Skip to main content
Log in

Does perceiving require perceptual experience?

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In Section I, I clarify turning point issues in the Phillips and Block debate about whether there is unconscious perception. These include questions about whether uptake of certain visual information is an individual or person level accomplishment, as required for genuine unconscious perceiving. Section II takes up a recent reorientation proposed in Block (2017) towards the question of whether there is unconscious perceiving, where we are to look for the pervasive role of unconscious perceiving in, perhaps especially, the online control of everyday reaching and grasping. I point out that while this may well be a helpfully different approach to explore, it does not evade the central questions and challenges familiar from the prior debate between Phillips and Block. Section III reviews an approach summarized in Dehaene (2014), drawing from a range of measures of neural activity. Dehaene provides evidence of quite rich non-conscious perceptual system responses, some arguably individual or person level. But in a fairly thin or fragile way, absent taking up, in higher level assessment, the information encoded in initial visual response. Or that is the interpretation I argue for, in relating the Dehaene account to the Phillips and Block debate, in a way that illuminates the Phillips and Block discussions. An Appendix provides an overview of debates in the literature about the Goodale and Milner Two Visual Systems Hypothesis, that Block (2017) makes central appeal to.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. I will regularly shorten this to “perceptual experience”. As the “sensory” indicates, I assume that perceptual consciousness implies sensory or phenomenal consciousness. I think it will be clear that this summary framing fits the proposals made and debated by Block, Phillips, and Dehaene.

  2. This use of “perceive”, and the discussion in Sect. 3 below of “perceptual consciousness” (which of course requires perceiving or perceptual representation), doesn’t map entirely straightforwardly onto discussions in the philosophical literature of “seeing” and “perceiving”. Neither Dretske’s “non-epistemic seeing” (1969) or his “object seeing” (2007) would qualify as clear cases of perceiving—in the sense at issue and on the view I favor—because of a lack of required engagement of workspace capacities. There is perhaps a better fit of the view of (at least clear) perceptual consciousness that I favor to “dual component” accounts of perceptual experience, where perceptual judgment figures in perceptual experience (see Smith 2002, for discussion). But there are differences. For example I allow (see Sect. 3) that workspace access might be triggered by phenomenally conscious and possibly constancy involving visual responses, that do not inherently involve a perceptual taking or judgment. In Sect. 3 I also sketch an account of workspace access which involves use of working memory capacities—which are not invoked in traditional “dual component” accounts of perceptual experience.

  3. This accords with widespread discussion in philosophy of perception and mind focused on distinguishing and relating “sub personal” perceptual mechanisms and “person level” perceiving and doing—discussions not specifically addressed to the question of whether there is unconscious perception. But not everyone would agree with the assumption made here, on a natural reading of it. For example, according to Olson (1997) each of us is somehow most fundamentally a human organism or human “animal”. Where we are typically also for most of our lives persons—much as many of us pass through a period of being students (an example Olson uses in this setting). In favor of such an account Olson points to, for example, ready acceptance of familiar “there I am” exclamations in looking at pictures of a parent holding a one month old infant. If so inclined one could, I think, reframe talk of accomplishment “by the persons that we are” in keeping with such a view. Compare: as persons, we can still note “student level” accomplishments as the students some of us also are.

  4. Block (2020) objects to the Chalmers (1995, 1996) argument that “that although phenomenal consciousness and access consciousness are metaphysically distinct, they are nomologically correlated, i.e. correlated as a consequence of laws of nature” (this is Block’s summary). But the Chalmers argument aims to establish that functional organization is nomologically correlated with phenomenology. I’m just here observing that access consciousness—at least in the “actual access” sense—is good reason to think that a creature (at least or especially a human person) is in a phenomenally conscious state because of how their psychologies are ordinarily constituted, leaving aside whether this requires an apt kind of biological make up.

  5. See Phillips (2018b), where the opening explanation of the “access hypothesis” for phenomenal consciousness is stated in terms of (“direct”) availability. But then there is subsequent discussion of particular views that conceive of access in terms of some form of actual access. And in the same article Phillips also says that “The access hypothesis corresponds to the claim that only mobilized information…is conscious”. That said, while some of the framing could mislead, the clear aim of the arguments given in Phillips (2018b) is to establish that it is an open question whether actual access is required for phenomenal consciousness.

