Traditionally, an argument has been considered a paradox if, and only if:

  1. (i)

    it is an apparently valid argument,

  2. (ii)

    it has apparently true premises, and

  3. (iii)

    it has an apparently false conclusion.

This view can be found, for instance, in Quine (1966, page 7), Beall & van Fraassen (2003, page 119), Priest (2006, page 9), Cave (2009, page 3), Sainsbury (2009, page 1) and Armour-Garb (2017, page 3) among many others.Footnote 1 This paper argues that the traditional characterization of the notion of paradox is too narrow — to wit, the conditions listed above are not necessary for being a paradox — and introduces an alternative proposal.

In the first section, I argue that the traditional characterization of the notion of paradox does not apply to certain kinds of arguments that are problematic in the same way as arguments that do fit the traditional characterization. Hence, the traditional characterization fails to capture whatever these two kinds of arguments have in common. Sections 2 and 3 discuss two alternative proposals to the characterization of the notion of paradox. In Section 4, I present a more general characterization of the notion of paradox that includes both the arguments that satisfy the traditional characterization and those arguments which, even if they do not satisfy it, are problematic in the same way. Finally, Section 5 contains some concluding remarks.Footnote 2

1 The Traditional Definition

Let us state again the traditional definition of the notion of paradox, henceforth ‘Definition 1’:

Definition 1

A paradox is an apparently valid argument with apparently true premises and an apparently false conclusion.

It is important to note that the sense in which ‘apparently valid’ (‘true’, ‘false’) is used in this definition is quite strong—although not as strong as declaring it valid (true, false), of course. To wit, a paradox is not an apparently valid argument in the sense that it merely seems valid, but in the sense that, declaring it invalid, implies giving up strong intuitions about logic. And the same occurs with the other conditions of the traditional characterization. Thus, the premises of a paradox are apparently true in the sense that their being not true would violate some of our core intuitions with respect to some of the concepts—either explicitly or implicitly—involved in them (and the same can be said about the apparent falsehood of the conclusion).Footnote 3 Accordingly, the sense of ‘paradox’ that I am trying to help elucidate in this paper is the technical or semi-technical sense that is usually used in the literature in philosophy of logic and language (what Quine 1966 calls ‘antinomy’). In this sense, then, a paradox points to a tension in the basic intuitions governing one or more of our concepts. That is why solving a paradox must involve giving up some of these core intuitions, all of which are, typically, equally cherished, and as a result, there is no agreement whatsoever as to which of them has to be abandoned. So the apparent validity of the argument, the apparent truth of the premises, and the apparent falsity of the conclusion are forced by the tension that arises from the concepts involved in the paradox; that is, we would be willing to state that the argument is valid, that the premises are true and that the conclusion is false but since this is, in principle, impossible, we are forced to declare these properties as apparent.Footnote 4

I want to show next that Definition 1 is too narrow. I will offer two arguments that I claim can reasonably be considered paradoxes but that do not satisfy Definition 1. The first counterexample to Definition 1 I want to consider is Curry’s paradox.Footnote 5 It can be presented concisely as follows.

Suppose that T is the truth predicate and that it obeys the so called ‘T-schema’, according to which, for any sentence ϕ, \(T\ulcorner \phi \urcorner \leftrightarrow \phi \).Footnote 6 Suppose, furthermore, that we have a Curry sentence γ, which is a sentence that asserts that if itself is true then snow is white:

$$ (\gamma) T\ulcorner\gamma\urcorner\to \text{snow is white} $$

Suppose, now, that \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \). Then, under this supposition, what γ says is the case; to wit, if \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \) then snow is white. We can apply next modus ponens and conclude, under the assumption that \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \), that snow is white. Since we have concluded that snow is white under the supposition that \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \), we can now conclude that if \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \), then snow is white. So we just proved γ itself and, hence, \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \). At this point, then, we have the following two claims: first, that if \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \), then snow is white; and, second, that \(T\ulcorner \gamma \urcorner \). From these, applying modus ponens again, we conclude that snow is white.

