Skip to main content
Log in

Difference and Robustness in the Patterns of Philosophical Intuition Across Demographic Groups

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In a recent paper, I argued that philosophical intuitions are surprisingly robust both across demographic groups and across development. Machery and Stich reply by reviewing a series of studies that do show significant differences in philosophical intuition between different demographic groups. This is a helpful point, which gets at precisely the issues that are most relevant here. However, even when one looks at those very studies, one finds truly surprising robustness. In other words, despite the presence of statistically significant differences between demographic groups, a core finding coming out of those studies is that philosophical intuitions are surprisingly robust across demographic groups.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2

Similar content being viewed by others

References

  • Buckwalter, W. 2010. Knowledge isn’t closed on Saturday: A study in ordinary language. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1: 395–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W. 2014. Gettier made ESEE. Philosophical Psychology 27 (3): 368–383.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., and Schaffer, J. 2015. Knowledge, stakes and mistakes. Noûs, 49(2): 201–234.

  • Cimpian, A., A.C. Brandone, and S.A. Gelman. 2010. Generic statements require little evidence for acceptance but have powerful implications. Cognitive Science 34: 1452–1482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cova, F., Olivola, C. Y., Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Alai, M., ..., and Cheon, H. 2019. De pulchritudine non est disputandum? A cross‐cultural investigation of the alleged intersubjective validity of aesthetic judgment. Mind & Language, 34(3):317–338.

  • Cova, F., and N. Pain. 2012. Can folk aesthetics ground aesthetic realism? The Monist 95 (2): 241–263.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donelson, R., and Hannikainen, I. R. 2020. The inner morality of law revisited. Oxford studies in experimental philosophy, 3, 6–28.

  • Dranseika, V., and Lauraitytė, E. 2016 Experimental Jurisprudence Cross-Cultural Study Swap Consortium. unpublished data. Cross-cultural Replication of Tobia.

  • Feltz, A., and C. Zarpentine. 2010. Do you know more when it matters less? Philosophical Psychology 23: 683–706.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frederick, S. 2005. Cognitive reflection and decision making. Journal of Economic Perspectives 19: 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hannikainen, I. R., Machery, E., Rose, D., Stich, S., Olivola, C. Y., Sousa, P., ..., and Berniūnas, R. 2019 For whom does determinism undermine moral responsibility? Surveying the conditions for free will across cultures. Frontiers in Psychology 10:2428.

  • Hannikainen, I. R., Tobia, K. P., De Almeida, G. D. F., Donelson, R., Dranseika, V., Kneer, M., and Struchiner, N. 2021. Are there cross-cultural legal principles? Modal reasoning uncovers procedural constraints on law. Cognitive Science 45(8), e13024.

  • Hitchcock, C., and J. Knobe. 2009. Cause and norm. The Journal of Philosophy 106 (11): 587612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2003. Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis 63: 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. 2014 Free will and the scientific vision. In E. Machery & E. Oneill (Eds.), Current controversies in experimental philosophy (pp. 69–85). New York: Routledge.

  • Knobe, J. 2019. Philosophical intuitions are surprisingly robust across demographic differences. Epistemology & Philosophy of Science 56(2), 29–36.

  • Leslie, S.J. 2008. Generics: Cognition and acquisition. Philosophical Review 117: 1–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Leslie, A.M., J. Knobe, and A. Cohen. 2006. Acting intentionally and the side-effect effect: Theory of mind and moral judgment. Psychological Science 17 (5): 421–427.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery, E., and Stich, S. 2019. Demographic differences in philosophical intuition: A reply to Joshua Knobe. Unpublished manuscript.

  • Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Chatterjee, A., Karasawa, K., Struchiner, N., ..., and Hashimoto, T. 2017a. Gettier across cultures 1. Noûs 51(3):645–664.

  • Machery, E., Stich, S., Rose, D., Alai, M., Angelucci, A., Berniūnas, R., ..., and Cohnitz, D. 2017b. The gettier intuition from South America to Asia. Journal of Indian Council of Philosophical Research 34(3):517–541.