  6. The Phillips claim that unconscious perception remains an open possibility even without contact with “central coordinating agency” is briefly made, and raises questions. Elsewhere Phillips objects that certain proposed examples of unconscious perception fail to be person level achievements because they don’t involve needed contact with “central coordinating agency”/global workspace capacities (see later this section as well as Sect. 3 below). This suggests that if there is unconscious perception, contact must be made to workspace capacities. As discussed in the text, it is then a fairly short step to the conclusion that sensory consciousness is guaranteed, at least as a matter of causal fixing. Phillips may be best read here as rejecting the idea that requirements for perception are to be determined entirely by a priori reflection, as opposed to relying on careful study of the explanatory commitments of empirical research on perceiving and acting—with the central questions about perceiving thereby remaining open to the results of ongoing empirical inquiry. Difficult questions of methodology are raised here (part 1 of Phillips, 2018a, is a relevant discussion).

  7. See Phillips (2018a) for brief explanation of “d-prime” and related signal detection terms and methods. The main line of the discussion in the text should be clear without any knowledge of basic signal detection theory and methods. Just, for example, think of the different tasks indicated. For a yes/no task, setting a “biased”, “conservative”, “high criterion” is to take a cautious attitude, only responding “yes (there is a stimulus present)” when more information has accumulated than is really necessary. There is sometimes independent evidence that subjects with neurological deficits do just this (see Phillips, 2018, 2020, 2021, for discussion; blindsight patients may also not exhibit perceptual constancy—see the summary by Phillips in P&B, 2016, p 166, and Phillips 2021, for longer discussion). By contrast, in a forced choice test—“was it an O or an X, pick one or the other”—a biased, conservative, high criterion strategy of the foregoing kind isn’t available. Subjects are forced to choose one answer or the other, even if they protest that they can’t see the stimuli (perhaps because of a cautious/conservative high criterion).

  8. Confusion is possible here. We know by Fourier analysis that 2D images can be represented by sums of sine wave gratings. Such an analysis can be used to represent scene visual information. It might be, and has been, proposed that human perceivers perform such an analysis. Individual such gratings might, as well, prove useful, precisely controllable stimuli in certain research settings—for example in studying orientation discrimination and perceptual adaptation (as in the He and MacLeod study). But in viewing ordinary scenes, gratings of various frequencies are not physically present, separable, detectable elements in the stimulus image.

  9. Block (2017, p 8) has “There is strong evidence that size constancy is registered in V1, independently of feedback from higher areas”. The Murray et al. (2006) fmri study provides support for the first part of this assertion; Burbeck (1987) and Bennett and Warren (2002) provide some additional indirect support (see also Bennett 2020). But it isn’t clear how these studies bear on whether any engagement of V1 in registering size constancy is independent of “feedback from higher areas”.

  10. This is a prominent lab and project and so appropriately cited in this context. I am not endorsing the thesis that Gabor patches and the like are likely stereo matching primitives.

  11. The stereo case is more complex than suggested here, as outside of the region in which images are fused double images are present under two-eye viewing and can carry useable information (Howard and Rogers 1995). The point in the text holds of regions of the viewed scene in which the left and right eye images are fused.

  12. Bennett and Foo (2010) contains a crisp summary of the Goodale and Milner Two Visual Systems Hypothesis; Milner and Goodale (2008) and Goodale (2013) helpfully explain the view and its basis; Franz and Gergenfurtner (2008) and Briscoe and Schwenkler (2015), summarize and press empirically backed worries. The Appendix below discusses some key results, observations, and areas of ongoing inquiry in debates in the literature about the Goodale and Milner Two Visual Systems Hypothesis.

  13. The wording in Deheane et al. (2017) suggests a similar ambivalence. Evidence for pervasive, function serving “unconscious computations” is reviewed. But it is only with “global availability of information” that there is held to be “conscious perception” (see the chart on page 46). However, this is compatible with the view that other responses qualify as “unconscious perception”. This is hinted at in the same paper in describing unconscious “perceptual computations”, that include “invariant face recognition”.

