 2015b, p. 588).

  28. Crucially, complex argument annotation systems are problematic also for experts, not only for laypeople. When using a simplified version of Walton’s argumentation scheme taxonomy (including 14 schemes out of 60), with coders trained on argumentation and four iterations of the annotation procedure, the final level of inter-coder agreement can still be as low as 0.48, measured by Cohen’s kappa (Schneider et al. 2013). This figure raises to more acceptable levels only when simpler annotation schemes are adopted (Schneider et al. 2012b), and it is further improved by isolating ex post the most reliable sub-groups of annotators (Peldszus and Stede 2013b).

  29. See http://dbp.idebate.org/en/index.php/Welcome_to_Debatepedia%21.

  30. See http://www.argublogging.com/.

  31. See https://play.google.com/store/apps/details?id=it.unibo.ai.microdebates&hl=en.

References

  • Amgoud, L., & Prade, H. (2009). Using arguments for making and explaining decisions. Artificial Intelligence, 173(3–4), 413–436.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Antoci, A., Sabatini, F., & Sodini, M. (2015). Online and offline social participation and social poverty traps. Journal of Mathematical Sociology. forthcoming.

  • Baroni, P., & Giacomin, M. (2007). On principle-based evaluation of extension-based argumentation semantics. Artificial Intelligence, 171(10), 675–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bench-Capon, T., & Dunne, P. (2007). Argumentation in artificial intelligence. Artificial Intelligence, 171(10), 619–641.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Besnar, P., & Hunter, A. (2001). A logic-based theory of deductive arguments. Artificial Intelligence, 128(1–2), 203–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F., Lawrence, J., Snaith, M., & Reed, C. (2013). Implementing the argument web. Communications of the ACM, 56(10), 66–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bex, F., Snaith, M., Lawrence, J., & Reed, C. (2014). ArguBlogging: an application for the argument web. Web Semantics: Science, Services and Agents on the World Wide Web, 25, 9–15.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boudry, M., Pigliucci, M., & Paglieri, F. (2015). The fake, the flimsy, and the fallacious: demarcating arguments in real life. Argumentation, 29(4), 431–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckingham Shum, S. (2008). Cohere: towards web 2.0 argumentation. In P. Besnard, S. Doutre, & A. Hunter (Eds.), Computational models of argument: proceedings of COMMA 2008 (pp. 97–108). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Buckingham Shum, S., Selvin, A., Sierhuis, M., Conklin, J., Haley, C., & Nuseibeh, B. (2006). Hypermedia support for argumentation-based rationale. In A. Dutoit, R. McCall, I. Mistrík, & B. Paech (Eds.), Rationale management in software engineering (pp. 111–132). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Butterworth, J., & Thwaites, G. (2013). Thinking skills: critical thinking and problem solving (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cabrio, E., & Villata, S. (2013). A natural language bipolar argumentation approach to support users in online debate interactions. Argument & Computation, 4(3), 209–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Caminada, M., & Amgoud, L. (2007). On the evaluation of argumentation formalisms. Artificial Intelligence, 171(5–6), 286–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carbogim, D., Robertson, D., & Lee, J. (2000). Argument-based applications to knowledge engineering. The Knowledge Engineering Review, 15(2), 119–149.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chang, C. F., Miller, A., & Ghose, A. (2010). Mixed-initiative argumentation: group decision support in medicine. In P. Kostkova (Ed.), Electronic healthcare: proceedings of eHealth 2009 (pp. 43–50). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chesnevar, C., McGinnis, J., Modgil, S., Rahwan, I., Reed, C., Simari, G., South, M., Vreeswijk, G., & Willmott, S. (2006). Towards an argument interchange format. Knowledge Engineering Review, 21(4), 293–316.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Collins, P., Hahn, U., von Gerber, Y., & Olsson, E. (2015). The bi-directional relationship between source characteristics and message content. In D. Noelle, R. Dale, A. Warlaumont, J. Yoshimi, T. Matlock, C. Jennings & P. Maglio (Eds.), Proceedings of the 37th Annual Meeting of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 423–428). Austin, TX: Cognitive Science Society.

  • Conklin, J., Selvin, A., Buckingham Shum, S., & Sierhuis, M. (2001). Facilitated hypertext for collective sensemaking: 15 years on from gIBIS. In K. Grønbæk, H. Davis &Y. Douglas (Eds.), Hypertext’01: Proceedings of the 12th ACM Conference on Hypertext and Hypermedia (pp. 123–124). New York: ACM.