This is, roughly put, how Curry’s Paradox allows us to conclude the consequent of γ; thus, in this particular case, it allows us to conclude that snow is white. Notice now that according to Definition 1, the argument provided by Curry’s reasoning with the use of γ is not a paradox, for the conclusion obtained is not false. I claim that this argument, though, is a paradox. Let me elaborate on that.

In general, Curry’s Paradox can be presented with a variable ϕ ranging over sentences in the position of ‘snow is white’ in γ; then, it would not have been a proper argument, but a schema whose instances would have been arguments. Independently of the interpretation of the sentence variable in Curry’s sentence, all instances of the schema would have been paradoxes. But, since ϕ could have been a true sentence, we conclude that we will have paradoxes, like the one mentioned above, with true conclusions. Hence, paradoxes like these are counterexamples to Definition 1.

At this point, there is a natural rejoinder that a proponent of Definition 1 could give in response to Curry’s paradox. A defender of Definition 1 could say that when we use a certain sentence ϕ to formulate Curry’s paradox the unacceptable conclusion we achieve is not ϕ but that ϕ logically follows from the premises in the Curry’s reasoning. We would still have, then, an apparently valid argument with apparently true premises and an apparently false conclusion (namely, the claim that ϕ logically follows from the premises in Curry’s argumentation). This reply might work with true sentences like ‘snow is white’; that is, if we run Curry’s paradox with ‘snow is white’ in the Curry sentence and we conclude ‘snow is white’, we can read the paradox as concluding that ‘snow is white’ logically follows from the premises in Curry’s reasoning.Footnote 7 Since this last claim is apparently false, Definition 1 would be vindicated. But notice that, even granting that understanding of Curry’s paradox, we can also build a Curry paradox using a logically valid sentence or a true arithmetical sentence, say, ψ. Then even if we understand Curry’s paradox as having as its conclusion that ψ logically follows from its premises, this conclusion will no longer be apparently false, but plainly true; because, in the case of ψ being a valid sentence, it will logically follow from the premises in Curry’s reasoning (in fact, it will follow from any premises) and in the case where ψ is a true arithmetic sentence, since arithmetic is present in the premises to prove the Diagonal Lemma (at least in some of the ways for formulating Curry’s paradox), ψ will logically follow from them.Footnote 8

In conclusion, even assuming that some of Curry’s paradoxes can be understood in a way such that they are no longer counterexamples to Definition 1, we can still, with the use of logically valid or true arithmetical sentences, devise other Curry’s paradoxes that are.

Let us present, next, another counterexample to Definition 1 which also shows that it does not provide the necessary conditions for being a paradox. Consider, for example, the following argument, where Alice is 120 cm tall (a clear case of not being tall):

  1. 1.

    Alice is tall,

  2. 2.

    if Alice is tall, so is someone who is 1 cm shorter,

  3. 3.

    someone 1 cm shorter than Alice is tall,

  4. 4.

    if someone who is 1 cm shorter than Alice is tall, so is someone who is 2 cm shorter than Alice,

  1. 151.

    if someone who is 99 cm shorter than Alice is tall, so is someone who is 100 cm shorter than Alice,

  2. 152.

    hence, someone who is 100 cm shorter than Alice is tall.

According to Definition 1, this is not a paradox; for it would only be a paradox, a Sorites paradox,Footnote 9 in situations where Alice was, say, 200 cm, as, then, the premises would be apparently true and the conclusion (that someone who is 100 cm is tall) would be apparently false. My point is that, even when Alice is not tall, the argument is still a paradox (see the discussion below on the paradox/pathodox distinction). Hence, once again, we conclude that the conditions stated in Definition 1 are not necessary for being a paradox. Notice that counterexamples of the soritical kind, such as Argument 1, are the strongest ones that can be raised against Definition 1 and, accordingly, they are perhaps also the least plausible ones. As a matter of fact, though, I think other weaker (and more plausible) soritical counterexamples can be presented. Let us see how.