  14. Dehaene thus requires actual access to high level cognizing for sensory-phenomenal consciousness. (Though in places he is not quite completely dismissive of the possibility of pre actual access phenomenal consciousness; cf., Dehaene, Lau, and Kouider, 2017, p 54.) He uses the term “preconscious” for states that are “potentially accessible yet not accessed” (Dehaene et al. 2006, p 204.) For our purposes, we can remain neutral on whether certain related specific proposals should be included as elements of an elaborated actual access account of sensory-phenomenal consciousness. For example, it might be held that attention of some kind to properties or scene elements is required—and so, with this, facilitation of high level processing of the visual coding of the scene elements attended to. Dehaene holds that attention is thus required, although not sufficient (Dehaene et al. 2006). Some, further, argue that a higher level representation of one’s visual responses or codings is required for phenomenal consciousness, whether in the form of a judgment or an ‘inner sense’ perception (see Block 2020, chapter 13, for a discussion of the different forms such higher order accounts of the first kind—involving higher order thought—can take). A view of this kind might also be fit to an actual access account. Such higher order requirements on sensory or phenomenal consciousness have been strongly criticized (cf., Dretske 1993, 1995; Block 2011,2020). In my view appropriately. But see Carruthers (2016) for a helpful overview discussion by someone sympathetic to a higher order thought account of visual or perceptual consciousness.

  15. Block (2007, 2020) is somewhat cautious about whether feedback to V1 is needed for visual experience, as opposed to only feedback to other, still “lower”, visual areas.

  16. For helpful treatment of key ideas see Hill’s (2009, pp 15–18) discussion of the two conceptions of “access consciousness” in work by Block (Block 1995, 2002, 2020), as well as his own related notion of “experiential consciousness”. In speaking of “access consciousness” (explicitly or implicitly) in the text I mean to include the Hill “experiential consciousness”—which is a wider category than the Block “access consciousness” notions in not requiring the accessed or accessible states to have representational content, and in invoking a larger, more diverse range of higher level mental capacities. Hill would opt for “accessible” here, against Block’s more recent views. Block suggests that his move to a characterization in terms of actual access reflects a move from “characterizing a strand of ordinary thinking” towards “characterizing an information-processing image” of the ordinary role of phenomenally conscious states (Block 2019, p 538). See also Stoljar (2019), who stresses that on an early (“accessibility”) Block version of access consciousness the idea is framed in terms of representations “poised” for—somehow on the verge of—engaging higher level cognizing and action (Block, 1994, introduces appeal to ‘poise’); Block (2019) is a reply to Stoljar (2019).

  17. Our question here is what sort of contact with higher level capacities is required for the person level achievement of perceiving--allowing, with Block, for pre actual access sensory-phenomenal consciousness. Dehaene frames his proposals as accounts of consciousness, and holds there is no pre actual access consciousness of any sort. For present purposes we can examine the Dehaene proposals as concerning the kind of contact with higher level capacities allowing the person level achievement of perceiving, though that’s not how Dehaene frames the proposals.

  18. Some more detailed characterizations are more in line with the point here. For example, “On top of a deep hierarchy of specialized modules, a ‘global neuronal workspace’ (GNW) with limited capacity, evolved to select a piece of information, hold it over time, and share it across modules. We call ‘conscious’ whichever representation, at a given time, wins the competition for access to this mental arena and gets selected for global sharing and decision-making” (Dehaene, Lau, Kouider, 2017). However, this language is still misleading: actual “global sharing” and actual contribution to decisions made is not required in order to perceive the world, at least if this involves high level reasoning. In the presentation of the GNW framework in a recent detailed assessment of relevant research (Mashour et al. 2020) the commitment, as requirement, to a mix of actual access to working memory resources and resulting availability is clearer. It is indeed stressed that “the relationship between attention, working memory, and conscious awareness is complex and warrants careful consideration”(p 783)—where the subsequent discussion of relevant research indicates that our references in the text to “working memory” are importantly simplified.

  19. Haffenden and Goodale (2000) and Haffenden et al. (2001) propose that the remaining effect on the MGA (action) measure, suggesting a role played by the illusory experience, is actually an artifact of aspects of the (Ebbinghaus) stimuli that result in obstacle avoidance shaping of the hand and fingers. However, Franz et al. (2003) present evidence against such a non-experiential, obstacle avoidance, explanation (further discussed in Franz and Gergenfurtner, 2008).

  20. Franz (2003, p 476) suggests that the Goodale and Milner two visual systems proposal might be reconciled with this conclusion by maintaining that the Ebbinghaus illusion derives from visual system response preceding a split into the two, perception vs. action, streams. In a somewhat different context Franz and Gegenfurtner (2008, p 935) cite the Murray et al. (2006) fmri evidence implicating V1 in achieving size constancy. However, on this proposal it isn’t clear what would be left of a perception vs. action two visual systems scheme, since both perception and action would be informed by the same visual representation of (at least) size.