  • May, J., W. Sinnott-Armstrong, J.G. Hull, and A. Zimmerman. 2010. Practical interests, relevant alternatives, and knowledge attributions: An empirical study. Review of Philosophy and Psychology 1 (2): 265–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Michelin, C., S. Pellizzoni, M.A. Tallandini, and M. Siegal. 2010. Evidence for the side-effect effect in young children: Influence of bilingualism and task presentation format. European Journal of Developmental Psychology 7: 641–652.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murray, D., and E. Nahmias. 2014. Explaining away incompatibilist intuitions. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 88 (2): 434–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Patil, I., Zucchelli, M. M., Kool, W., Campbell, S., Fornasier, F., Calò, M., Silani, G., Cikara, M., and Cushman, F. 2021. Reasoning supports utilitarian resolutions to moral dilemmas across diverse measures. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 120(2), 443–460.

  • Pellizzoni, S., M. Siegal, and L. Surian. 2009. Foreknowledge, caring, and the side-effect effect in young children. Developmental Psychology 45: 289–295.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, J., J. De Freitas, C. Mott, J. Gruber, and J. Knobe. 2017. True happiness: The role of morality in the folk concept of happiness. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 146 (2): 165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pinillos, Á. 2012. Knowledge, Experiments and Practical Interests. In Knowledge Ascriptions, eds. Brown and Gerken, 192–221. Oxford University Press.

  • Rakoczy, H., T. Behne, A. Clüver, S. Dallmann, S. Weidner, and M.R. Waldmann. 2015. The side-effect effect in children is robust and not specific to the moral status of action effects. PLoS ONE 10 (7): e0132933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, E., J. Shepard, and P. Rochat. 2017. Variations in judgments of intentional action and moral evaluation across eight cultures. Cognition 164: 22–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., W. Buckwalter, and S. Nichols. 2017. Neuroscientific prediction and the intrusion of intuitive metaphysics. Cognitive Science 41 (2): 482–502.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rose, D., Machery, E., Stich, S., Alai, M., Angelucci, A., Berniūnas, R., ..., and Cohnitz, D. 2019. Nothing at stake in knowledge. Noûs 53(1):224–247.

  • Samland, J., M. Josephs, M.R. Waldmann, and H. Rakoczy. 2016. The role of prescriptive norms and knowledge in children’s and adults’ causal selection. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 145 (2): 125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sarkissian, H., J. Park, D. Tien, J.C. Wright, and J. Knobe. 2011. Folk moral relativism. Mind & Language 26 (4): 482–505.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sripada, C., and J. Stanley. 2012. Empirical tests of interest-relative invariantism. Episteme 9: 3–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tasimi, A., S.A. Gelman, A. Cimpian, and J. Knobe. 2017. Differences in the evaluation of generic statements about human and non-human categories. Cognitive Science 41 (7): 19341957.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K.P. 2015. Personal identity and the Phineas Gage effect. Analysis 75 (3): 396–405.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tobia, K.P. 2016. Personal identity, direction of change, and neuroethics. Neuroethics 9 (1): 37–43.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yang, F., J. Knobe, and Y. Dunham. 2021. Happiness is from the soul: Origins of an evaluative view of happiness. Journal of Experimental Psychology: General 150: 276–288.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yuan, Y., and Kim, M. 2021 Cross-cultural convergence of knowledge attribution in East Asia and the US. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 1–28.

Download references

Acknowledgements

I am grateful to Edouard Machery and Stephen Stich for sharing an earlier draft of their reply and for helpful discussions of these issues. Thanks also to Ivar Hannikainen and Vilius Dranseika, who kindly provided detailed information on the methods and results of their studies.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joshua Knobe.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of Interest

None

Additional information

Publisher's Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor (e.g. a society or other partner) holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Knobe, J. Difference and Robustness in the Patterns of Philosophical Intuition Across Demographic Groups. Rev.Phil.Psych. 14, 435–455 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-023-00683-z

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-023-00683-z

Navigation