Skip to main content
Log in

Does Non-Moral Ignorance Exculpate? Situational Awareness and Attributions of Blame and Forgiveness

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

In this paper, we set out to test empirically an idea that many philosophers find intuitive, namely that non-moral ignorance can exculpate. Many philosophers find it intuitive that moral agents are responsible only if they know the particular facts surrounding their action (or inaction). Our results show that whether moral agents are aware of the facts surrounding their (in)action does have an effect on people’s attributions of blame, regardless of the consequences or side effects of the agent’s actions. In general, it was more likely that a situationally aware agent will be blamed for failing to perform the obligatory action than a situationally unaware agent. We also tested attributions of forgiveness in addition to attributions of blame. In general, it was less likely that a situationally aware agent will be forgiven for failing to perform the obligatory action than a situationally unaware agent. When the agent is situationally unaware, it is more likely that the agent will be forgiven than blamed. We argue that these results provide some empirical support for the hypothesis that there is something intuitive about the idea that non-moral ignorance can exculpate.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. For an overview of the literature on the epistemic condition on moral responsibility, see Wieland (2017).

  2. On the method of cases, see Nagel (2012), Mizrahi (2014), and Baz (2016).

  3. According to Wieland (2017, p. 3), “As many say since Strawson (1962), S is morally blameworthy for X (whether it is an action, omission, consequence, etc.) iff on account of X, S is a proper candidate for the reactive attitudes, such as resentment, indignation, and condemnation.”

  4. Cf. Sher’s (2009, p. 143) “full epistemic condition,” which is also stated in terms of awareness and lack of awareness. For a discussion of the epistemic requirements for moral responsibility in the context of criminal law, see Oshana (2013).

  5. See also Fischer and Tognazzini (2009). Cf. Mele (2011).

  6. In addition to an epistemic condition, there may be other conditions for blameworthiness (and for moral responsibility in general, see, e.g., Cova 2017). For example, some have argued for the principle known as “Ought Implies Can” (OIC) on the grounds that to blame moral agents who are unable to do what they ought to do would be unfair. See Fischer (2003). Cf. Graham (2011). In this paper, we are interested in the epistemic dimension of moral responsibility, in particular, non-moral ignorance. Mizrahi (2009) and (2012).

  7. See, e.g., Haji (1997). On blameworthiness and control, see Brekke Carlsson (2017).

  8. Cf. Rosen (2004). See also Wieland (2015).

  9. For an overview of this literature, see Feltz (2007) and Cova (2016). For a critical discussion, see Nadelhoffer (2004) and Sauer (2014).

  10. For arguments against the so-called “tracing principle,” see Khoury (2012).

  11. According to Zaibert (2009, p. 388), the “standard view” is that “to forgive is, explicitly, to overcome resentment (even if this overcoming is done for a moral reason,” but Zaibert (2009, p. 368) argues that “to forgive is to deliberately refuse to punish.” Cf. Warmke (2011).

  12. See also Wieland (2015) for the contrast between moral ignorance and factual ignorance.

  13. In Luke 23:34, Jesus says “Father, forgive them; for they know not what they do.” Presumably, Jesus is talking about moral ignorance here; that is, they do not know that what they are doing is morally wrong, which is different from being ignorant of non-moral facts. For more on moral ignorance, see Guerrero (2007).

  14. We chose a gender-neutral name, like “Alex,” in an attempt to avoid as much as possible any gender-related influences on people’s judgments.

  15. Although demographics had no statistical effects, it is worth noting that our sample was extremely diverse, with participants (ages 18–65) claiming at least three different genders (624 men, 433 women, and 6 other), 17 different ethnic backgrounds, and 25 distinct religious affiliations.

  16. We chose not to dichotomize the data into two categories—agree/disagree or, for example, blame/do not blame—because we want to be able to test the strength of the agreement. Dichotomizing would mean we would not be able to discover if one receives strong blame and another is only somewhat blameworthy. We would only be able to say that blame was assigned in both cases. For more on the problems with dichotomization, see MacCallum et al. (2002).