As a number of authors note (see, especially, Barnes 1982, page 30), in order to construct a Sorites paradox with a given vague predicate P, it is sufficient to have an ordered series of objects a1, a2,…an such that Pa1, ¬Pan and such that all adjacent objects in the series must be related by the tolerance relation (see Wright 1975, page 333); that is, for each 0 ≤ i < n, ai and ai+ 1 must be indiscriminable with respect to the application of P. What I am claiming is that although these conditions are sufficient for having a paradox, they are not necessary, as we can still have a paradox when ¬Pa1 and ¬Pan (and, indeed, when Pa1 and Pan). We can even construct a series of objects a1, a2,…an respecting the tolerance relation as above such that Pa1, Pan and ¬Pam, where 1 < m < n. In this case, the corresponding Sorites argument would begin with the true claim that a1 is P; it would, then, argue the false claim that am is P; and, it would end with the true conclusion that an is P. Hence, this argument would not fit the traditional characterization of a paradox, for it would have a true conclusion, in spite of the fact that its paradoxical character is hard to deny (cf. Oms & Zardini 2019a, fn. 14).Footnote 10

At this point, the natural rejoinder in defense of Definition 1 is that the arguments just presented (like the Curry argument, where Curry’s sentence is build using ‘snow is white’, and the Sorites argument where Alice is not tall) are not paradoxes—so that they are not valid counterexamples to Definition 1—, but something different, albeit that they are closely related to paradoxes. Let us call them, say, ‘pathodoxes’ (from pathos and doxa; arguments leading to some kind of ill-formed opinion) and let us call the arguments that fit the traditional characterization ‘traditional paradoxes’. The complaintant might go on by saying that the traditional characterization was not intended to characterize pathodoxes, but only the traditional paradoxes. As far as I can see, though, the discussion at this point is just a semantic one; if we really have to differentiate between these two notions—traditional paradoxes and pathodoxes—, then in this paper I seek a characterization of the notion that includes both, which I will call ‘paradox’. I think this project makes sense for the following reasons.

The diagnosis of the problems that a traditional paradox and an analogous pathodox pose seems to be the same, as does the solution. To wit, if somebody claims that a traditional Sorites paradox should be solved in a different way from a Sorites pathodox, we would expect some explanations as to why this should be the case, for the conceptual tensions to which both arguments give rise are the same. This means that the phenomena underlying both kinds of arguments are the same and that research involving both traditional paradoxes and pathodoxes must help enlighten the notions involved in them in the same way; hence, the importance of capturing the notion that encompasses both traditional paradoxes and pathodoxes.

To be clear, I am not claiming that pathodoxes are paradoxes because they instantiate some schemata or patterns of reasoning which are instantiated respectively by traditional versions of the paradoxes in question (as a matter of fact, I explicitly deny this claim in the next section). What I am saying is that a pathodox and an analogous traditional paradox are both problematic; there is something wrong with both of them. Moreover, the source of its problematic character seems to be the same in both cases. And, hence, it is natural to try to capture this problematic character in general for both pathodoxes and traditional paradoxes. In this paper, I want to explore some ideas regarding this general notion of paradox.

Albeit, perhaps, less persuasive, I think we can also appeal to the phenomenology of paradoxes; when we are faced with a paradox we have a characteristic feeling that there is something wrong, that is, a feeling which constitutes what it is like to be faced with a paradox, although we find it very hard to say exactly what that feeling is. This feeling is the same, for instance, with respect to any Curry case, regardless of whether the conclusion is acceptable or not. (It’s just that when the conclusion is not acceptable, this feeling might be more pressing.)Footnote 11

2 The Logical Form

One possible and, at first sight, natural alternative characterization of the notion of paradox could be stated along the following lines:

Definition 2

A paradox is an apparently valid argument whose logical form can be used to derive an apparently false conclusion from apparently true premises.