References

  • Andersen, R. A., K. N. Andersen, E. J. Hwang, and M. Hauschild. 2014. Optic ataxia: from Balint’s syndrome to the parietal reach area. Neuron 82 (5): 967–983.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bennett, D.J. & Warren, W. (2002). Size scaling: Retinal or environmental frame of reference? Perception & Psychophysics, 64 (3), 462–477.

  • Bennett, D.J. (2009). Varieties of visual perspectives. Philosophical Psychology, 22 (3), 329–352.

  • Bennett, D.J. & Foo, P. (2010). Mid-Range Action-Driving Visual Information and the Milner and Goodale “Two Visual Systems” Hypothesis. Psyche.

  • Bennett, D.J. (2016). The role of spatial appearances in gaining spatial-geometric perceptual constancy. Philosophical Topics, 44 (2), 1–42.

  • Bennett, D.J. (2020). Are V1 Scotomas Visual Angle Deficits? Ms.

  • Biederman, I. 1981. On the semantics of a glance at a scene. In Perceptual organization, eds. M. Kubovy, and J. R. Pomerantz, 213–263. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Binds, P., and S. Murray. 2015. Keeping a large-pupilled eye on high-level visual processing. Trends in Cognitive Science 19 (1): 1–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 1995. On a Confusion about a Function of Consciousness. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 18: 227–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2002. Concepts of Consciousness. In David ]. Chalmers (ed.), Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings, 206–218.

  • Block, N. 2005. Two neural correlates of consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 9 (2): 46–52.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2007. Consciousness, accessibility, and the mesh between psychology and neuroscience. Behavioral and Brain Sciences 30: 481–548.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2011. The higher-order approach to consciousness is defunct. Analysis 71: 419–431.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2012. The grain of vision and the grain of attention. Thought 1: 170–184.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2013. Seeing and windows of integration. Thought 2: 29–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2016. The Anna Karenina principle and skepticism about unconscious perception. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XCIII: 2, 452–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Block, N. 2017. Does unconscious perception really exist? Neuroscience of Consciousness, 3 (1).

  • Block, N. 2019. Poise, dispositions, and access consciousness: Reply to Daniel Stoljar. In A. Pautz and D. Stoljar (Eds.) Blockheads! Essays on Ned Block’s Philosophy of Mind and Consciousness, 537–544. MIT Press.

  • Block, N. January 2020. The Border Between Seeing and Thinking. Book ms.

  • Brascamp, J., R. Blake, and T. Knapen. 2015. Negligible fronto-parietal BOLD activity accompanying unreportable switches in bistable perception. Nature Neuroscience 18 (11): 1672–1678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bridgeman, Kirch, Sperling. 1981. Segregation of cognitive and motor aspects of visual function using induced motion. Perception & Psychophysics 29 (4): 336–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R., and J. Schwenkler. 2015. Conscious Vision in Action. Cognitive Science 39: 1435–1467.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burbeck, C. 1987. Locus of spatial-frequency discrimination. Journal of the Optical Society of America A: 4, 1807–1813.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 2009. Primitive Agency and Natural Norms. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 74: 251–278.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burge, T. 2010. The Origins of Objectivity. OUP.

  • Carey, D. P., H. C. Dijkerman, and A. D. Milner. 1998. Perception and action in depth. Consciousness and Cognition 7: 438–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P. 2016. Higher-order theories of consciousness. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

  • Castiello, U., Y. Paulignan, and M. Jeannerod. 1991. Temporal dissociation of motor responses and subjective awareness a study in normal subjects. Brain 114: 2639–2655.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cesanek, E., C. Campagnoli, J. A. Taylor, and F. Domini. 2018. Does visuo-motor adaptation contribute to illusion-resistant grasping? Psychonomic Bulletin Review 25: 827–845.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 1995. Absent Qualia, Fading Qualia, Dancing Qualia. In (Ed) T. Metzinger, Conscious Experience. Academic Imprint.

  • Chalmers, D. 1996. The Conscious Mind: In Search of a Fundamental Theory. OUP.

  • Dehaene, S. 2014. Consciousness and the Brain. Penguin.

