Skip to main content
Log in

A Brief Remark on Non-prioritized Belief Change and the Monotony Postulate

  • Published:
Acta Analytica Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

The AGM success postulates for belief expansions and revisions have been widely criticized. This has resulted in the development of a number of non-prioritized belief change theories that violate these postulates. It is shown that we must also discard the monotony postulate for belief expansions if we abandon the success postulates. Non-prioritized belief change theories should instead fulfill a weaker postulate, which we call Conditional Monotony.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Although the original paper by Alchourrón et al. (1985) is quite clear, the presentation in Gärdenfors (1988) is even more accessible.

  2. In this paper, I use the term “information” to denote any propositional input that is offered to the epistemic subject regardless of whether the subject decides to incorporate it or not. In contrast to that, any previously received information that has actually been incorporated is called a “belief” of the subject. The difference between these two terms was obscured in an earlier draft of this paper. I thank an anonymous reviewer for drawing my attention to this point as well as for some other helpful comments.

  3. A case in point is, for instance, Hansson’s (1999) revision procedure that involves two steps: (1) A non-closing expansion by the new information and (2) consolidation to reestablish consistency. Although this procedure prevents inconsistent new information from being incorporated in some cases, Hansson’s procedure still satisfies the success postulate for consistent new information. Cf. Sec. 3.12.

  4. See Hansson (1999, p. 238).

  5. The success postulate for expansions is sometimes also referred to as Weak Success. Cf., e.g., Fermé and Hansson (1999) and (Hansson (1997a).

  6. I have adapted this example for the present context from BonJour (1985).

References

  • Alchourrón, C. E., Gärdenfors, P., & Makinson, D. (1985). On the logic of theory change: partial meet contraction and revision functions. Journal of Symbolic Logic, 50, 510–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge: Mass.: Harvard Univ. Pr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brewka, G. (1991). Belief revision in a framework for default reasoning. In A. Fuhrmann & M. Morreau (Eds.), Proceedings of the workshop: the logic of theory change (pp. 206–222). Konstanz: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cross, C. B., & Thomason, R. H. (1992). Conditionals and knowledge-base update. In P. Gärdenfors (Ed.), Belief revision (pp. 247–275). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Dalal, M. (1988). Investigations into a theory of knowledge base revision: preliminary report. In T. M. Mitchell & R. G. Smith (Eds.), Proceedings of the Seventh National Conference on Artificial Intelligence (AAAI-88) (pp. 475–479). St. Paul: AAAI Pr.

  • Falappa, M. A., Kern-Isberner, G., Reis, M. D. L., & Simari, G. R. (2012). Prioritized and non-prioritized multiple change on belief bases. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 41, 77–113.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fermé, E. L., & Hansson, S. O. (1999). Selective revision. Studia Logica, 63(3), 331–342.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gallier, J. R. (1992). Autonomous belief revision and communication. In P. Gärdenfors (Ed.), Belief revision (pp. 220–246). Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gärdenfors, P. (1988). Knowledge in flux: modeling the dynamics of epistemic states. Cambridge: Mass.: MIT Pr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haas, G. (1999). Überzeugungen, Revision und Rechtfertigung. In J. Mittelstraß (Ed.), Proceedings of the Deutscher Kongreß für Philosophie XVIII: Die Zukunft des Wissens (pp. 45–50). Konstanz: Konstanz Univ. Pr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haas, G. (2005). Revision und Rechtfertigung: Eine Theorie der Theorieänderung. Heidelberg: Synchron.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1997a). Semi-revision. Journal of Applied Non-Classical Logic, 7(1–2), 151–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1997b). Special issue on non-prioritized belief revision. Theoria, 63(1–2), 1–134.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hansson, S. O. (1999). A textbook of belief dynamics: theory change and database updating. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1991). The fixation of belief and its undoing. Cambridge: Cambridge Univ. Pr.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gordian Haas.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Haas, G. A Brief Remark on Non-prioritized Belief Change and the Monotony Postulate. Acta Anal 31, 319–322 (2016). https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-015-0281-9

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s12136-015-0281-9

Keywords

Navigation