According to this definition, the pathological Sorites of Section 1 is a paradox even when Alice is tall, because an argument with the same logical form could be used to get a false conclusion from true premises. And the same with Curry’s paradox using a true sentence to build Curry’s sentence.

Definition 2, though, is too broad, for compare the following two arguments:

Argument 1

  1. 1.

    2 is a natural number,

  2. 2.

    if a number is a natural number, so it is its successor,

  3. 3.

    hence, 20564 is a natural number.

Argument 2

  1. 1.

    2 grains of sand do not form a heap,

  2. 2.

    if n grains of sand do not form a heap, neither do n + 1 grains of sand,

  3. 3.

    hence, 20564 grains of sand do not form a heap.

which have the same logical form.

Now, according to Definition 2, since Argument 2 allows us to infer an apparently false conclusion from apparently true premises and since Argument 1 and 2 share the same logical form, we should claim that Argument 1 is a paradox; but, this is not the case. Clearly, the paradoxicality of Argument 2 does not depend solely on its logical form, but also on certain properties of the vague predicate ‘heap’.

At this point, an advocate of Definition 2 might try to argue that, in this case, there is a broader notion of form involved, which takes into account the vagueness of ‘heap’. Then, she would argue, the stipulation that the predicate used in the argument is vague should be understood as an intrinsic part of its form, in which case Arguments 1 and 2 would no longer have the same form. There are at least two problems with this line of thought. First, such an account of what a paradox is would presuppose a conception of vagueness that should be prior to its susceptibility to soritical arguments and, second, we would need to characterize the notion of form in question, which seems far from simple.Footnote 12

3 A First Attempt

Another way out of this situation has been proposed by López de Sa and Zardini (2007):

Definition 3

What really seems to be of the essence [of a paradox] is that, despite the apparent validity of the argument, the premises do not appear rationally to support the conclusion. (López de Sa & Zardini 2007, page 67)Footnote 13

This definition, though, is unclear in a way that could result in it, once again, being too broad. Consider the following argument:Footnote 14

Zebra Argument

  1. 1.

    This is a zebra,

  2. 2.

    if this is a zebra, then it is not a cleverly disguised mule,

  3. 3.

    hence, this is not a cleverly disguised mule.

In some reasonable sense of ‘not rationally supporting’, the Zebra Argument just introduced is a valid argument (it is an instance of modus ponens) such that the premises do not appear rationally to support the conclusion. This argument is a prototypical case of an argument that begs the question. It seems that the Zebra Argument begs the question because someone who does not accept the conclusion 3 will deny the evidence that supports 1—for instance, someone who thinks, precisely, that what seems a zebra is a disguised mule.Footnote 15

What I wish to stress here is that if we understand the notion of not rationally supporting as something on the lines of not giving the right kind of reason—which is usually taken to be one of the features of begging the question arguments; see Sinnott-Armstrong (2012, page 179)—, something that can be typically tested in terms of not succeeding dialectically, then Definition 3 is too broad. For arguments like that of the Zebra Argument, which are not paradoxical, will count then as cases in which the premises do not rationally support the conclusion. Even more, plain circular arguments are also arguments such that the premises do not rationally support the conclusion in the sense just stated:

Circular Argument

  1. 1.

    snow is white

  2. 2.

    hence, snow is white

which means that this kind of argument would count as a paradox, too, according to this understanding of Definition 3 (with the aforementioned sense of ‘not rationally supporting’).

A proponent of Definition 3 could reply that the Zebra Argument and the Circular Argument are paradoxes, in particular, they are some kind of pathodox. It should be noticed, however, that circular arguments like the one above do not necessarily point to any tension in the concepts involved (furthermore, they do not seem to share the phenomenology of paradoxes, that is, when faced with them we do not feel the discomfort we feel when we are faced with a paradox). Let me elaborate on this in order to see why circular arguments are not, in general, pathodoxes. As we shall see, this distinction will help determine the definition of the notion of paradox I defend in this paper.