  17. Likert-type items are single questions that still use the same layout as the questions within a full Likert scale. Individual items in a full Likert scale are then summed to form what is assumed to be a continuous variable. For more on the statistical difference between Likert-type items and full Likert scales, see Clason and Dormody (1994).

  18. It is common to test Likert-type data as if it is continuous. The commonality of this practice does not mean it is the appropriate test. For example, Likert-type data fails the assumptions for ANOVA testing, meaning the results from such a test may be wrong. For a detailed explanation of ART procedures, see Wobbrock et al. (2011). We performed the statistical analysis in R using the ARTool package provided by Wobbrock et al. An overview of the tool and package can be accessed at https://depts.washington.edu/aimgroup/proj/art/.

  19. The null hypothesis for these tests is that “true location shift is equal to 0” for two between-subjects groups.

  20. It is important to note here that the agent is not morally ignorant; i.e., the agent is not ignorant of moral facts. Rather, the agent is situationally ignorant, i.e., ignorant of the non-moral facts surrounding his/her (in)action, in particular, that that a person using crutches just boarded the train and there are no available seats. On moral ignorance, see Guerrero (2007).

  21. See footnotes 13 and 20.

  22. See Buckwalter and Turri (2015), Mizrahi (2015a), (2015b), Chituc et al. (2016), and Henne et al. (2016).

  23. For more on this sort of “positive” program or, more precisely, experimental philosophy as cognitive science, see Knobe (2016).

  24. Strawson (1962) does include forgiveness in his list of “reactive attitudes,” which also includes resentment, indignation, anger, and gratitude. As mentioned above, however, philosophers of moral responsibility have focused mostly on praise and blame. See, e.g., Macnamara (2011).

  25. See Martin and Cushman (2016) for an experimental test of the hypothesis that we forgive unintentional actions because “we do not believe the agent is even causally responsible for them” (Martin and Cushman 2016, p. 134). Recall that our experimental study is not about intentional (or unintentional) actions but rather about situational awareness (or lack of situational awareness) and attributions of blame as well as forgiveness.

  26. As another anonymous reviewer helpfully pointed out, a possible symmetry between blameworthiness and being worthy of forgiveness might be taken as a platitude that any account of forgiveness must be able to accommodate. However, we think that it would be useful to have empirical evidence, even for something that is considered a platitude, when possible.

References

  • Agule, C. K. (2016). Resisting tracing’s siren song. Journal of Ethics & Social Philosophy, 10(1), 1–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Allais, L. (2008). Wiping the slate clean: the heart of forgiveness. Philosophy and Public Affairs, 36(1), 33–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baz, A. (2016). Recent attempts to defend the philosophical method of cases and the linguistic turn. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 92(1), 105–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benchimol, J. (2011). The moral significance of unintentional omission: comparing will-centered and non-will-centered accounts of moral responsibility. In N. A. Vincent, I. van de Poel, & J. van den Hoven (Eds.), Moral responsibility: beyond free will and determinism (pp. 101–120). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brekke Carlsson, A. (2017). Blameworthiness as deserved guilt. The Journal of Ethics, 21(1), 89–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brogaard, B. (2014). Intuitions as intellectual Seemings. Analytic Philosophy, 55(4), 382–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Buckwalter, W., & Turri, J. (2015). Inability and obligation in moral judgment. PLoS One, 10(8), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chituc, V., Henne, P., Sinnott-Armstrong, W., & De Brigard, F. (2016). Blame, not ability, impacts moral “ought” judgments for impossible actions: toward an empirical refutation of “ought” implies “can”. Cognition, 150, 20–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, R. (2012). What is an omission? Philosophical Issues, 22(1), 127–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clason, D., & Dormody, T. (1994). Analyzing data measured by individual Likert-type items. Journal of Agricultural Education, 35(4), 31–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cole, J., & Bengson, J. (2009). Asymmetries in judgments of responsibility and intentional action. Mind & Language, 24(1), 24–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cova, F. (2016). The folk concept of intentional action: empirical approaches. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 121–141). Malden: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cova, F. (2017). Frankfurt-style cases and the explanation condition for moral responsibility: a reply to Swenson. Acta Analytica. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-017-0316-5.

