Skip to main content
Log in

Different Kinds of Fusion Experiences

  • Published:
Review of Philosophy and Psychology Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Some people have stressed that there is a close analogy between meaning experiences, i.e., experiences as of understanding concerning linguistic expressions, and seeing-in experiences, i.e., pictorial experiences of discerning a certain item – what a certain picture presents, viz. the picture’s subject – in another item – the picture’s vehicle, the picture’s physical basis. Both can be seen as fusion experiences, in the minimal sense that they are experiential wholes made up of different aspects. Actually, two important similarities between such experiences may lead one to think that they are experiences of the same type. In this paper, however, I will try to show that notwithstanding such similarities, these experiences are typologically different. For there are two dissimilarities between such experiences that are more relevant on this typological concern than their similarities. Indeed, unlike meaning experiences, seeing-in experiences are first of all recognitional experiences of a sort that makes them perceptual experiences (though sui generis) as well. Moreover, again unlike meaning experiences, seeing-in experiences are fusion experiences in the substantial sense that the experiential whole is more than the sum of its experiential parts taken in isolation, for when such parts figure in that whole, they interact with each other. In a nutshell, unlike meaning experiences, seeing-in experiences are proper fusion experiences.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. In this paper, I will assume that what the picture presents coincides with its subject, taken as what the picture is about. Actually, this assumption is rightly controversial. See fn. 9.

  2. Husserl (2006) holds a similar idea as regards the relationship in pictorial experience between its experiential component that concerns what he calls the image-object – again, what the picture presents (which for him differs from the picture’s subject, taken as what the picture is about) – and the experiential component concerning the picture’s vehicle (cf. Eldridge 2018).

  3. Some people oppose this claim, by holding that what one sees in the altered shot is rather a black-and-white subject matter: Husserl (2006), Nanay (2016, 2018). For some reasons against this opposition, cf. Voltolini (2018); see also below.

  4. I do not want to deny that grasping a certain morphosyntactic structure in a (meaningless) expression goes along with grasping a structural form of meaning for it, as all philosophers of language endorsing a Chomskyan attitude as to meaning matters maintained. By hearing the meaningless Jabberwocky-like sentence “the mome raths the borogrove”, someone competent in English certainly grasps that something did something to something else. Yet she grasps neither the lexical meaning of its constituent expressions nor their truthconditional contribution, for there is none.

  5. One might remark that this argument is simply based on introspective evidence. In one sense, this remark is correct. The argument is based on two cases of phenomenal contrast – the contrast between the auditory experience of a meaningless yet morphosyntactically articulated expression and the experience of that expression as endowed with a certain meaning, and the contrast between an expression in a certain morphosyntactic articulation and that expression in another such articulation – and sometimes at least, phenomenal contrast cases rely on introspection (Chudnoff 2015:56). Yet in another sense, the remark is incorrect. For the second case of phenomenal contrast simply serves to show that, as regards a meaning experience, its first aspect is identical to the auditory experience of an expression in a certain morphosyntactic articulation taken in isolation; in other words, that such an experience is unaltered by figuring as an aspect of a meaning experience. As we will immediately see, this is not the case with the perception of a picture’s vehicle qua mere physical object and the perception of it qua pictorial vehicle, i.e., the CF of a seeing-in experience.

  6. Clearly enough, in order to so see the vehicle pictorially as it were, one must take a certain vantage point, as anamorphoses clearly show. But this is another issue.

  7. One might legitimately wonder whether this is always the case. What about sculptorial seeing-in, in which since the vehicle is already 3D one must not project depth on it? One might say that one threedimensionally organizes the sculture’s vehicle without seeing anything in it. Yet even in that case, the proper visual grouping affecting the 3D elements of the vehicle as a sculpture’s vehicle in the CF of the relevant seeing-in experience enables the vision of that vehicle to be suitably modified, so that another 3D scene emerges in it as grasped in the RF of that seeing-in experience. This may be easily captured in Luca Patella’s Vasa physiognomica, a 3D sculptorial instance of the Rubin’s vase. In order for one to see a 3D ‘facial’ organization as protruding out of a receding 3D background organization, so that in a 3D vase and its surrounding space one sees two faces in profile as standing out of a background, one must suitably rearrange visually that vase and that space.