Take a pathodoxical Sorites like the ones presented in Section 1, and take, also, the Circular Argument. Notice that both are apparently valid arguments in the sense discussed before; to wit, declaring them invalid would require giving up core intuitions of the notion of logical validity. On the other hand—at least if we suppose that logic is normative; more on this below—, in each of them, in virtue of their validity, if I believe its premises I ought to believe its conclusion.Footnote 16 This can be stated in terms of commitment; in both the pathodoxical Sorites and the Circular Argument, if a subject believes the premises and believes the argument to be valid then she is committed, in virtue of the fact that she believes the premises and the fact that she believes the argument to be valid, to believe the conclusion.Footnote 17 The crucial difference between the pathodoxical Sorites and the Circular Argument is that when faced with the former I do not want to have to believe the conclusion in virtue of the fact that I believe the argument to be valid and the fact that I believe the premises; this commitment makes me uncomfortable. In contrast, in the latter case, I am willing to believe the conclusion in virtue of the fact that I believe the argument to be valid and the fact that I believe the premises; this commitment I embrace willingly. The same occurs with arguments that beg the question, such as the Zebra Argument; if I believe the premises and I accept the argument as valid, I willingly embrace the commitment to the conclusion. To my mind, the main characteristic of paradoxes and the reason of the phenomenology we associate with them is strongly related to the fact that we are not willing to accept the commitment that stems from them; this is what explains our discomfort when we are faced with a paradox. That is why we should not consider arguments like the Circular Argument or the Zebra Argument as paradoxes.

4 The Notion of Paradox

Nevertheless, the characterization provided by López de Sa and Zardini (2007) seems to follow the right track. We may try to refine it by making more precise about what is meant when it is said that in paradoxes the premises do not rationally support the conclusion.

We have seen that what differentiates traditional paradoxes and pathodoxes (to wit, paradoxes) on the one hand from question-begging and circular arguments on the other, is the fact that we are only willing to accept the commitment that follows from the apparent validity of the argument in the latter case. As a matter of fact, we can state something stronger. Consider, for instance, a pathodoxical Sorites with a false premise and a true conclusion (for example, like the one introduced at page 6, in which the true Pan is concluded through the false Pam). We have seen that, in this case, since it is still a paradox, we are not willing to accept the commitment that stems from it.

Suppose now that a given subject S who accepts the validity of the argument and the truth of the premises does not accept the truth of the conclusion. Suppose, also, that nothing is known about the conclusion, in the sense that there are no any other arguments neither in favor nor against it, so that the subject is epistemically neutral with respect to it (let us call these conditions ‘conditions of epistemic neutrality’). If we are not willing to accept the commitment that the pathodox generates, then we will not be willing to accuse S of having done anything wrong.

Consider now the following principle:

  1. C

    If there is a commitment to accept the conclusion of an argument by virtue of its validity and the acceptance of the truth of its premises, then (under conditions of epistemic neutrality) a subject who accepts the argument to be valid, the truth of the premises and does not accept the truth of the conclusion is doing something wrong.

Then, since, as we just saw, when faced with a pathodoxical Sorites we believe that a subject who accepts the argument to be valid, the truth of the premises, and does not accept the truth of the conclusion is not doing anything wrong, C implies that there is no commitment implied by the pathodoxical Sorites. This can be generalized to any paradoxical argument and, hence, any paradoxical argument is such that when we reflect on the notion of commitment and on how a subject should behave when faced with a paradox we realize that, apparently, there is no commitment to accept the conclusion in virtue of the acceptance of its validity and the acceptance of its premises (under conditions of epistemic neutrality). So, it is not only that we are not willing to accept the commitment that stems from a paradox (as we just saw), but that, apparently, there is no commitment at all!Footnote 18