  • Corner, A., & Hahn, U. (2012). Normative theories of argumentation: are some norms better than others? Synthese, 190(16), 3579–3610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Moor, A., & Aakhus, M. (2006). Argumentation support: from technologies to tools. Communications of the ACM, 49(3), 93–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duggan, M. (2014). Online harassment. Washington: Pew Research Internet Project.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dung, P. (1995). On the acceptability of arguments and its fundamental role in nonmonotonic reasoning, logic programming, and n-person games. Artificial Intelligence, 77, 321–357.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dung, P., Kowalski, R., & Toni, F. (2006). Dialectic proof procedures for assumption-based, admissible argumentation. Artificial Intelligence, 170(2), 114–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellison, N., Steinfield, C., & Lampe, C. (2007). The benefits of facebook friends: social capital and college students’ use of online social network sites. Journal of Computer-Mediated Communication, 12, 114–1168.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ennis, R. (1989). Critical thinking and subject specificity: clarification and needed research. Educational Researcher, 18(3), 4–10.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ennis, R. (1993). Critical thinking assessment. Theory Into Practice, 32(3), 179–186.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Facione, P. (Ed.) (1990). Critical thinking: a statement of expert consensus for purposes of educational assessment and instruction. American Philosophical Association: ERIC document ED 315–423.

  • Finocchiaro, M. (1981). Fallacies and the evaluation of reasoning. American Philosophical Quarterly, 18(1), 13–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fiske, S., & Taylor, S. (1984). Social cognition. Reading: Addison-Wesley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Floridi, L. (2009). Logical fallacies as informational shortcuts. Synthese, 167, 317–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fogg, B. J. (2003). Persuasive technology: using computers to change what we think and do. San Francisco: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S. (2005). Cognitive reflection and decision making. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 19(4), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gabbriellini, S., & Torroni, P. (2012). Large-scale agreements via microdebates. In S. Ossowski, G. Vouros & F. Toni (Eds.), AT 2012: Proceedings of the 1st International Conference on Agreement Technologies (pp. 366–377). Tilburg: CEUR-WS.org.

  • Garcia, A., & Simari, G. (2014). Defeasible logic programming: DeLP-servers, contextual queries, and explanations for answers. Argument & Computation, 5(1), 63–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garrison, D. R., Anderson, T., & Archer, W. (2001). Critical thinking, cognitive presence, and computer conferencing in distance education. American Journal of Distance Education, 15(1), 7–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Selten, R. (Eds.). (2001). Bounded rationality: the adaptive toolbox. Cambridge: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., Hertwig, R., & Pachur, T. (Eds.). (2011). Heuristics: the foundations of adaptive behavior. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodwin, J. (1998). Forms of authority and the real ad verecundiam. Argumentation, 12(2), 267–280.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, T. (2010). An overview of the Carneades argumentation support system. In C. Tindale & C. Reed (Eds.), Dialectics, dialogue and argumentation. An examination of Douglas Walton’s theories of reasoning (pp. 145–156). London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Govier, T. (1987). Problems in argument analysis and evaluation. Dordrecht: Foris.

    Google Scholar 

  • Groarke, L. (2009). What’s wrong with the California critical thinking skills test? CT testing and accountability. In J. Sobocan & L. Groarke (Eds.), Critical thinking education and assessment: can higher order thinking be tested? (pp. 35–54). London: The Althouse Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action. Boston: Beacon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., & Oaksford, M. (2007). The rationality of informal argumentation: a Bayesian approach to reasoning fallacies. Psychological Review, 114, 704–732.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Harris, A. J. L., & Corner, A. (2009). Argument content and argument source: an exploration. Informal Logic, 29(4), 337–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Oaksford, M., & Harris, A. J. L. (2012). Testimony and argument: a Bayesian perspective. In F. Zenker (Ed.), Bayesian argumentation (pp. 15–38). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hahn, U., Oaksford, M., & Harris, A. J. L. (2013). Rational inference, rational argument. Argument & Computation, 4, 21–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hamblin, C. (1970). Fallacies. London: Methuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, A. J. L., Hsu, A. S., & Madsen, J. K. (2012). Because Hitler did it! Quantitative tests of Bayesian argumentation using ad hominem. Thinking and Reasoning, 18(3), 311–343.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (1987). The fallacy of fallacies. Argumentation, 1(3), 211–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. (1995). Do the fallacies have a place in the teaching of reasoning skills or critical thinking? In H. V. Hansen & R. C. Pinto (Eds.), Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings (pp. 319–327). University Park: Penn State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. (2006). Informal logic and the concept of argument. In D. Jacquette (Ed.), Philosophy of logic (Handbook of the philosophy of science, Vol. Volume 5, pp. 101–129). Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hitchcock, D. (2007). Why there is no argumentum ad hominem fallacy. In F. H. van Eemeren & B. Garssen (Eds.), Proceedings of the Sixth Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation (Volume 1, pp. 615–620). Amsterdam: Sic Sat.