  • Cushman, F. (2008). Crime and punishment: distinguishing the roles of causal and intentional analyses in moral judgment. Cognition, 108(2), 353–380.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Faraci, D., & Shoemaker, D. (2014). Huck vs. Jojo: moral ignorance and the (a)symmetry of praise and blame. In J. Knobe, T. Lombrozo, & S. Nichols (Eds.), Oxford studies in experimental philosophy (pp. 7–27). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Feltz, A. (2007). The Knobe effect: a brief overview. Journal of Mind and Behavior, 28(3–4), 265–277.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. (2003). ‘Ought-implies-can’, causal determinism and moral responsibility. Analysis, 63(3), 244–250.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J. (2006). My way: essays on moral responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J., & Ravizza, M. (1998). Responsibility and control: a theory of moral responsibility. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, J., & Tognazzini, N. (2009). The truth about tracing. Nous, 43(3), 531–556.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gamlund, E. (2011). Forgiveness without blame. In C. Fricke (Ed.), The ethics of forgiveness: a collection of essays (pp. 107–129). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (2000). The epistemic requirements for moral responsibility. Nous, 34(14), 267–277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Graham, P. A. (2011). Fischer on blameworthiness and “ought” implies “can”. Social Theory and Practice, 37(1), 63–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guerrero, A. (2007). Don’t know, don’t kill: moral ignorance, culpability, and caution. Philosophical Studies, 136(1), 59–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haji, I. (1997). An epistemic dimension of blameworthiness. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 57(3), 523–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harman, E. (2011). Does moral ignorance exculpate? Ratio, 24(4), 443–468.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henne, P., Chituc, V., De Brigard, F., & Sinnott-Armstrong, W. (2016). An empirical refutation of ‘ought’ implies ‘can’. Analysis, 76(3), 283–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Holmgren, M. R. (2012). Forgiveness and retribution: responding to wrongdoing. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kekes, J. (2009). Blame versus forgiveness. The Monist, 92(4), 488–506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Khoury, A. C. (2012). Responsibility, tracing, and consequences. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 42(3), 187–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003a). Intentional action in folk psychology: an experimental investigation. Philosophical Psychology, 16(2), 309–325.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2003b). Intentional action and side effects in ordinary language. Analysis, 63(3), 190–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2004a). Intention, intentional action and moral considerations. Analysis, 64(2), 181–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2004b). Folk psychology and folk morality: response to critics. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 24(2), 270–279.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Knobe, J. (2016). Experimental philosophy is cognitive science. In J. Sytsma & W. Buckwalter (Eds.), A companion to experimental philosophy (pp. 37–52). Malden: Wiley Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagnado, D. A., & Channon, S. (2008). Judgments of cause and blame: the effects of intentionality and foreseeability. Cognition, 108(3), 754–770.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacCallum, R. C., Zhang, S., Preacher, K. J., & Rucker, D. (2002). On the practice of dichotomization of quantitative variables. Psychological Methods, 7(1), 19–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Macnamara, C. (2011). Holding others responsible. Philosophical Studies, 152(1), 81–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, J. W., & Cushman, F. (2016). Why we forgive what can’t be controlled? Cognition, 147, 133–143.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mason, E. (2015). Moral ignorance and blameworthiness. Philosophical Studies, 172(11), 3037–3057.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. (2011). Moral responsibility for actions: epistemic and freedom conditions. Philosophical Explorations, 13(2), 101–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mizrahi, M. (2009). ‘Ought’ Does Not Imply ‘Can’. Philosophical Frontiers, 4(1), 19–35.

  • Mizrahi, M. (2012). Does ‘Ought’ Imply ‘Can’ from an Epistemic Point of View? Philosophia 40(4), 829–840.