Compare this situation with our discussion of traditional paradoxes and Definition 1 in Section 1. We said that, when faced with a traditional paradox we see that, although the argument is apparently valid, its premises are apparently true and its conclusion is apparently false (in the sense that denying any of these claims would involve giving up some core intuitions of either validity or some of the key notions in the argument). We saw that these must be apparent, because they are jointly impossible. At the same time, it could be claimed, since having true premises and a false conclusion is a sufficient condition for being invalid, a traditional paradox is an argument that is apparently valid and apparently invalid.

We are now in a similar situation. Traditional paradoxes and pathodoxes (to wit, paradoxes) are apparently valid arguments—and, hence, apparently, they make us commit, under conditions of epistemic neutrality, to the conclusion when we accept the validity of the argument and the truth of the premises—and, at the same time, apparently, there is no commitment at all (given the argument above involving principle C). Again, these must be apparent for they are arguably jointly impossible (see the Final Remarks though). Moreover, if generating commitment to the conclusion is a necessary feature of any valid argument, then a paradox is, as before, an argument that is apparently valid and apparently invalid.

Let us try to spell this out more clearly. The idea is that for any given set of premises Γ that imply a sentence δ in a certain argument A and any subject S the following is the case:

  1. (*)

    if S believes Γ and believes that A is valid, then S is committed (under conditions of epistemic neutrality) to believe δ.

We can then introduce the following definition of the notion of paradox:

Definition 4

A paradox is an apparently valid argument such that, apparently, (*) fails; that is, apparently, someone can believe the premises and believe that the argument is valid while not being committed (under conditions of epistemic neutrality) to the conclusion.

When faced with a paradox, we are not committed, apparently, to believe its conclusion even when, under conditions of epistemic neutrality, we believe that the argument is valid and that the premises are true.Footnote 19

Therefore, the idea underpinning Definition 4 is that when faced with a paradox there are two strong, confronting appearances that make us reconsider some of our basic intuitions of some of the concepts somehow or other involved in the paradox. On the one hand, the rules that constitute our logic lead us to consider the paradox as a valid argument. But on the other, when we reflect on the commitments that follow from our acceptance of the premises and our acceptance of the validity of the argument, we realize that, apparently, there is no commitment at all.Footnote 20 And the appearances of validity and invalidity, as in the case of Definition 1 (see the discussion at the beginning of Section 1), are forced upon us.

Definition 4, thus, can be seen as a generalization of Definition 1. In the latter case, the conclusion of the paradox was something unacceptable, typically, a contradiction. Similarly, in the former case, there also is something apparently unacceptable, namely, the fact that a certain apparently valid argument apparently does not satisfy (*). As a matter of fact, if satisfying (*) is taken as a necessary condition for being a valid argument, we are then faced, as we saw, with an uncomfortable situation: the argument is apparently valid and apparently invalid.

5 Final Remarks

Definition 4 can be seen as a generalization of Definition 1 for yet another reason. It is usually agreed that solving a traditional paradox involves one of the following options: (i) denying the validity of the argument (and explaining why it seems valid); (ii) denying the truth of some of the premises (and explaining why they seem true); or (iii) denying the falsity of the conclusion (and explaining why it seems false). As we will see, according to Definition 4, solving a paradox involves these very same options.

In order to see this, let us try to capture the essentials of the normative nature of valid arguments. In order to do so I will use what MacFarlane (2004) calls ‘bridge principles’, principles that try to connect logical facts with norms of reasoning. MacFarlane proposes an exhaustive list of such principles, but, for our purposes here it will be enough to use (a variation of) one of these bridge principles that has been endorsed by some authors for capturing the (alleged) normative nature of logic (it is adapted from Broome 1999. See also Steinberger 2020 and MacFarlane 2004). Suppose that Δ is an argument with the members of the set Γ as premises and δ as the conclusion. Then,

$$ \text{O(B}{\Gamma}\leadsto \text{B}\delta\text{)}, $$

is taken to mean that you ought to see that if it is the case that you believe the premises in Γ then it is the case that you believe the conclusion, under conditions of epistemic neutrality.