  • Introne, J., & Iandoli, L. (2014). Improving decision-making performance through argumentation: an argument-based decision support system to compute with evidence. Decision Support Systems, 64, 79–89.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janier, M., Lawrence, J., & Reed, C. (2014). OVA+: an argument analysis interface. In S. Parsons, N. Oren, C. Reed & F. Cerutti (Eds.), Computational Models of Argument: Proceedings of COMMA 2014 (pp. 463–464). Amsterdam: IOS Press

  • Johnson, R., & Blair, A. (1977). Logical self-defense. Toronto: McGraw-Hill Ryerson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Karacapilidis, N., & Papadias, D. (2001). Computer supported argumentation and collaborative decision making: the HERMES system. Information Systems, 26(4), 259–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karunatillake, N., Jennings, N., Rahwan, I., & McBurney, P. (2009). Dialogue games that agents play within a society. Artificial Intelligence, 173(9–10), 935–981.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, P. (2015). Facebook as learning platform: argumentation superhighway or dead-end street? Computers in Human Behavior, 53, 621–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirschner, P., Buckingham Shum, S., & Carr, C. (Eds.). (2003). Visualizing argumentation. Software tools for collaborative and educational sense-making. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klein, M. (2012). Enabling large-scale deliberation using attention-mediation metrics. Journal of Computer-Supported Cooperative Work, 21(4), 449–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klein, M., & Convertino, G. (2014). An embarrassment of riches. Communications of the ACM, 57(11), 40–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, D. (1991). The skills of arguments. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. Psychological Bulletin, 108, 480–498.

  • Laughlin, P., & Ellis, A. (1986). Demonstrability and social combination processes on mathematical intellective tasks. Journal of Experimental Social Psychology, 22, 177–189.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lave, J., & Wenger, E. (1991). Situated learning: legitimate peripheral participation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawrence, J., Bex, F., & Reed, C. (2012). Dialogues on the argument web: mixed initiative argumentation with Arvina. In B. Verheij, S. Szeider & S. Woltran (Eds.), Computational Models of Argument: Proceedings of COMMA 2012 (pp. 513–514). Amsterdam: IOS Press.

  • Lawrence, J., Reed, C., Allen, C., McAlister, S., Ravenscroft, A., & Bourget, D. (2014). Mining arguments from 19th century philosophical texts using topic based modelling. In N. Green, K. Ashley, D. Litman, C. Reed & V. Walke (Eds.), Proceedings of the First Workshop on Argumentation Mining (pp. 79–87). Stroudsburg, PA: ACL

  • Levesque, H. J. (1986). Making believers out of computers. Artificial Intelligence, 30(1), 81–108.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, D. S. (1999). The fallacy of treating the ad baculum as a fallacy. Informal Logic, 19(2–3), 145–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lindsay, B. (2009). Creating “the Wikipedia of pros and cons”. In D. Riehle & A. Bruckman (Eds.), WikiSym’09: Proceedings of the 5th International Symposium on Wikis and Open Collaboration (n. 36). New York: ACM.