  • Mizrahi, M. (2014) Does the Method of Cases Rest on a Mistake? Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(2), 183–197.

  • Mizrahi, M. (2015a). Ought, can, and presupposition: an experimental study. Methode: Analytic Perspectives, 4(6), 232–243.

  • Mizrahi, M. (2015b). Ought, can, and presupposition: A Reply to Kurthy and Lawford-Smith. Methode: Analytic Perspectives, 4(6), 250–256.

  • Montminy, M. (2016). Doing one’s reasonable best: what moral responsibility requires. Journal of the American Philosophical Association, 2(1), 55–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Moody-Adams, M. (2015). The enigma of forgiveness. Journal of Value Inquiry, 49(1), 161–180.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nadelhoffer, T. (2004). On praise, side-effects, and folk ascriptions of intentionality. Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical Psychology, 24(2), 196–213.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, J. (2012). Intuitions and experiments: a defense of the case method in epistemology. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 85(3), 495–527.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Open Science Collaboration. (2015). Estimating the reproducibility of psychological science. Science, 349(6251). https://doi.org/10.1126/science.aac4716.

  • Oshana, M. (2013). Second hand (moral) responsibility in law. In I. Haji & J. Caouette (Eds.), Free will and moral responsibility (pp. 229–248). Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raju, M. & Cohen, M. (2017). Dems to Mueller: Flynn failed to disclose trip to broker Saudi-Russian business deal.” CNN Politics. http://www.cnn.com/2017/09/13/politics/democrats-mueller-flynn-middle-east-trip-disclosure/index.html. Accessed 13 Sept 2017.

  • Rosen, G. (2004). Scepticism about moral responsibility. Philosophical Perspectives, 18(1), 295–313.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. (2008). Kleinbart the oblivious and other tales of ignorance and responsibility. The Journal of Philosophy, 105(10), 591–610.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sauer, H. (2014). It’s the Knobe effect, stupid. Review of Philosophy and Psychology, 5(4), 485–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sher, G. (2009). Who knew? Responsibility without awareness. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1962). Freedom and resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy, 48, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sytsma, J., & Livengood, J. (2016). The theory and practice of experimental philosophy. Tonawanda: Broadview.

    Google Scholar 

  • Talbot, B. (2014). Why so negative? Evidence aggregation and armchair philosophy. Synthese, 191(16), 3865–3896.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tognazzini, N. A. (2010). Review of George Sher, Who Knew? Responsibility without Awareness. Notre Dame Philosophical Review (January 3, 2010): http://ndpr.nd.edu/news/24254-who-knew-responsibility-without-awareness/.

  • Warmke, B. (2011). Is forgiveness the deliberate refusal to punish? Journal of Moral Philosophy, 8(4), 613–620.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Warmke, & McKenna. (2013). Moral responsibility, forgiveness and conversation. In I. Haji & J. Caouette (Eds.), Free will and moral responsibility (pp. 189–212). Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wieland, J. W. (2015). What’s special about moral ignorance? Ratio, 30(2), 149–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wieland, J. W. (2017). The epistemic condition. In P. Robichaud & J. W. Wieland (Eds.), Responsibility—the epistemic condition (pp. 1–28). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Wobbrock, J.O., Findlater, L., Gergle, D. and Higgins, J.J. (2011). The Aligned Rank Transform for nonparametric factorial analyses using only ANOVA procedures. Proceedings of the ACM Conference on Human Factors in Computing Systems (pp. 143–146). New York: ACM.

  • Zaibert, L. (2009). The paradox of forgiveness. Journal of Moral Philosophy, 6(3), 365–393.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We are grateful to the two anonymous reviewers of Acta Analytica for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Moti Mizrahi.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Kissinger-Knox, A., Aragon, P. & Mizrahi, M. Does Non-Moral Ignorance Exculpate? Situational Awareness and Attributions of Blame and Forgiveness. Acta Anal 33, 161–179 (2018). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-017-0339-y

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-017-0339-y

Keywords

Navigation