According to Definition 4, then, a paradox is an apparently valid argument with premises Γ and conclusion δ, such that, apparently,

$$ \neg\text{O(B}{\Gamma}\leadsto\text{ B}\delta\text{)} $$

We can show now what is needed to solve a paradox according to Definition 4. First, in what we will call a type 1 solution, we can show that the argument is not valid. In this case, it would be immediately explained why believing the premises does not commit you, even under conditions of epistemic neutrality, to believe the conclusion. Ideally, we should be able to explain why, pace the fact that the argument is not valid, it is apparently valid, so why we should abandon the intuitions about validity that are involved in its being apparently valid and why they are so compelling.

Alternatively, in a type 2 solution, we can defend the validity of the argument. In this case, since the argument is valid, believing the premises commits you, under conditions of epistemic neutrality, to believe the conclusion; or, more succinctly,

$$ \text{O(B} {\Gamma}\leadsto \text{ B}\delta\text{)} $$

and hence, the failure of commitment to the conclusion must be just apparent. This appearance would be prompted, according to the proponents of a type 2 solution, by the fact that we are offered a case of an argument in which the premises are apparently true and the conclusion is apparently false. The situation can be described as follows. From the fact that, apparently,

  1. 1.

    OBΓ

and, apparently,

  1. 2.

    Bδ

you conclude that, apparently,

  1. 3.

    ¬O(BΓ ⇝ Bδ)Footnote 21

What a proponent of a type 2 solution would say is that it is this inference that explains why we think that a paradox is an apparently valid argument that, apparently, does not present the expected commitment to its conclusion. Then, what type 2 solutions would show is that either 1 is not the case, and hence ¬OBΓ (because some of the premises are not true) or 2 is not the case, and hence, ¬O¬Bδ (because the conclusion is, after all, true) and, thus, we do not have to conclude 3 and, consequently, we can accept the validity of the argument. Analogously to the case of type 1 solutions, a proponent of a type 2 solution should be able to explain, ideally, why 1 (2) seems true, which will typically imply abandoning some of the core intuitions governing the concepts involved in the paradox.

This discussion has a somewhat unexpected consequence. In order to adopt a type 2 solution you need to have been confronted with a paradox that fits Definition 1 (the traditional characterization) for, if not, you will be unable to identify the truth of the premises and the falsity of the conclusion as the culprits of your impression that the paradoxical argument does not present the expected commitment to its conclusion. In other words, if you are in front of a paradox for the first time, and the paradox is one of the examples we have seen like Curry’s paradox with a true sentence in Curry’s sentence, your first impression will be to blame the logic, not the truth value of the truth-bearers involved in the argument. I think this is perfectly reasonable; it would, after all, be very difficult to blame the inductive hypothesis in a Sorites argument that proceeds, say, from true premises to a true conclusion, although we would still have the impression that there is something wrong with the argument.Footnote 22

The second question I wish to address is an objection to Definition 4 that is related to the Preface paradox. The Preface paradox, first introduced by Makinson (1965), asks us to consider an author of an academic book who, in the preface to her book, throws in a caveat to the reader about the errors that the book surely contains. At the same time, though, she is committed to each of the assertions in the book. Thus, on the one hand, she believes that each assertion made in the book, say a1, a2,…,an, is true but, at the same time, given the knowledge of her own fallibility, she also believes that the conjunction of all the assertions in the book is false; that is, a1a2 ∧… ∧ an is false and, hence, ¬(a1a2 ∧… ∧ an) is true. This can be represented in the following way (using ‘B’ for ‘the author believes that’):