  • Mackenzie, P. T. (1980). Ad hominem and ad verecundiam. Informal Logic, 3(3), 9–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • Massey, G. (1981). The fallacy behind fallacies. Midwest Studies In Philosophy, 6(1), 489–500.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McPeck, J. (1990). Critical thinking and subject specificity: a reply to Ennis. Educational Researcher, 19(4), 10–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H. (2010). The social origins of folk epistemology. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1(4), 499–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H. (2013). Our pigheaded core: how we became smarter to be influenced by other people. In K. Sterelny, R. Joyce, B. Calcott, & B. Fraser (Eds.), Cooperation and its evolution (pp. 373–398). Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2009). Intuitive and reflective inferences. In J. S. B. T. Evans & K. Frankish (Eds.), In two minds: dual processes and beyond (pp. 149–170). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2011). Why do humans reason? Arguments for an argumentative theory. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 34(2), 57–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H., Trouche, E., Yama, H., Heintz, C., & Girotto, V. (2015). Experts and laymen grossly underestimate the benefits of argumentation for reasoning. Thinking and Reasoning, 21(3), 341–355.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2010). Take my advice—I am not following it: ad hominem arguments as legitimate rebuttals to appeals to authority. Informal Logic, 30(4), 435–456.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mochales Palau, R., & Moens, M.-F. (2009). Argumentation mining: the detection, classification and structure of arguments in text. In P. Casanovas & C. Hafner (Eds.), Proceedings of the 12th International Conference on Artificial intelligence and Law (pp. 98–107). New York: ACM.

  • Mochales Palau, R., & Moens, M.-F. (2011). Argumentation mining. Artificial Intelligence and Law, 19(1), 1–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modgil, S. (2009). Reasoning about preferences in argumentation frameworks. Artificial Intelligence, 173(9–10), 901–934.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modgil, S., & Caminada, M. (2009). Proof theories and algorithms for abstract argumentation frameworks. In I. Rahwan & G. Simari (Eds.), Argumentation in artificial intelligence (pp. 105–129). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Modgil, S., & Prakken, H. (2014). The ASPIC+ framework for structured argumentation: a tutorial. Argument and Computation, 5(1), 31–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Modgil, S., Toni, F., Bex, F., Bratko, I., Chesñevar, C., Dvorák, W., & Woltran, S. (2013). The added value of argumentation. In S. Ossowski (Ed.), Agreement technologies (pp. 357–403). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Moens, M.-F., Boiy, E., Mochales Palau, R., & Reed, C. (2007). Automatic detection of arguments in legal texts. In A. Gardner & R. Winkels (Eds.), Proceedings of the 11th International Conference on Artificial intelligence and Law (pp. 225–230). New York: ACM.

  • Morge, M. (2008). The hedgehog and the fox. An argumentation-based decision support system. In I. Rahwan, S. Parsons & C. Reed (Eds.), Argumentation in Multi-Agent Systems: Proceedings of ArgMAS 2007 (pp. 114–131). Berlin: Springer.

  • Moshman, D., & Geil, M. (1998). Collaborative reasoning: evidence for collective rationality. Thinking and Reasoning, 4(3), 231–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nickerson, R. (1998). Confirmation bias: a ubiquitous phenomena in many guises. Review of General Psychology, 2, 175–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • O’Keefe, D. (1977). Two concepts of argument. Journal of the American Forensic Society, 13, 121–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ossowski, S. (Ed.). (2012). Agreement technologies. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paglieri, F. (2016). Don’t worry, be gappy! On the unproblematic gappiness of fallacies. In F. Paglieri, L. Bonelli, & S. Felletti (Eds.), The psychology of argument: cognitive approaches to argumentation and persuasion (pp. 153–172). London: College Publications.

  • Paglieri, F., & Castelfranchi, C. (2010). Why argue? Towards a cost–benefit analysis of argumentation. Argument and Computation, 1(1), 71–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peldszus, A., & Stede, M. (2013a). From argument diagrams to argumentation mining in texts: a survey. International Journal of Cognitive Informatics and Natural Intelligence, 7(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peldszus, A., & Stede, M. (2013b). Ranking the annotators: An agreement study on argumentation structure. In S. Dipper, M. Liakata & A. Pareja-Lora (Eds.), Proceedings of the 7th Linguistic Annotation Workshop & Interoperability with Discourse (pp. 196–204). Stroudsburg, PA: ACL.