  • Dehaene, S., J.-P. Changeux, L. Naccache, J. Sackur, and C. Sergent. 2006. Conscious, preconscious, and subliminal processing: A testable taxonomy. Trends in Cognitive Science 10 (5): 204–211.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deheane, S., H. Lau, and S. Kouider. 2017. What is consciousness, and could have it? Science 358 (6362): 486–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dijkerman, H. C., A. D. Milner, and D. P. Carey. 1998. Grasping spatial relationships: Failure to demonstrate allocentric visual coding in a patient with visual form agnosia. Consciousness and Cognition 7: 424–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1969. Seeing and Knowing. University of Chicago Press.

  • Dretske, F. 2007. What change blindness teaches about consciousness. Philosophical Perspectives 21: 215–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1993. Conscious experience. Mind 102: 263–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dretske, F. 1995. Naturalizing the Mind. MIT Press.

  • Felleman, D. J., and D. C. Van Essen. 1991. Distributed hierarchical processing in the primate cerebral cortex. Cerebral Cortex, 1–17.

  • Fisch, L., E. Privman, M. Ramot, M. Harel, Y. Nir, S. Kipervasser, and F. Andelman, et al. 2009. Neural ‘ignition’: Enhanced activation linked to perceptual awareness in human ventral stream visual cortex. Neuron 64 (4): 562–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H. 2003. Manual size estimation: a neurophysiological measure of perception? Experimental Brain Research 151: 471–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V. H., H. H. Bulthoff, and M. Fahle. 2003. Grasp effects of the Ebbinghaus illusion: Obstacle avoidance is not the explanation. Experimental Brain Research 149: 470–477.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Franz, V., and K. Gegenfurtner. 2008. Grasping visual illusions: Consistent data and no dissociation. Cognitive Neuropsychology 25: 920–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Green, E. J., and J. Quilty-Dunn. 2017. What is an object file? British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 72(3).

  • Goodale, M. A. 2013. Visual control of action. In The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Neuroscience, Volume 1: Core Issues, eds. K. N. Ochsner, and S. A. Kosslyn, 273–295. OUP.

  • Haffenden, A. M., and M. A. Goodale. 2000. Independent effects of pictorial displays on perception and action. Vision Research 40: 1597–1607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haffenden, A. M., K. C. Schiff, and M. A. Goodale. 2001. The dissociation between perception and action in the Ebbinghaus illusion: Nonillusory effects of pictorial cues on grasp. Current Biology 11: 177–181.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haefner, R. M., and B. G. Cumming. 2008. Adaptation to natural binocular disparities in primate V1 explained by a generalized energy model. Neuron 57 (1): 147–158.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • He, S., and D. MacLeod. 2001. Orientation selective adaptation and tilt after-effect from invisible patterns. Nature 411: 473–476.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, C., K. Ball, and T. Schenk. 2012. Visuomotor performance based on peripheral vision is impaired in the visual form agnostic patient DF. Neuropsychologia 50: 90–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hill, C. 2009. Consciousness. O.U.P.

  • Howard, I., and B. Rogers. 1995. Binocular Vision and Stereopsis. O.U.P.

  • Jiang, Y. V., P. Costello, F. Fang, M. Huang, and S. He. 2006. A gender and sexual orientation dependent spatial attentional effect of invisible images. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, 103(45), 17048–17052.

  • Kesner, R. P., and S. H. Creem-Regehr. 2013. Parietal contributions to spatial cognition. In Handbook of Spatial Cognition, eds. D. Waller, and L. Nadel, 35–63. American Psychological Association.

  • Kravitz, D. J., K. S. Salem, C. I. Baker, and M. Mishkin. 2011. A new framework for visuospatial processing. Nature Reviews 12: 217–230.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Livingston, M., and D. Hubel. 1988. Segregation of form, color, movement, and depth: Anatomy, physiology, and perception. Science 240: 740–749.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacEvoy, S., and M. Paradiso. 2001. Lightness constancy in primary visual cortex. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, USA, 98, 8827–31.

  • Marotta, J. J., M. Behrmann, and M. A. Goodale. 1997. The removal of binocular cues disrupts the calibration of grasping in patients with visual form agnosia. Experimental Brain Research 116: 113–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mashour, G. A., P. Roelfsema, J. P. Changuex, and S. Deheane. 2020. Conscious processing and the global neuronal workspace hypothesis. Neuron 105: 776–788.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Milner, D., and M. Goodale. 2008. Two visual systems re-viewed. Neuropsychologia 46: 774–785.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, J. S., A. Ohman, and R. J. Dolan. 1998. Conscious and unconscious emotional learning in the human amygdala. Nature 393 (6684): 467–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Morris, J. S., A. Ohman, and R. J. Dolan. 1999. A subcortical pathway to the right amygdala mediating ‘unseen’ fear.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 96 (4): 1680–85.