  8. On this difference between the Kanizsa case and the Dalmatian case (and the fact that cognitive penetration is necessary for the nonpictorial and the pictorial reading respectively), cf. Zeimbekis 2015.

  9. Pace Wittgenstein, who once said that meaning is a physiognomy (Wittgenstein 2009:§ 568).

  10. If one distinguishes what a picture presents from its subject, once this is taken as what a picture is about (Husserl 2006, Nanay 2016, 2018; Voltolini 2015, 2018), one cannot read off from the picture’s vehicle properly threedimensionally organized what that picture is about, even if this is constrained by what the picture presents. Indeed, a picture may present the same scene, hence its seeing-in experience still mobilizes the same RF (and also the same CF), and yet be possibly or actually about different things compatible with that scene. This makes the picture not perceptually, but merely representationally ambiguous (Wiesing 2010; Voltolini 2015). For example, by still seeing in it the very same serious man in a hieratic pose, an incompetent audience may take Piero’s fresco of St. Louis de Toulouse as being about Michael Schumacher, the former F1 pilot, instead as being about St. Louis. Or a snapshot of Alan Parker’s Evita, in which one sees an elegant lady on a certain background, may count both as a picture of Madonna, the actress playing the role of Evita Peron in that movie, and as a picture of Evita herself. But for the purposes of this paper I leave this point aside.

  11. Granted, one might wonder whether there is a sui generis cognitive phenomenology, or whether that phenomenology can be reduced to a kind of sensuous phenomenology (Carruthers and Vellet 2011; Prinz 2011; Tye and Wright 2011). If this were the case, one might surmise that the phenomenology of a meaning experience remains perceptual. Yet, there may be different meaning experiences of one and the same lexically ambiguous expression such that not only that expression remains auditorily experienced in the same way as far as its morphosyntactic identity is concerned, as we saw before, but also it involves the same mental imagery. For more on this, cf. Martina and Voltolini (2017).

  12. I owe this example to an anonymous referee.

  13. As regards the picture’s vehicle, Husserl (2006) shares this idea: in picture perception but not in its perception per se, the vehicle is seen as a pictorial vehicle. Cf. Eldridge (2018).

  14. In Voltolini (2015), I provide an argument as to why this is the case. Only in the RF, but not in the face-to-face vision of the picture’s subject, one needs a conceptual content. For one needs to perceptually distinguish that subject from a different item, i.e., the picture’s vehicle, which in the CF of the relevant seeing-in experience one co-locates where, in the RF, one knowingly illusorily sees that subject.