  • Perkins, D., Farady, M., & Bushey, B. (1991). Everyday reasoning and the roots of intelligence. In J. Voss, D. Perkins, & J. Segal (Eds.), Informal reasoning and education (pp. 83–105). Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Possin, K. (2008). A field guide to critical-thinking assessment. Teaching Philosophy, 31(3), 201–228.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prakken, H. (2010). An abstract framework for argumentation with structured arguments. Argument and Computation, 1(2), 93–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I. (2008). Mass argumentation and the semantic web. Web Semantics: Science, Services and Agents on the World Wide Web, 6(1), 29–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., & McBurney, P. (2007). Argumentation technology. IEEE Intelligent Systems, 22(6), 21–23.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., & Simari, G. (Eds.). (2009). Argumentation in artificial intelligence. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., Ramchurn, S., Jennings, N., McBurney, P., Parsons, S., & Sonenberg, L. (2004). Argumentation-based negotiation. The Knowledge Engineering Review, 18(4), 343–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., Zablith, F., & Reed, C. (2007). Laying the foundations for a world wide argument web. Artificial Intelligence, 171(10–15), 897–921.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., Banihashemi, B., Reed, C., Walton, D., & Abdallah, S. (2011). Representing and classifying arguments on the semantic web. The Knowledge Engineering Review, 26(4), 487–511.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rahwan, I., Krasnoshtan, D., Shariff, A., & Bonnefon, J.-F. (2014). Analytical reasoning task reveals limits of social learning in networks. Journal of the Royal Society, Interface, 11(93), 20131211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rainie, L., Lenhart, A., & Smith, A. (2012). The tone of life on social networking sites. Washington: Pew Internet Research Center.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C., & Norman, T. (Eds.). (2004). Argumentation machines. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C., & Rowe, G. (2004). Araucaria: software for argument analysis, diagramming and representation. International Journal on Artificial Intelligence Tools, 13(4), 961–980.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reed, C., & Walton, D. (2003). Argumentation schemes in argument-as-process and argument-as-product. in J. A. Blair, D. Farr, H. Hansen, R. Johnson and C. Tindale (Eds.), Informal Logic @ 25: Proceedings of the 5th OSSA Conference. Windsor, Ontario: OSSA.

  • Reed, C., Wells, S., Snaith, M., Budzynska, K., & Lawrence, J. (2011). Using an argument ontology to develop pedagogical tool suites. In P. Blackburn, H. van Ditmarsch, M. Manzano, & F. Soler-Toscano (Eds.), Tools for teaching logic: proceedings of TICTTL 2011 (pp. 207–214). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rowe, G., Macagno, F., Reed, C., & Walton, D. (2006). Araucaria as a tool for diagramming arguments in teaching and studying philosophy. Teaching Philosophy, 29(2), 111–124.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sà, W., West, R., & Stanovich, K. (1999). The domain specificity and generality of belief bias: searching for a generalizable critical thinking skill. Journal of Educational Psychology, 91(3), 497–510.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sabatini, F., & Sarracino, F. (2014). Online networks and subjective well-being. ArXiv, 1408, 3550.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheuer, O., Loll, F., Pinkwart, N., & McLaren, B. (2010). Computer-supported argumentation: a review of the state of the art. International Journal of Computer-Supported Collaborative Learning, 5(1), 43–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, J. (2014). An informatics perspective on argumentation mining. In E. Cabrio, S. Villata, & A. Wyner (Eds.), Proceedings of the workshop on frontiers and connections between argumentation theory and natural language processing (pp. 1–4). Aachen: CEUR-WS.org.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schneider, J., Groza, T., & Passant, A. (2012a). A review of argumentation for the Social Semantic Web. Semantic Web-Interoperability, Usability, Applicability, 4(2), 159–218.

  • Schneider, J., Passant, A., & Decker, S. (2012b). Deletion discussions in Wikipedia: decision factors and outcomes. In C. Lampe (Ed.), WikiSym2012: Proceedings of the 8th Annual International Symposium on Wikis and Open Collaboration (n. 17). New York: ACM.

  • Schneider, J., Samp, K., Passant, A., & Decker, S. (2013). Arguments about deletion: how experience improves the acceptability of arguments in ad-hoc online task groups. In A. Bruckman, S. Counts, C. Lampe & L. Terveen (Eds.), CSCW2013: Proceedings of the 2013 Conference on Computer Supported Cooperative Work (pp. 1069–1080). New York: ACM.

  • Scriven, M. (1987). Fallacies of statistical substitution. Argumentation, 1, 333–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. A. (1956). Rational choice and the structure of the environment. Psychological Review, 63, 129–138.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., Clément, F., Heintz, C., Mascaro, O., Mercier, H., Origgi, G., & Wilson, D. (2010). Epistemic vigilance. Mind & Language, 25(4), 359–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stanovich, K., & West, R. (2007). Natural myside bias is independent of cognitive ability. Thinking and Reasoning, 13(3), 225–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steinfield, C., Ellison, N., & Lampe, C. (2008). Social capital, self-esteem, and use of online social network sites: a longitudinal analysis. Journal of Applied Developmental Psychology, 29, 434–445.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, M. (2012). Denying the antecedent: its effective use in argumentation. Informal Logic, 32(3), 327–356.