  • Murray, S., H. Boyaci, and D. Kersten. 2006. The representation of perceived angular size in human primary visual context. Nature Neuroscience 9: 429–434.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nassi, J. J., and E. M. Callaway. 2009. Parallel processing strategies of the primate visual system. Nature Reviews Neuroscience 10: 360–372.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oliva, A., and A. Torralba. 2007. The role of context in object recognition. Trends in Cognitive Sciences 11 (12): 520–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Olson, E. 1997. The Human Animal: Personal Identity Without Psychology. New York: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I., and N. Block. 2016. Debate on unconscious perception. In Current Controversies in Philosophy of Perception, ed. B. Nanay, 165–192. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. 2016. Consciousness and criterion; On Block’s case for unconscious seeing. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research XCIII: 419–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. 2017. What do we need to think about when we think of unconscious perception? Neuroscience of Consciousness, 3 (1).

  • Phillips, I. 2018a. Unconscious perception reconsidered. Analytic Philosophy 59 (4): 471–514.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phillips, I. 2018b. The methodological puzzle of phenomenal consciousness. Phil. Trans. R. Soc. B, 373.

  • Phillips, I. 2020. Making sense of blindsense: A commentary on Garric et al. 2019. Cortex, 127, 388–392.

  • Phillips, I. 2021. Blindsight is qualitatively degraded conscious vision. Psychological Review.

  • Pisella, L., H. Grea, C. Tilikete, A. Vighetto, M. Desmurget, G. Rode, D. Boisson, and Y. Rossetti. 2000. An ‘automatic pilot’ for the hand in posterior parietal cortex: toward reinterpreting optic ataxia. Nature Neuroscience 3 (7): 729–736.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schenk, T. 2010. Visuomotor robustness is based on integration not segregation. Vision Research 50: 2627–2632.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sergent, C., S. Baillet, and S. Dehaene. 2005. Timing of the brain events underlying access to consciousnesses during the attentional blink. Nature Neuroscience 8 (10): 1391–1400.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Silvato, J., N. Lavie, and V. Walsh. 2005. Double dissociation of V1 and V5/MT activity in visual awareness. Cerebral Cortex 15: 1736–1741.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. D. 2002. The Problem of Perception. Harvard University Press.

  • Stoljar, D. 2019. In praise of poise. In A. Pautz and D. Stoljar (Eds.) Blockheads! Essays on Ned Block’s Philosophy of Mind and Consciousness, 5511–536. MIT Press.

  • Ungerleider, L. G., and M. Mishkin. 1982. Two cortical visual systems. In Analysis of Visual Behavior, eds. D. J. Ingle, M. A. Goodale, and R. J. W. Mansfield, 548–586. MIT Press.

  • Van den Bussche, E., K. Notebaert, and B. Reynvoet. 2009. Masked primes can be genuinely semantically processed. Journal of Experimental Psychology 56 (5): 295–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van Gaal, S., L. Naccache, J. D. I. Meeuwese, A. M. van Loon, L. Cohen, and S. Dehaene. 2014. Can multiple words be integrated unconsciously? Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B Biological Sciences, 369.

  • Van Essen, D. C. 2004. Organization of visual areas in macaque and human visual cortex. In The Visual Neurosciences, eds. I. M. Chalupa, and J. S. Werner, 507–521. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Warren, W. H. 2006. The dynamics of perception and action. Psychological Review 113: 358–389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watson, G. 1975. Free Agency. Journal of Philosophy 72: 205–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wu, W. 2014. Against division: Consciousness, information, and the visual streams. Mind and Language 29 (4): 383–406.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zipser, K., V. A. Lamme, and P. Schiller. 1996. Contextual modification in primary visual cortex. Journal of Neuroscience 16 (22): 7376–7389.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for acute comments.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David John Bennett.

Ethics declarations

Conflict of interest

None.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Bennett, D.J. Does perceiving require perceptual experience?. Rev.Phil.Psych. 14, 763–790 (2023). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-022-00620-6

Download citation

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-022-00620-6

Navigation