References

  • Bantinaki, K. 2018. Stylistic deformity and pictorial experience. In The pleasure of pictures, ed. J. Pelletier and A. Voltolini, 125–143. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bayne, T., and M. Montague. 2011. Cognitive phenomenology: An introduction. In Cognitive phenomenology, ed. T. Bayne and M. Montague, 1–34. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Briscoe, R. 2018. Gombrich and the duck-rabbit. In Aspect perception after Wittgenstein: Seeing-as and novelty, ed. M. Beaney, B. Harrington, and D. Shaw, 49–88. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown, J. 2010. Seeing things in pictures. In Philosophical perspectives on depiction, ed. C. Abell and K. Bantinaki, 208–236. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carruthers, P., and B. Vellet. 2011. The case against cognitive phenomenology. In Cognitive phenomenology, ed. T. Bayne and M. Montague, 35–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. 2004. The representational character of experience. In The future of philosophy, ed. B. Leiter, 153–181. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chudnoff, E. 2015. Cognitive phenomenology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crane, T. 2001. Elements of mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dokic, J. 2012. Pictures in the flesh: Presence and appearance in pictorial experience. British Journal of Aesthetics 52: 391–405.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eldridge, P. 2018. Depicting and seeing-in. The ‘Sujet’ in Husserl’s phenomenology of images. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 17: 555–578.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferretti, G. 2018. Visual feeling of presence. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 99: 112–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gombrich, E. 1960. Art and illusion. London: Phaidon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hagberg, G. 2016. Leonardo’s challenge. Wittgenstein and Wollheim at the intersection of perception and projection. In Wollheim, Wittgenstein, and pictorial representation, ed. G. Kemp and G.M. Mras, 117–159. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. 1998. Picture, image and experience. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, R. 2008. What do we see in film? The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 66: 149–159.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 2002. Ideas: General introduction to pure phenomenology. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. 2006. Phantasy, image consciousness, memory. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jagnow, R. 2011. Ambiguous figures and the spatial contents of perceptual experience: A defense of representationalism. Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences 10: 325–346.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kriegel, U. 2015. The varieties of consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, J. 1998. Wollheim on pictorial representation. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56: 227–233.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lopes, D. 1996. Understanding pictures. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. 2012. Cognitive penetration of color experience: Rethinking the issue in light of an indirect mechanism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 84: 24–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Macpherson, F. 2015. Cognitive penetration and nonconceptual content. In The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives, ed. A. Raftopoulos and J. Zeimbekis, 331–358. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martina, G., and A. Voltolini. 2017. Perceiving groupings, experiencing meanings. Rivista di estetica 66: 22–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M. 2005. Seeing, doing, and knowing. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. 1998. In defense of modesty. In Meaning, knowledge, and reality, 87–107. Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Montague, M. 2016. The given. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. 2016. Aesthetics as philosophy of perception. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nanay, B. 2018. Threefoldness. Philosophical Studies 175: 163–182.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nes, A. 2016. On what we experience when we hear people speak. Phenomenology and Mind 10: 58–85.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’ Callaghan, C. 2011. Against hearing meanings. The Philosophical Quarterly 61: 783–807.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinker, S. 1994. The language instinct. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pitt, D. 2004. The phenomenology of cognition, or, what is it like to think that P? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 69: 1–36.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prinz, J. 2011. The sensory basis of cognitive phenomenology 1. In Cognitive phenomenology, ed. T. Bayne and M. Montague, 174–196. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schier, F. 1986. Deeper into pictures. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J.R. 1983. Intentionality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, G. 1994. Mental reality. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stumpf, C. 1890. Tonpsychologie. Vol. II. Leipzig: Hirzel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Textor, M. 2018. Apprending a multitude as a unity. In Philosophy of mind in the nineteenth century, ed. S. Lapointe, 190–213. London: Routledge.

  • Tye, M., and B. Wright. 2011. Is there a phenomenology of thought? In Cognitive phenomenology, ed. T. Bayne and M. Montague, 326–344. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voltolini, A. 2015. A syncretistic theory of depiction. Basingstoke: Palgrave.

  • Voltolini, A. 2018. Twofoldness and three-layeredness in pictorial representation. Estetika 55: 89–111.

  • Wiesing, L. 2010. Artificial presence. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1977. Remarks on colour. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 1991. Remarks on the philosophy of psychology vol. 1. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, L. 2009. Philosophical investigations. Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Wollheim, R. 1980. Art and its objects. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. 1987. Painting as an art. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Wollheim, R. 1998. On pictorial representation. The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 56: 217–226.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. 2003a. In defense of seeing-in. In Looking into pictures, ed. H. Hecht, R. Schwartz, and M. Atherton, 3–15. Cambridge MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wollheim, R. 2003b. What makes representational painting truly visual?. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society suppl. 77: 131-147.

  • Zeimbekis, J. 2015. Seeing, visualizing, and believing. Pictures and cognitive penetration. In The cognitive penetrability of perception: New philosophical perspectives, ed. A. Raftopoulos and J. Zeimbekis, 298–325. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper has been originally presented in a seminar at Institut Jean Nicod, April 4 2018, Paris, and in two other conferences: The Borders of Perception, The Van Leer Jerusalem Institute and the Hebrew University of Jerusalem, January 16-17 2018, Jerusalem; Themes from Aesthetics and Phenomenology, Department of Philosophy and Education Sciences, University of Turin, June 7 2018, Turin. I thank all the participants for their stimulating remarks. I warmly thank Giulia Martina and Elisabetta Sacchi for their detailed comments on previous version of the paper, as well as two anonymous reviewers of this Review for their helpful criticisms.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alberto Voltolini.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Voltolini, A. Different Kinds of Fusion Experiences. Rev.Phil.Psych. 11, 203–222 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00456-7

Download citation

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-019-00456-7

Keywords

Navigation