  • Surowiecki, J. (2004). The wisdom of crowds. New York: Doubleday.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toplak, M., West, R., & Stanovich, K. (2011). The cognitive reflection test as a predictor of performance on heuristics-and-biases tasks. Memory & Cognition, 39, 1275–1289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Towne, W. B., & Herbsleb, J. (2012). Design considerations for online deliberation systems. Journal of Information Technology & Politics, 9(1), 97–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trouche, E., Sander, E., & Mercier, H. (2014). Arguments, more than confidence, explain the good performance of reasoning groups. Journal of Experimental Psychology. General, 143(5), 1958–1971.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Trouche, E., Johansson, P., Hall, L., & Mercier, H. (in press). The selective laziness of reasoning. Cognitive Science, doi: 10.1111/cogs.12303

  • Tsovaltzi, D., Greenhow, C., & Asterhan, C. (2015a). When friends argue: learning from and through social network site discussions. Computers in Human Behavior, 53, 567–569.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tsovaltzi, D., Judele, R., Puhl, T., & Weinberger, A. (2015b). Scripts, individual preparation and group awareness support in the service of learning in Facebook: how does CSCL compare to social networking sites? Computers in Human Behavior, 53, 577–592.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1971). Belief in the law of small numbers. Psychological Bulletin, 76(2), 105–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1982). Evidential impact of base rates. In D. Kahneman, P. Slovic, & A. Tversky (Eds.), Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases (pp. 153–160). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1983). Extensional versus intuitive reasoning: the conjunction fallacy in probability judgment. Psychological Review, 90(4), 293–315.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F., & Grootendorst, R. (1992). Relevance reviewed: the case of argumentum ad hominem. Argumentation, 6(2), 14–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Eemeren, F., & Grootendorst, R. (1995). The pragma-dialectical approach to fallacies. In H. V. Hansen & R. C. Pinto (Eds.), Fallacies: classical and contemporary readings (pp. 130–144). University Park: Penn State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1992). Nonfallacious arguments from ignorance. American Philosophical Quarterly, 29(4), 381–387.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1996). Argumentation schemes for presumptive reasoning. Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1997). Appeal to expert opinion: arguments from authority. University Park: The Pennsylvania State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1998). Ad hominem arguments. Tuscaloosa: The University of Alabama Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (1999). The appeal to ignorance, or argumentum ad ignorantiam. Argumentation, 13(4), 367–377.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D. (2000). Scare tactics: arguments that appeal to fear and threats. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., & Godden, D. M. (2007). Informal logic and the dialectical approach to argument. In H. Hansen & R. Pinto (Eds.), Reason reclaimed (pp. 3–17). Newport News: Vale Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., & Gordon, T. (2012). The Carneades model of argument invention. Pragmatics & Cognition, 20(1), 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Walton, D., Reed, C., & Macagno, F. (2008). Argumentation schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. C. (1966). Reasoning. In B. Foss (Ed.), New horizons in psychology: I (pp. 106–137). Harmandsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberger, A., Stegmann, K., Fischer, F., & Mandl, H. (2007). Scripting argumentative knowledge construction in computer-supported learning environments. In F. Fischer, I. Kollar, H. Mandl, & J. M. Haake (Eds.), Scripting computer-supported collaborative learning (pp. 191–211). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (1998). Argumentum ad baculum. Argumentation, 12(4), 493–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2013). Errors of reasoning. Naturalizing the logic of inference. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., & Walton, D. (1974). Argumentum ad verecundiam. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 7(3), 135–153.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J., & Walton, D. (1978). The fallacy of ‘ad ignorantiam’. Dialectica, 32(2), 87–99.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yaglikci, N., & Torroni, P. (2014). Microdebates app for Android: a tool for participating in argumentative online debates using a handheld device. In A. Andreou & G. A. Papadopoulos (Eds.), Proceedings of ICTAI 2014: IEEE 26th International Conference on Tools with Artificial Intelligence (pp. 792–799). Los Alamitos, CA: IEEE.

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Fabio Paglieri.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Paglieri, F. A Plea for Ecological Argument Technologies. Philos. Technol. 30, 209–238 (2017). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-016-0222-6

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13347-016-0222-6

Keywords

Navigation