  1. (i)

    Ba1, Ba2, …, Ban (that is because the author believes all her claims in the book to be true)

  2. (ii)

    B¬(a1a2 ∧… ∧ an) (that is because the author is aware of her own fallibility)

And if we accept the principle of agglomeration,

  1. (Agg)

    (Ba1Ba2) →B(a1a2)

then from (i) we can conclude B(a1a2 ∧… ∧ an). Hence, the author has inconsistent beliefs; in particular, if we suppose that B¬ϕ implies that ¬Bϕ we have a plain inconsistency: B(a1a2 ∧… ∧ an) ∧¬B(a1a2 ∧… ∧ an).

Consider now, keeping in mind the situation described above, the following argument:

Adjunction Argument

  1. 1.

    a1,…an

  2. 2.

    a1a2 ∧… ∧ an,

which seems to be a perfectly harmless argument. According to Definition 4, though, the instance of the Adjunction argument given by the situation described in the Preface paradox will be a paradox; because, in this situation, believing the premises does not commit us, under conditions of epistemic neutrality, to believe the conclusion—that is precisely what the Preface paradox shows; you can believe all the premises while you believe the negation of the conclusion. But even if a1, a2,…,an are the assertions in the author’s book, the resulting instance of the Adjunction Argument is not a paradox, the objector to Definition 4 would claim; it is just a harmless application of adjunction (the principle according to which ϕ,ψϕψ). What this would mean, then, is that Definition 4 is too broad; some arguments that are not paradoxes would be declared as paradoxes.Footnote 23

Notice, though, that the fact that the logical form of an argument seems innocuous does not mean that the argument is. Consider a soritical paradox like Argument 2 in Section 2; its paradoxical status did not depend on its logical form—which was shared by the trivial arithmetical Argument 1 in the same section—but on certain properties of the notions involved in the argument. The case is similar with respect to the instance of the Adjunction Argument where a1, a2,…,an are the assertions in the author’s book. In this case, the argument is a paradox, even if its logical form can be instantiated by perfectly sound arguments. Its paradoxical status, though, stems from certain properties of the sentences in the argument, not from its logical form.

The third question I wish to address is the following objection to Definition 4. Given the challenges that have been presented against the normative status of logic,Footnote 24 it might seem problematic to characterize the notion of paradox in terms of this very same status.Footnote 25 To my mind, two responses can be given to this objection. First, note that Definition 4 does not need logic to be normative in order for it to work, but it is enough that logic is apparently normative, which is a far weaker claim and a much more plausible one.Footnote 26 If logic is apparently normative, we still remain stuck when we are in front of a paradox, for we still have the two conflicting intuitions regarding the commitments that stem from the paradoxical argument: apparently there is no commitment (for the reasons discussed in Section 4) and, apparently, there is (for the apparent normativity of logic). This leaves another possibility open, one that stems from Definition 4 (which did not stem from Definition 1, and hence can be seen as an advantage of the former), and which leads to the second response to the objection: we might interpret pathodoxes like the Curry argument where Curry’s sentence is build using ‘snow is white’ as perfectly sound arguments that do not generate the kind of commitment expected from the point of view of the normativity of logic, so that pathodoxes like these ones would constitute counterexamples to the normativity of logic. In short, Definition 4 can be understood as characterizing the notion of paradox, not in terms of the normative character of logic, but in terms of the apparent normative character of logic (which is far less problematic) and, this, in turn, opens a new possible response to the paradoxes: denying that the fact that the paradoxical argument is valid implies that believing its premisses and accepting its validity commits one to its conclusion; to wit, denying the normative status of logic.

One last remark: I think Definition 4 captures well other paradoxes in the field of Philosophy of logic like, for example, the Liar paradox, the paradoxes of material implication or the paradoxes of strict implication, but it remains to see whether this definition can capture other so-called ‘paradoxes’ in other fields. I will leave this endeavour for future research.